Skip to main content

Moral Motivation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Games, Groups, and the Global Good

Part of the book series: Springer Series in Game Theory ((SSGT))

  • 1530 Accesses

Abstract

This paper is about moral motivation from the perspective of Kantian moral philosophy. It looks at recent literature on the development of human sociality from within game theory, and argues that a retrieval of Kant’s views on moral theology would be helpful in understanding an aspect of this sociality. In particular, Kant’s view that we need to postulate the existence of God as sovereign of the kingdom of ends helps us understand the role of religion in making self-indexed and non-self-indexed motivation consistent (i.e., motivation towards a good which is specified with essential reference to the self and motivation towards a good which is specified without such reference). Kant’s complex views on divine punishment are also helpful, and his views on divine assistance in the production of moral motivation can help us understand the invocation of such assistance in signaling difficult commitment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Binmore (1994, vol. 1, p 152). The title of the chapter is a quotation from Samuel Johnson, “My Dear Sir, Clear Your Mind of Cant.”

  2. 2.

    Binmore (1994, p 18).

  3. 3.

    Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 4: 419. I will cite Kant’s works in the Berlin Academy edition, by volume and page number, and I will abbreviate the present work as Groundwork.

  4. 4.

    Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 4: 421.

  5. 5.

    The description of a maxim as giving the “actually intended reason” raises important questions about “proximate” and “ultimate” causes of behavior, and about self-deception. See Trivers (2000). In this paper I am distinguishing reasons (not necessarily articulated to herself) that an agent gives to herself for acting in a certain way, from external causes of behavior. There are large philosophical questions about whether an agent’s reasons for action are ultimately caused by forces (for example the evolutionary imperative to reproduce) outside the agent’s rational will. If they are, then Kant’s moral philosophy fails. But we do not yet know that they are, and in the meantime we need a theory of reasons for action.

  6. 6.

    Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 4: 422.

  7. 7.

    Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 4: 429.

  8. 8.

    Critique of Practical Reason 5: 114.

  9. 9.

    Nowak and Coakley (2009), introduction.

  10. 10.

    Sober and Wilson (1998, pp 4–6).

  11. 11.

    Bowles and Gintis (2009) final paragraph.

  12. 12.

    Binmore (2005).

  13. 13.

    There are complex questions in the philosophy of mind about whether brain imaging would help determine empirically what is going on “inside a person” in the relevant sense. This is not a debate I can get into in this paper.

  14. 14.

    For example, Critique of Practical Reason, 5: 129, but there are similar statements in the Critique of Judgment, the Metaphysics of Morals, Religion, Conflict of the Faculties, and elsewhere in the corpus.

  15. 15.

    Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, 6: 154. I will abbreviate this work as Religion.

  16. 16.

    Groundwork, 4: 434.

  17. 17.

    Critique of Practical Reason, 5: 25.

  18. 18.

    Religion 6: 3.

  19. 19.

    Religion 6: 6. This does not mean, in Kant’s view that only theists can be morally good, but he holds that the position of the morally good atheist is “rationally unstable.” See Hare (2005).

  20. 20.

    Schneewind (1998) 447, 520–521.

  21. 21.

    I have laid out the history more fully in Hare (2007) especially Chap. 2.

  22. 22.

    Religious Affections, x. The words of Moses are at Exodus 32: 32, and of Paul at Romans 9: 3.

  23. 23.

    The quotation is from Gintis (2005, p 8). Non-self-indexed motivation also needs to be distinguished from the benefactor’s and recipient’s so-called “reciprocal altruism” (where there is expectation of benefit from the recipient) and “indirect reciprocity” (in which one’s reputation for cooperation is rewarded indirectly through the favor of third-party observers).

  24. 24.

    One study worked in 12 countries on four continents, and recruited subjects from 15 small-scale societies, consisting of three foraging groups, six slash-and-burn horticulturalists and agropasturalists, four nomadic herding groups, and two sedentary, small-scale agricultural societies, Henrich (2004).

  25. 25.

    The claim about primates is defended by Silk (2005, pp 63–64).

  26. 26.

    Silk (2005, p 63).

  27. 27.

    Fehr and chter (2002, pp 137–140).

  28. 28.

    The claim about the pervasiveness of religion is in Brown (1991) and Boyer (2001). See also Bering and Johnson (2005). In the standard cross-cultural sample of 186 societies (from the Ethnographic Atlas of 1,267 entries) all have gods and 168 have “high gods.”

  29. 29.

    A number of writers have suggested such a connection. See Johnson and Kruger (2004), Roes and Raymond (2003), Sosis and Alcorta (2003), and Wilson (2002).

  30. 30.

    Religion 6: 6.

  31. 31.

    It is possible that there is empirical evidence of some kind of human predisposition to entertain the idea of divine agency. See Bering (2006).

  32. 32.

    I have explained this in more detail in God and Morality, op. cit. Chap. 3.

  33. 33.

    Here I depart from Kant, who does make the necessity claim, e.g., Critique of Practical Reason 5: 138. See also footnote 38 of the present paper.

  34. 34.

    Metaphysics of Morals 6: 396.

  35. 35.

    Groundwork 4: 431.

  36. 36.

    Johnson (2005, p 411). The point, made by Johnson, that punishment is more effective motivationally than reward (sticks than carrots) does not affect the distinction I have just made. Being motivated by a reward in heaven is no more autonomous than being motivated by punishment in hell.

  37. 37.

    Sidgwick (1981, p 505).

  38. 38.

    Kant, like other contemporaries in the Enlightenment, is too optimistic that he can identify what reason tells every human at every time and place. See Religion 6: 9. He did think that the categorical imperative has been known to all humans at all times and places.

  39. 39.

    We might expect that if God is believed to be the ultimate guarantor of justice, human punishers, though they will punish failures to cooperate, will not punish so readily failures to punish those who fail to cooperate. The reason is that the second-order punishing (and perhaps third-order punishing of those who fail to punish those who fail to punish those who fail to cooperate) is closer to the systems maintenance which is the role given to the gods. In such a set of beliefs, the rules of cooperation might survive without large-scale human second-order and higher-order punishing.

  40. 40.

    For a more detailed treatment of these tasks see Swinburne (1989, 25f), and Hare (1996) Chap. 9.

  41. 41.

    Religion 6: 72.

  42. 42.

    There has been an interest in the literature on the benefits of religion in providing costly signaling. See Sosis and Alcorta (2003).

  43. 43.

    Religion 6: 44.

  44. 44.

    Carson (2000) Chap. 8.

  45. 45.

    Anscombe (reprinted 1981). Adams (1999) 253f argues that Durkheim parodied this concept in order to get a concept of society as the source of moral obligation.

  46. 46.

    Nietzsche (1967, pp 90–91), “There is no small probability that with the irresistible decline of faith in the Christian God, there is now also a considerable decline in mankind’s feeling of guilt.” Williams (1985, pp 191–196). I am grateful to Dominic Johnson for comments on the present paper.

References

  • Adams RM (1999) Finite and Infinite Goods. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe E (1981) Modern moral philosophy, In: Ethics, religion, and politics. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Bering JM (2006) The cognitive psychology of belief in the supernatural. Am Sci 94:142–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Bering JM, Johnson DDP (2005) O Lord  You perceive my thoughts from afar: recursiveness and the evolution of supernatural agency. J Cogn Cult 5:118–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (1994) Game theory and the social contract. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2005) Natural justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles S, Gintis H (2009) Cooperative Homo economicus, present volume

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer P (2001) Religion explained: the evolutionary origins of religious thought. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown DE (1991) Human universals, McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson T (2000) Value and the good life. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards J (1746) Religious affections

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Gächter S (2002) Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415:137–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H et al (2005) Moral sentiments and material interests. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare JE (1996) The moral gap. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare JE (2005) Kant on the rational instability of atheism. In: Dole A, Chignell A (eds) God and the ethics of belief. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 202–218

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hare JE (2007) God and morality: a philosophical history. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J et al (2004) Foundations of human sociality: ethnography and experiments in fifteen small-scale societies. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson DDP (2005) God’s punishment and public goods. Human Nature 16

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson DDP, Kruger O (2004) The good of wrath: supernatural punishment and the evolution of cooperation. Polit Theol 5:159–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1785) Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1788) Critique of practical reason

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1790) Critique of judgment

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1793/4) Religion within the boundaries of mere reason

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1797) Metaphysics of morals

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche F (1967) On the genealogy of morals. Vintage Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak MA, Coakley S (2009) Evolution, games and God: the principle of cooperation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Roes FL, Raymond M (2003)Belief in moralizing Gods. Evolution and human behavior 24:126–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneewind JB (1998) The invention of autonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick H (1981) The methods of ethics, 7th edn. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Silk JB (2005) The evolution of cooperation in primate groups, In: Gintis

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosis R, Alcorta C (2003) Signaling, solidarity, and the sacred: the evolution of religious behavior. Evol Anthropol 12:264–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne R (1989) Responsibility and atonement. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers R (2000) The elements of a scientific theory of self-deception. Ann NY Acad Sci 907:114–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (2002) Darwin’s cathedral: evolution, religion, and the nature of society. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hare, J.E. (2009). Moral Motivation. In: Levin, S. (eds) Games, Groups, and the Global Good. Springer Series in Game Theory. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-540-85436-4_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-540-85436-4_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-540-85435-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-540-85436-4

  • eBook Packages: Business and EconomicsEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics