Skip to main content

Robust Equal Representation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Decision-Making in Committees

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems ((LNE,volume 635))

  • 670 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter investigates the robustness of square root rules for equal representation in two-tiered voting systems. When policy alternatives are non-binary and decisions are made by simple majority rule, Chap. 2 demonstrated that weight proportional to the square root of population size is approximately optimal, which may be interpreted as extending the scope of Penrose’s square root rule beyond the narrow limits of binary decision-making. However, in light of the normative character of this result, the simplifications used in the modeling of a complex real situation, such as, e.g., decision-making in the EU Council of Ministers, require special scrutiny.

Specifically, the aim of this chapter is to conduct a ‘sensitivity analysis’ regarding the square root rule, addressing the following questions How does a ‘simple’ voting rule that derives directly from constituency sizes perform compared to more sophisticated rules that use standard power indices as reference points? What is the fair voting rule under supermajority rules at the top tier? How does the fair voting rule react to heterogeneity across constituencies?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A subset of a partially ordered set (or poset) (P, <  P ) – where P is a set, and <  P is a partial order relation – is an antichain if any two elements of the subset are incomparable under <  P . Applied to simple voting games, the power set 2N is partially ordered in respect to the inclusion ⊆ , and each set of minimum winning coalitions, characterizing a game, corresponds to an antichain.

  2. 2.

    The minimum integer weight representations of these four games are (3; 2, 1, 1), (3; 1, 2, 1), (3; 1, 1, 2), and (2; 1, 1, 1). In Fig. 3.1, these games correspond to the four points in the interior of the simplex.

  3. 3.

    In 15 of the configurations, population sizes were drawn from a uniform distribution, and in the other 15 from a Pareto distribution with κ = 1. 0.

  4. 4.

    For special classes of weighted voting games, Lindner and Machover (2004) prove Penrose’s 1952 Limit Theorem with respect to the Penrose–Banzhaf index for q = 0. 5 and with respect to the Shapley–Shubik index for q ∈ (0, 1). Their conjecture that the Theorem holds ‘almost always’ under rather general conditions is corroborated in a simulation study by Chang et al. (2006).

  5. 5.

    The Nelder–Mead algorithm does not rely on numerical or analytic gradients, which makes it particularly suitable to non-linear optimization problems like the present. In each step of the search, the probabilities \({\pi }_{j} \equiv \Pr \left (j = P\! :\! m\right )\) of representative j being pivotal in the top-tier committee are approximated by their empirical average over 10 million iterations. A MATLAB computer program is used for the computations. The source code is available upon request.

  6. 6.

    Generally, α = 0. 5 is not exactly the best exponent among all power laws. Obviously, the best power law weights \({w}_{j} = {n}_{j}^{{\alpha }^{{_\ast}} }\) for a given configuration result in a lower deviation from egalitarian representation than simple square root weights, but they turn out to perform still worse than w β and w ϕ.

  7. 7.

    The 12 configurations consist of 3  × 4 configurations with population sizes drawn from a uniform, a normal, and a Pareto (κ = 1. 0) distribution, respectively.

  8. 8.

    One criticism advanced by Rae (1975) is that Pareto-optimality is compatible with a possibly outrageous distributional situation which is locked in under unanimity rule.

  9. 9.

    On the other hand, supermajorities could serve to mitigate time inconsistencies if they make it more difficult to revise a policy.

  10. 10.

    More precisely, the ‘social consensus’ which Caplin and Nalebuff (1988) presuppose amounts to the restriction that the density of voters’ ideal points is a logarithmically concave function, e.g., a uniform density over a convex set. Then, points exist which cannot be defeated by any other alternative under a majority requirement larger than or equal to \(1 - 1/e \approx 0.64\).

  11. 11.

    The claim that supermajorities are minority-protecting rests on the assumption, uncovered by McGann (2004), that the status quo is more benign for the minority than government action to change it.

  12. 12.

    The tests for 30-constituency unions reported at the end of Sect. 3.1 concern precisely the configurations which are used in the present simulations on quota variation.

  13. 13.

    It is not possible to compare the columns in Table 3.3 with respect to the variance of constituency sizes because the variance of P(κ, \underline{x}) is infinity for κ ≤ 2.

  14. 14.

    A ‘common belief’ is also represented by Straffin’s (1977) homogeneity assumption under which the probability of a voter ‘affecting the outcome’ coincides with the Shapley–Shubik index.

  15. 15.

    Concerning the probabilistic interpretation of power measures (cf. Sect. 1.2.1), Braham and Steffen (2002) argue that the whole range of partial homogeneity assumptions is no less a priori than its two borderline cases, i.e., the Banzhaf index and the Shapley–Shubik index.

  16. 16.

    If the distributions of individual ideal points are symmetric, \(\tilde{{\Delta }}_{j}\) could also refer to the mean of the distribution f j .

  17. 17.

    Eurostat population numbers for EU27 countries as of 01/01/2007 are used as simulation input.

  18. 18.

    The assumption that preferences are more heterogeneous in large populations is also made in Alesina and Spolaore (2003), and the trade-off between the costs of differences and the economies of scope in large jurisdictions determines nation size in their framework.

  19. 19.

    The difference between these two quantities is very similar to the mean majority deficit which is also minimized under square root weights (see Felsenthal and Machover, 1998, pp. 72ff).

References

  • Alesina, A., & Spolaore, E. (2003). The size of nations. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avriel, M. (1976). Nonlinear programming: Analysis and methods. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, R. E., Berglöf, E., Giavazzi, F., & Widgrén, M. (2001). Nice try: Should the treaty of nice be ratified? Monitoring European Integration 11. London: Center for Economic Policy Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C., & Bovens, L. (2007). Welfarist evaluations of decision rules for boards of representatives. Social Choice and Welfare, 29(4), 581–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C., & Hartmann, S. (2006). Welfarism and the assessment of social decision rules. In U. Endriss & J. Lang (Eds.), Computational social choice 2006 (pp. 35–48). Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braham, M., & Steffen, F. (2002). Local monotoncity of voting power: A conceptual analysis. Mimeo. University of Hamburg, Hamburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., & Nalebuff, B. (1988). On 64%-majority rule. Econometrica, 56(4), 787–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chamberlain, G., & Rothschild, M. (1981). A note on the probability of casting a decisive vote. Journal of Economic Theory, 25(1), 152–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, P.-L., Chua, V. C., & Machover, M. (2006). L S Penrose’s limit theorem: Tests by simulation. Mathematical Social Sciences, 51(1), 90–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, P., & Shapley, L. S. (1979). Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Mathematics of Operations Research, 4(2), 99–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal, D., & Machover, M. (1998). The measurement of voting power – theory and practice, problems and paradoxes. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal, D., & Machover, M. (2001). The treaty of nice and qualified majority voting. Social Choice and Welfare, 18(3), 431–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J., & Mayer, L. S. (1975). Estimating the efficacy of a vote. Behavioral Science, 20(1), 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harstad, B. (2005). Majority rules and incentives. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 120(4),1535–1568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harstad, B. (2008). Strategic delegation and voting rules. Mimeo. Kellogg School of Management, Evanston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollander, M., & Wolfe, D. A. (1999). Nonparametric statistical methods (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holler, M. J. (1985). Strict proportional power in voting bodies. Theory and Decision, 19(3),249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaniovski, S. (2008). The exact bias of the Banzhaf measure of power when votes are neither equiprobable nor independent. Social Choice and Welfare, 31(2), 281–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsch, W. (2007). On penrose’s square-root law and beyond. Homo Oeconomicus, 24(3–4),357–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laruelle, A., & Valenciano, F. (2007). Bargaining in committees as an extension of Nash’s Bargaining theory. Journal of Economic Theory, 132(1), 291–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laruelle, A., & Valenciano, F. (2008a). Bargaining in committees of representatives: The ‘neutral’ voting rule. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 20(1), 93–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leech, D. (2003). Power indices as an aid to institutional design: The generalised apportionment problem. In M. J. Holler, H. Kliemt, D. Schmidtchen, & M. E. Streit (Eds.), Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie (Vol. 22, pp. 107–121). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leech, D., & Machover, M. (2003). Qualified majority voting: The effect of the quota. In M. J. Holler, H. Kliemt, D. Schmidtchen, & M. E. Streit (Eds.), Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie 22 (pp. 127–143). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindner, I., & Machover, M. (2004). L. S. Penrose’s limit theorem: Proof of some special cases. Mathematical Social Sciences, 47(1), 37–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, K. O. (1952). A set of independent, necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica, 20(4), 680–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGann, A. J. (2004). The tyranny of the supermajority: How majority rule protects minorities. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16(1), 53–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1984). Are qualified majority rules special? Social Choice and Welfare, 18(3), 431–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rae, D. W. (1969). Decision-rules and individual values in constitutional choice. American Political Science Review, 63(1), 40–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, D. W. (1975). The limits of consensual decision. American Political Science Review, 69(4), 1270–1294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiebout, C. (1956). A pure theory of local expenditure. Journal of Political Economy, 64(5), 416–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicksell, K. (1969[1896]). Finanztheoretische Untersuchungen nebst Darstellung und Kritik des Steuerwesens Schwedens. Aalen: Scientia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicola F. Maaser .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Maaser, N.F. (2010). Robust Equal Representation. In: Decision-Making in Committees. Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems, vol 635. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-04153-2_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-04153-2_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-04152-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-04153-2

  • eBook Packages: Business and EconomicsEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics