Skip to main content

The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Paradox, Bell’s Theorem and Nonlocality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Bell's Theorem and Quantum Realism

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Physics ((SpringerBriefs in Physics))

  • 1325 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter we turn to the paradox of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen, and Bell’s Theorem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The account presented here follows similar lines as that of J.S. Bell and many other authors. See Bell in [2, 3]. Others authors who concur include Dürr, Goldstein, Zanghí (Sect. 8) in [4], Maudlin in [5, 6], Norsen [79] and Wiseman [10].

  2. 2.

    See [1216].

  3. 3.

    See [17].

  4. 4.

    To be precise, Bell worked directly with the David Bohm’s spin-singlet version of Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen [18], pp. 611–623. A recent reprint appears within [19], pp. 356–368.

  5. 5.

    See footnote 1 above. Not all authors agree with this position. Some reject quantum nonlocality. See Jarrett [20] and also Evans, Price and Wharton in [21]. Others argue that the theorem constitutes a proof that realism is impossible in quantum physics. See Bethe [22], Gell-Mann [23], p. 172, and Wigner [19], p. 291.

  6. 6.

    In particular, one cannot take the conclusion of the EPR paradox—the existence of noncontextual hidden variables—as received and final. This conclusion is based not only on quantum mechanical predictions, but also on the assumption of locality, which will ultimately be seen to fail. The status of EPR becomes clearer when one recognizes that the analysis is in fact equivalent to a theorem, as we demonstrate in Sect. 3.2.3.

  7. 7.

    The Bohm spin singlet version and the original version of the EPR paradox differ essentially in the states and observables with which they are concerned. We shall consider the original EPR state more explicitly in Sect. 4.2.1.

  8. 8.

    See for example, Messiah [24], and Shankar [25].

  9. 9.

    Note that a term such as \(|a\rangle^{(1)}|b\rangle^{(2)}\) represents a tensor product of the vector \(|a\rangle^{(1)}\) of the Hilbert space associated with the first particle with the vector \(|b\rangle^{(2)}\) of the Hilbert space associated with the second. The formal way of writing such a quantity is as: \(|a\rangle^{(1)}\otimes |b\rangle^{(2)}.\) For simplicity of expression, we shall omit the symbol ‘\(\otimes\)’ here.

  10. 10.

    If we multiply a wave function by any constant factor c, where \(c \neq 0\) the resulting wave function represents the same physical state. We multiply \(\psi_{ss}\) by \(-1\) to facilitate comparison with (3.2).

  11. 11.

    Already we see a contrast with the point of view of quantum theory, which asserts that no physical property has meaning apart from a measurement procedure. One could at this point assert that the incompleteness of quantum mechanics has been established. It is interesting to note in this connection that Einstein [26, pp. 167–168] disliked that Podolsky and Rosen had formulated incompleteness by reference to both x and p when just one quantity would suffice.

  12. 12.

    A few things may need to be clarified. First, no dependence on \(\psi\) need be included in this formulation since we are considering a fixed wave-function, namely that of the spin-singlet state. Second, writing such a mathematical function does not in any sense constitute an additional assumption. The existence of particular values which match measurement results perfectly assures that a value map of just this form must exist.

  13. 13.

    Readers may object that on the relevant spin space each component of the spin-\(\frac{1} {2}\) observable is non-degenerate, so that the considerations of measurement procedure play very little role. However, an observable need not be a member of a commuting family in order for a choice of measurement procedures to come into play. Even a spin-\(\frac{1} {2}\) particle exhibits contextuality and dependence of measurement result upon the choice of experimental procedure. See Sect. 2.5.

  14. 14.

    Among the set \(\{\sigma^{(1)}_{\theta,\,\phi}\}\) it is of course, trivial to locate a pair of incompatible observables, e.g., \(\sigma^{(1)}_{x}\) and \(\sigma^{(1)}_{y}.\)

  15. 15.

    Once again, we emphasize that this conclusion ought not be taken as the final word on the spin singlet state. It follows only if one admits the assumption of locality, which axiom is to meet its doom, once we are aware of Bell’s Theorem and its implications. The death of locality is to to discussed in the final section of the chapter.

  16. 16.

    As everyone knows, a paradox is a self-contradiction. However, this name is not descriptive of what the analysis offers. In the situation analyzed by EPR, it happens that the conclusion runs counter to quantum mechanics. Here, quantum mechanics is essentially being used to point the road to its own limitations.

  17. 17.

    We will use the term “the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Theorem” in this section, in spite of the fact that it is not a term which appears in the literature. We do so for ease of discussion, to avoid using cumbersome phrases such as “the theorem implied by the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox.” The proof that the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox is equivalent to a theorem is presented in Sect. 3.2.3.

  18. 18.

    The latter is due to the fact that what previously served as a premise of Bell—the existence of non-contextual hidden variables—turns out to be a nonbasic premise within the complex argument.

  19. 19.

    The large majority of experiments have dealt with a two-photon system, rather than two spins. See for example, Freedman and Clauser [27], Fry and Thompson [28], and Aspect et al. [2931]. For such quantum systems, the most definitive theoretical analysis was given by Clauser, Horne, Holt and Shimony [32]. Here the photon polarizations play the role of the spin components. The experiment of Lamehi-Rachti, and Mittig [33] involves a pair of protons described by the spin singlet state. For a discussion of quantum nonlocality experiments, see Bell in [2, 34] and Herbert in [35].

  20. 20.

    Bell briefly confronts the concept in [36], p. 47. He discusses the interpretation that “the world is superdeterministic.” In another work, [37, 38] Bell treats the same concept in a somewhat more mathematical and detailed manner. See also Goldstein, Norsen, Tausk, Zanghi in [39], specifically their reference to the ‘no-conspiracies’ assumption. We find the Bell term ‘superdeterminism’ more conducive to the expostulation of the principle involved.

  21. 21.

    See for example, G.C. Ghirardi [40], pp. 243–246.

  22. 22.

    Note that the means of such disturbance requires an inventive imagination. It seems rather odd to suppose that a signal might pass from the spin-measuring apparatus on one side of the lab to the particle on the other. However, since the question at issue is one that “shakes the foundations” of physical science, it might be reasonable to account for even such unknown and unusual hypotheses.

  23. 23.

    In a hidden variables context, this would mean that the quantum system has “preprogrammed answers” for the measurements which will be made by the two scientists. But Bell’s theorem is derived based upon a continuously infinite set of hidden variables, and it is not clear whether or how Bell’s conclusion—empirical disagreement between the different styles of theories—can be developed from a small and finite set.

  24. 24.

    Or perhaps we could call it “pseudo-choice” if we take seriously the position of superdeterminism.

  25. 25.

    To follow the example offered by Bell [33, 34].

  26. 26.

    Although there are some obvious restrictions set down by social norms and by biological limitations.

  27. 27.

    Indeed, such a “martial law” precisely fixing human actions in lockstep with quantum states invokes a scenario as bizarre as any science fiction. Does this not remove the meaning most people ascribe to all human activities not just scientific, but intellectual, cultural and even social?

  28. 28.

    See [2, 3] Also see Dürr, Goldstein, Zanghí (Sect. 8) in [4], Maudlin in [5, 6], Norsen [7] and Wiseman [10].

  29. 29.

    As noted above, there is another assumption behind the logic here, namely what we called the ‘no-superdeterminism’. However, this does not constitute a refutation of the argument, but only an explicit recognition of the same assumption that underlies all scientific research.

References

  1. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., Rosen, N.: Can quantum-Mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777 (1935). Reprinted in [19, p. 138]

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bell, J.S.: Atomic cascade photons and quantum mechanical non-locality. Comments At. Mol. Phys. 9, 121–126 (1980). Reprinted in [41, p. 782]

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bell, J.S.: Bertlemann’s socks and the nature of reality. Journal de Physique Colloque C2, suppl. au numero 3, Tome 42 1981, pp. C2 41–61 (1981). Reprinted in [42, p. 139]

    Google Scholar 

  4. Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., Zanghí, N.: Quantum equilibrium and the role of operators as observables in quantum theory. J. Stat. Phys. 116, 959–1055 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Maudlin, T.: Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity: Metaphysical Intimations of Modern Physics, 3rd edn. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Maudlin, T.: Space-time in the quantum world. In: Cushing, J., Fine, A., Goldstein, S., (eds.) Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: an Appraisal, pp. 285–307. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Norsen, T.: Against ‘realism’. Found. Phys. 37, 311–340 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Norsen, T.: Bell locality and the nonlocal character of nature. Found. Phys. Lett. 19(7), 633–655 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Norsen, T.: Local causality and completeness: Bell vs. Jarrett. Found. Phys. 39(3), 237 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Wiseman, H.M.: From Einstein’s theorem to Bell’s theorem: A history of quantum nonlocality. Contemp. Phys. 47, 79–88 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Bell, J.S.: On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1, 195–200 (1964). Reprinted in [42, p. 14] and in [19, p. 403]

    Google Scholar 

  12. Bell, J.S.: Six possible worlds of quantum mechanics. In: Proceedings of the Nobel Symposium 65: Possible Worlds in Arts and Sciences. Stockholm, August 11–15 (1986). Reprinted in [42, p. 181]

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bell, J.S.: On the impossible pilot wave. Found. Phys. 12, 989–999 (1982). Reprinted in [42, p. 159]

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bell, J.S.: Quantum mechanics for cosmologists. In: Isham, C., Penrose, R., Sciama, D. (eds.) Quantum Gravity, vol. 2, p. 611. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1981). Reprinted in [42, p 117]

    Google Scholar 

  15. Bell, J.S.: De Broglie-Bohm, delayed choice double slit experiment and density matrix. Int. J. Quantum Chem. Quantum Chemistry Symposium 14, 155–159 (1980). Reprinted in [42, p. 111]

    Google Scholar 

  16. Bell, J.S.: In: M. Flato et al. (eds) Quantum mechanics, determinism, causality, and particles. D. Reidel, Dordrecht-Holland, 11–17 (1976). Reprinted in [42, p. 93].

    Google Scholar 

  17. Bohm, D.: A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. Phys. Rev. 85, 166, 180 (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Bohm, D.: Quantum Theory. Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs (1951)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Wheeler, J.A., Zurek,W.H. (eds.): Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Jarrett, J.: On the physical significance of the locality conditions in the Bell arguments. Nous 18, 569–589 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Evans, P., Price, H., Wharton, K.B.: New slant on the EPR-Bell experiment. Physics. arXiv:1001.5057v3 [quant-ph].

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bethe, H.: My experience in teaching physics. Am. J. Phys. 61, 972 (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gell-Mann, M.: The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the Complex. W.H. Freeman, New York (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Messiah, A.: Quantum Mechanics, Volumes I and II. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam. English translation by G.M. Temmer published by John Wiley and Sons, New York, 1976 (1959)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Shankar, R.: Principles of Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edn. Plenum Press, New York (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Gilder, L.: The Age of Entanglement: When Quantum Physics Was Reborn. Alfred A. Knopf, New York (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Freedman, S.J., Clauser, J.F.: Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 28, 938 (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Fry, E.S., Thompson, R.C.: Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 37, 465 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Aspect, A., Grangier, P., Roger, G.: Experimental tests of realistic local theories via Bell’s theorem. Phys. Rev. Lett. 47, 460 (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Aspect, A., Grangier, P., Roger, G.: Experimental realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen gedankenexperiment: a new violation of Bell’s inequalities. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Aspect, A., Dalibard, J., Roger, G.: Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804 (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Clauser, J.F., Horne, M., Holt, R.A., Shimony, A.: Proposed Experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880 (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Lamehi-Rachti, M., Mittig, W.: Quantum mechanics and hidden variables: a test of Bell’s inequality by the measurement of the spin correlation in low-energy proton-proton scattering. Phys. Rev. D, 2543–2555 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Bell, J.S.: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen experiments. In: Proceedings on the Frontier Problems in High Energy Physics, Pisa, pp. 33–45 (1976). Reprinted in [41, p. 768]

    Google Scholar 

  35. Herbert, N.: Quantum Reality. Doubleday, New York (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Davies, P.C.W., Brown, J.R.: The Ghost in the Atom. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Bell, J.S.: Free variables and local causality. Epistemol. Lett. 15 (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  38. Bell, J.S.: Free variables and local causality. Dialectica 39, 103–106 (1985). This paper is also presented in [41, p. 778–781]

    Google Scholar 

  39. Goldstein, S., Norsen, T., Tausk, D., Zanghi, N.: “Bell’s Theorem” in Scholarpedia peer-reviewed online encyclopedia.www.scholarpedia.org/article/Bell_theorem

  40. Ghirardi, G.C.: Sneaking a Look at God’s Cards. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Bell, M., Gottfried, K., Veltman, M. (eds.): Quantum Mechanics High Energy Physics and Accelerators: Selected Papers of John S. Bell (with commentary). World Scientifc Publishing, Singapore (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Bell, J.S.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1987). Many of the works by Bell which are of concern to us may be found in this reference. See also [41] and [43]. The latter two are complete collections containing all of Bell’s papers on quantum foundations

    Google Scholar 

  43. Bell, M. Gottfried, K., Veltman, M. (eds.): John S. Bell on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. World Scientifc Publishing, Singapore (2001)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas L. Hemmick .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hemmick, D.L., Shakur, A.M. (2012). The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Paradox, Bell’s Theorem and Nonlocality. In: Bell's Theorem and Quantum Realism. SpringerBriefs in Physics. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-23468-2_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-23468-2_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-23467-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-23468-2

  • eBook Packages: Physics and AstronomyPhysics and Astronomy (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics