Skip to main content

Generalized Probability Measures and the Framework of Effects

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Probability in Physics

Part of the book series: The Frontiers Collection ((FRONTCOLL))

Abstract

This paper is dedicated to the memory of Itamar Pitowsky. It develops the idea that the generalized probability measures of quantum mechanics are the probabilities of “effects.” As explained below, effects are included among measurement outcomes but are not exhausted by them. They also differ in key respects from propositions which attribute dynamical properties to the systems that are probed by measurements. These differences are elaborated, and an interpretation of the implicit probability theory of quantum mechanics in terms of effects is outlined. A central feature of this interpretation is that it supports a form of realism that accommodates the no hidden variable theorem of Kochen and Specker, and it does so without appealing to any notion of contextuality.

This paper was intended for presentation to the December 2008 Jerusalem conference in Itamar’s honor; unfortunately, circumstances prevented me from attending the conference. The paper is a sequel to “Effects and propositions” [1], to which the reader is referred for a more complete list of references and the historical context of some of the views presented here. A very early version of this paper was given as a talk to Chris Fuchs’s Perimeter Institute seminar on the foundations of quantum mechanics in May of 2008. Many thanks to Chris for numerous discussions and comments on subsequent drafts. I am indebted to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada and to the Killam Foundation for support of my research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    These definitions are taken from Pitowsky [3].

  2. 2.

    This thesis has been advanced and defended by Itamar in Pitowsky [5, 6]. See also Fuchs [7] for a recent statement and defense from a different “Quantum Bayesian” perspective.

  3. 3.

    The possibility of running an argument like Kochen and Specker’s backwards is exploited by a theorem of Pitowsky [3] showing that given any two noncomeasurable propositions P x and P y represented by rays in H3, we can always find a finite set Γ of rays of H3 which contains the representatives of P x and P y and has an orthogonality structure that forces any generalized two-valued measure on Γ to assign them both 0. More generally, one can show that either the probability of any two noncomeasurable P x and P y is 0, or at least one of them has a probability strictly between 0 and 1.

  4. 4.

    See Camilleri [10] for discussions of the views of Heisenberg, Bohr and Pauli and the similarities and divergences among them. Fuchs’s Quantum Bayesian approach to the theory preserves the primacy of the observer that was emphasized by Pauli. Observers in Fuchs’s framework are called “agents.” In conformity with Fuchs’s understanding of the purely epistemic character of the quantum state, effects belong to agents and consist in modifications of their subjective probability judgements.

  5. 5.

    Petersen [11]. Thanks to Hilary Putnam for bringing this remark to my attention.

  6. 6.

    The definition given in square brackets is from Vaidman [12, p. 133]. The italics are Vaidman’s and are intended to emphasize that the definition depends on the atemporal notion of inferring rather than the temporally directed notion of predicting. The three box paradox goes back at least as far as [13]. It is discussed in several other of Vaidman’s papers. See for example Vaidman [14] for a more elaborate discussion and for an explicit statement of the principle which underlies this reasoning, namely, the Aharonov-Bergmann-Lebowitz rule for calculating probabilities for the results of an intermediate measurement performed on a pre- and post-selected system.

References

  1. Demopoulos, W.: Effects and propositions. Found. Phys. 40, 368–389 (2010)

    Article  MATH  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Gleason, A.M.: Measures on the closed subspaces of Hilbert space. J. Math. Mech. 6, 885–893 (1957)

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. Pitowsky, I.: Infinite and finite Gleason’s theorem and the logic of indeterminacy. J. Math. Phys. 39, 218–228 (1998)

    Article  MATH  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Kochen, S., Specker, E.P.: The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 17, 59–87 (1967)

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Pitowsky, I.: Betting on the outcomes of measurements: a Bayesian theory of quantum probability. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 34, 395–414 (2003)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Pitowsky, I.: Quantum mechanics as a theory of probability. In: Demopoulos, W., Pitowsky, I. (eds.) Physical Theory and Its Interpretation: Essays in Honor of Jeffrey Bub, pp. 213–240. Springer, Dordrecht (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Fuchs, C.A.: QBism, the perimeter of quantum Bayesianism. arXiv:1003.5209v1 [quant-ph] 26 Mar 2010 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Stevens, K.W.H.: The spin-Hamiltonian and line widths in nickel Tutton salts. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A Math. Phys. Sci. 214, 237–246 (1952)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  9. Bell, J.S.: On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics 1, 195–200 (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Camilleri, K.: Heisenberg and the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: The Physicist as Philosopher. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2009)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Petersen, A.: The philosophy of Niels Bohr. Bull. At. Sci. 19(7), 8–14 (1963)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Vaidman, L.: Counterfactuals in quantum mechanics. In D. Greenberger et al. (eds) Compendium of Quantum Physics: Concepts, Experiments, History and Philosophy. Springer-Verlag, pp. 132–136. Berlin and Heidelberg (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Aharonov, Y., Vaidman, L.: Properties of a quantum system during the time interval between two measurements. Phys. Rev. A 41, 11–20 (1990)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Vaidman. L.: Lorentz-invariant “elements of reality” and the joint measurability of commuting observables. Phys. Rev. Lett. 70, 3369–3372 (1993)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Demopoulos .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Itamar on Locality as a Special Case of Non-contextuality

Appendix: Itamar on Locality as a Special Case of Non-contextuality

This paper was close to its final form when I sent it to Itamar for his reaction to it. I had intended to incorporate a suggestion of his into the paper before submitting the final version for publication. With his death, it occurred to me to simply quote from an e-mail in which he commented at some length on the paper. I think the e-mail conveys some of the remarkable mix of warmth and generosity—greatness of soul—that were characteristic of him and that were so highly valued by his friends.

The context of Itamar’s letter is my discussion of contextuality and locality which begins on p. 207. Toward the conclusion of this discussion (beginning on p. 208) I give an argument, based on Kochen and Specker’s proof of their principal theorem, for why effects rather than propositions should be understood as the proper subject of the probability assignments of quantum mechanics. Itamar’s letter supplements this argument with another which he traces to a thought experiment of Vaidman. Our two arguments are linked by the connection Itamar draws between what I call “propositions belonging to particles” and EPR’s elements of reality. Itamar and I argue that both notions should be rejected in favor of effects.

I am very much indebted to Jeffrey Bub for an extended e-mail correspondence which led to the clarification of Itamar’s argument and to the suggestion that Vaidman [12] is a plausible choice for the paper of Vaidman’s that Itamar had in mind. What we think is the relevant passage from Vaidman is quoted after Itamar’s letter. In quoting from Itamar’s letter, I have made some very minor stylistic changes which I’ve left invisible. More significant changes which correct or slightly elaborate Itamar’s remarks are enclosed in square brackets.

From Itamar, September 28, 2009:

…Back to your paper and to the discussion of locality as a special case of [non-]contextuality, I think that’s exactly right and it brings into focus the question about the relation between EPR’s “elements of reality” and the concepts of proposition and effect. As you recall, something is an element of reality if its existence can be predicted with certainty. The EPR argument is built upon assigning elements of reality, by this criterion, to properties whose existence is never actually measured. They never leave a trace, and that’s where they fail. I think that EPR’s criterion is at best necessary but insufficient, and proper elements of reality should also be required to leave a trace that can in principle be retrodicted, at least for a short time after the effect (in fact according to quantum mechanics if there is an effect the wave function changes, while unmeasured “elements” don’t change the wave-function). So EPR’s mistake is like what you describe for the Kochen-Specker case of assigning truth values to propositions, in particular the value “true” to a contradiction. GHZ’s (or Mermin’s) version of EPR shows that the two arguments, Kochen-Specker and Bell’s, are the same in this respect. The lesson of EPR is not about locality but about how their criterion of reality is insufficient.

There is a paper by Vaidman who shows the shortcomings in the EPR criterion (although Vaidman does not see it that way and does not use the result for this purpose). He creates a simple thought experiment with a system that has no locality issues (no tensor products), and considers a measurement on the system at t 1 and a subsequent measurement (of some other observable) at t 2. Now he considers a hypothetical measurement of property A at a t between t 1 and t 2 and asks: If we measured A at t, would we have discovered that the system had property A? By construction the results of the [measurements at t 1 and t 2] force the answer YES with certainty. However if we use [the measurement at t 1 and] the later measurement at t 2 and ask the same question about a hypothetical measurement [of B at the earlier time t, the answer is also YES with certainty. But A and B are contrary propositions, and therefore cannot be true together. Hence the answer to whether A is true] is NO with probability one. So the property A cannot be assigned a truth value that will be consistent across time.

From (Vaidman [12], pp. 134–135):

A peculiar example of time symmetric counterfactuals is the three box paradox […]. Consider a single particle prepared at time t 1 in a superposition of being in three separate boxes:

$$ |{\Psi_1}\rangle = {1}/\surd {3 }(|{\hbox{A}}\rangle + |{\hbox{B}}\rangle + |{\hbox{C}}\rangle ). $$

At a later time t 2 the particle is found in another superposition:

$$ |{\Psi_2}\rangle = {1}/\surd {2 }(|{\hbox{A}}\rangle + |{\hbox{B}}\rangle - |{\hbox{C}}\rangle ). $$

For this particle, a set of counterfactual statements, which are elements of reality according to the … definition,

[If we can infer with certainty that the result of measuring at time t of an observable O is o, then, at time t, there exists an element of reality O = o,]

is:

$$ {{\hbox{P}}_{\rm{A}}} = {1}, $$
$$ {{\hbox{P}}_{\rm{B}}} = {1}. $$

Or, in words: if we open box A, we find the particle there for sure; if we open box B (instead), we also find the particle there for sure.Footnote 6

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Demopoulos, W. (2012). Generalized Probability Measures and the Framework of Effects. In: Ben-Menahem, Y., Hemmo, M. (eds) Probability in Physics. The Frontiers Collection. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-21329-8_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-21329-8_13

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-21328-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-21329-8

  • eBook Packages: Physics and AstronomyPhysics and Astronomy (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics