Skip to main content

The Ethical Treatment of Animals: The Moral Significance of Darwin’s Theory

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Evolution 2.0

Part of the book series: The Frontiers Collection ((FRONTCOLL))

Abstract

Although Darwin’s theory is not a moral theory, it is not morally insignificant. In this paper, I consider one area of ethics in which Darwin’s theory has a real impact: the ethical treatment of animals. Peter Singer characterises speciesism as the discrimination between different animals (favouring humans) solely on the grounds of species membership (rather than morally relevant considerations such as sentience and self-awareness). In response, a number of Singer’s opponents have embraced speciesism. Carl Cohen, for example, states “I am a speciesist. Speciesism is not merely plausible, it is essential for right conduct.” In this paper, I argue that a proper understanding of evolution poses serious problems for those who want to oppose Singer in this way. Moral status is transitive and sortal: if A has the same moral status as B and B has the same moral status as C, then A and C must also have the same moral status. But species membership is (on standard definitions) non-transitive. Dawkins states that “Non-interbreeding is the recognised criterion for whether two populations deserve distinct species names.” According to this (and most other definitions of “species”) if A is the same species as B and B is the same species as C, it is not the case that A and C must be the same species. (A could interbreed with B but not C). It is only the fact that most intermediates have died out that gives the impression of distinct species (and gives the impression of transitivity).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Based on a brief search of half a dozen dictionaries.

  2. 2.

    And, of course, the interbreeding criterion can’t be the criterion for life forms that reproduce asexually.

  3. 3.

    See Dawkins’ examples of the salamanders and the gulls [9, pp. 308–311].

  4. 4.

    If you want to resist the conclusion that we have special obligations to other mammals, over reptiles for example, this looks less problematic than in the previous case, because the idea that the principle may effectively fade away at some stage seems more plausible than the on and off nature of the previous account.

  5. 5.

    The human is severely mentally disabled in this case so that the human does not have capabilities that the dog lacks, so that if we follow Singer’s suggestion of judging individuals by their individual capabilities, we would not be able to distinguish between the two. As such, if we think we should save the human rather than the dog, it would seem to be just because he is human, and not because he is autonomous or has capacities that the dog does not.

References

  1. Blackburn, S.: Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Tooley, M.: Abortion and infanticide. Philos. Public Aff. 2(1), 51 (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Singer, P.: Practical Ethics, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cohen, C.: The case for the use of animals in biomedical research. N. Engl. J. Med. 315(14), 867 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. LaFollette, H., Shanks, N.: The origin of speciesism. Philosophy 71, 41 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Oderberg, D.: Applied Ethics: A Non-consequentialist Approach. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Singer, P.: A Darwinian Left: Politics, Evolution, and Cooperation. Yale University Press, New haven (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Oderberg, D.: Moral Theory: A Non-consequentialist Approach. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Dawkins, R.: The Ancestor’s Tale: A pilgrimage to the Fawn of Life. Phoenix, London (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Darwin, C.: The Origin of the Species – Wordsworth Classics of World Literature. Wordsworth Editions, Ware (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Edwards, A.W.F.: Human genetic diversity: Lewontin’s fallacy. Bioessays 25, 798–801 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For comments and helpful advice on previous drafts, I am grateful to Paul Affleck, Mikel Burley, Daniel Elstein, Shane Glackin, Gerald Lang, Chris Megone, Georgia Testa, and an anonymous referee for this book.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rob Lawlor .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lawlor, R. (2012). The Ethical Treatment of Animals: The Moral Significance of Darwin’s Theory. In: Brinkworth, M., Weinert, F. (eds) Evolution 2.0. The Frontiers Collection. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-20496-8_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics