Skip to main content

Learning, Social Intelligence and the Turing Test

Why an “Out-of-the-Box” Turing Machine Will Not Pass the Turing Test

  • Conference paper
How the World Computes (CiE 2012)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 7318))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

The Turing Test checks for human intelligence, rather than any putative general intelligence. It involves repeated interaction requiring learning in the form of adaption to the human conversation partner. It is a macro-level post-hoc test in contrast to the definition of a Turing machine, which is a prior micro-level definition. This raises the question of whether learning is just another computational process, i.e., can be implemented as a Turing machine. Here we argue that learning or adaption is fundamentally different from computation, though it does involve processes that can be seen as computations. To illustrate this difference we compare (a) designing a Turing machine and (b) learning a Turing machine, defining them for the purpose of the argument. We show that there is a well-defined sequence of problems which are not effectively designable but are learnable, in the form of the bounded halting problem. Some characteristics of human intelligence are reviewed including it’s: interactive nature, learning abilities, imitative tendencies, linguistic ability and context-dependency. A story that explains some of these is the Social Intelligence Hypothesis. If this is broadly correct, this points to the necessity of a considerable period of acculturation (social learning in context) if an artificial intelligence is to pass the Turing Test. Whilst it is always possible to ‘compile’ the results of learning into a Turing machine, this would not be a designed Turing machine and would not be able to continually adapt (pass future Turing Tests). We conclude three things, namely that: a purely “designed” Turing machine will never pass the Turing Test; that there is no such thing as a general intelligence since it necessarily involves learning; and that learning/adaption and computation should be clearly distinguished.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Beer, R.D.: Intelligence as adaptive behavior: an experiment in computational neuroethology. Academic Press (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ben-Jacob, E., Becker, I., Shapira, Y., Levine, H.: Bacterial linguistic communication and social intelligence. Trends in Microbiology 12(8), 366–372 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Byrne, Whiten, A.: Machiavellian intelligence. Oxford University Press (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Copeland, B.J.: The Modern History of Computing. In: Edward, N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall 2008 edn.) (2008), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/computing-history

  5. Cutland, N.: Computability, an introduction to recursive function theory. Cambridge University Press (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Tomasello, M.: The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  7. De Waal, F.: Chimpanzee politics: power and sex among apes. John Hopkins University Press (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Edmonds, B.: The constructability of artificial intelligence (as defined by the Turing Test). Journal of Logic Language and Information 9, 419–424 (2000)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Edmonds, B.: The social embedding of intelligence: how to build a machine that could pass the Turing Test. In: Epstein, R., Roberts, G., Beber, G. (eds.) Parsing the Turing Test, pp. 211–235. Springer (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  10. French, R.M.: Subcognition and the limits of the Turing Test. Mind 99, 53–64 (1989)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Garnier, S., Gautrais, J., Theraulaz, G.: The biological principles of swarm intelligence. Swarm Intelligence 1(1), 3–31 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Gershenson, C.: Cognitive paradigms: Which one is the best? Cognitive Systems Research 5(2), 135–156 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Gershenson, C.: Computing Networks: A General Framework to Contrast Neural and Swarm Cognitions, Paladyn. Journal of Behavioral Robotics 1(2), 147–153 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gershenson, C.: The implications of interactions for science and philosophy. Technical Report, 04, C3, UNAM, Mexico (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Guimond, S., et al.: Social comparison, self-stereotyping, and gender differences in self-construals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 90(2), 221–242 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Glymour, C.: Learning, prediction and causal Bayes nets. Trends in Cognitive Sciences (1), 43–48 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Humphrey, N.K.: The social function of the intellect. In: Bateson, P.P.G., Hinde, R.A. (eds.) Growing Points in Ethology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kirshner, H.S.: Approaches to intellectual and memory impairments. In: Gradley, W.G., et al. (eds.) Neurology in Clinical Practice, 5th edn., ch. 6, Butterworth-Heinemann (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Kummer, H., Daston, L., Gigerenzer, G., Silk, J.: The social intelligence hypothesis. In: Weingart, et al. (ed.) Human by Nature: Between Biology and the Social Sciences, pp. 157–179. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lane, H.: The Wild Boy of Aveyron. Harvard University Press (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Marr, D.: Vision: A Computational Approach. Freeman & Co., San Francisco (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Reader, J.: Man on Earth. Penguin Books (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Trewavas, A.: Aspects of plant intelligence. Annals of Botany 92(1), 1–20 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Turing, A.M.: On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proc. of the London Mathematical Society 2 42, 230–265 (1936)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Turing, A.M.: Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind 59, 433–460 (1950)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Turkle, S.: The second self: computers and the human spirit. Simon and Schuster (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  27. van Rooij, I.: Tractable Cognition: Complexity Theory in Cognitive Psychology. PhD Thesis, Katholieke Universiteit Nijmegen, Netherlands (1998), http://www.nici.ru.nl/~irisvr/PhDthesis.pdf

  28. Wolpert, D.H.: The lack of a priori distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation 8(7), 1341–1390 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this paper

Cite this paper

Edmonds, B., Gershenson, C. (2012). Learning, Social Intelligence and the Turing Test. In: Cooper, S.B., Dawar, A., Löwe, B. (eds) How the World Computes. CiE 2012. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 7318. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-30870-3_18

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-30870-3_18

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-30869-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-30870-3

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics