Skip to main content

Hegel and McDowell on Perceptual Experience and Judgment

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
McDowell and Hegel

Part of the book series: Studies in German Idealism ((SIGI,volume 20))

Abstract

In this paper, I start from a criticism that John McDowell has made of the account of perception contained in Mind and World. In the essay Avoiding the Myth of the Given, he describes his earlier account as having been flawed by his having equated the idea of the conceptuality of perceptual experience with that of its propositionality. While agreeing with this criticism, I suggest that McDowell’s diagnosis of the earlier problem, as well as his suggestions for its solution, are obscured by his continuing to situate his account of perception within the predominantly epistemological framework of Mind and World. In contrast, and guided by Hegel’s account of the logic of perceptual judgment, I invoke a different function served by Kant’s idea of the “intuitive” content of perceptual experience—its modal function of indicating actual from merely possible states of affairs. Comparing Hegel’s metaphysical position to that of contemporary modal actualists, I argue that by transforming Kant’s concept–intuition distinction into a logical distinction between different types of judgment employing different notions of predication, Hegel was able to capture the modal function played by Kantian intuition without falling into the problematic “Myth of the Given.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    AMG, 257.

  2. 2.

    AMG, 258.

  3. 3.

    See AMG, 258: “I used to assume that to conceive experiences as actualizations of conceptual capacities, we would need to credit experiences with propositional content, the sort of content judgments have. And I used to assume that the content of an experience would need to include everything the experience enables its subject to know non-inferentially. But both these assumptions now strike me as wrong.”

  4. 4.

    Davidson (1983, 426).

  5. 5.

    AMG, 268.

  6. 6.

    AMG, 268–269.

  7. 7.

    AMG, 269.

  8. 8.

    Kant (1998, A51/B75).

  9. 9.

    In recent work Stalnaker has emphasized that his approach to possible-world semantics involves a retreat from the principle of extensionality as applying to non-actual worlds. See especially Stalnaker (2012). Here I treat as “intensional,” any logic that cannot be interpreted as fully extensional.

  10. 10.

    In the Metaphysical Deduction of Critique of Pure Reason, Kant discusses the modal categories of possibility, existence, and necessity [Kant (1998, A80/B106)], linking them the modality of problematic, assertoric and apodictic judgments [Kant (1998, A70/B95)].

  11. 11.

    Kant (1998, A218/B265), emphasis added.

  12. 12.

    When Kant here repeats that “in the mere concept of a thing no characteristic of its existence can be encountered at all” he obscures the role played by the form of intuition here. “For even if this concept is so complete that it lacks nothing required for thinking of a thing with all of its inner determinations, still existence has nothing in the least to do with all of this, but only with the question of whether such a thing is given to us in such a way that the perception of it could in any case precede the concept.” Kant (1998, A225/B272).

  13. 13.

    Kant (1998, A225/B272–3).

  14. 14.

    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant describes sensation as “the effect of an object on the capacity for representation, insofar as we are affected by it” and characterizes an empirical intuition as one that is “related to the object through sensation.” Kant (1998, A20/B34).

  15. 15.

    For example, the criteria for an attitude’s content being actual is just what, in relation to the attitude itself, marks it as a case of perceiving rather than, say merely hypothesising or imagining

  16. 16.

    See here especially Michael Friedman’s lucid presentation of these issues in Friedman (1992, Ch. 2, Concepts and Intuitions in the Mathematical Sciences).

  17. 17.

    See here in particular Thompson (1972–1973), in which Thompson portrays Kant’s transcendental logic as anticipating Fregean formal logic, with a concomitant treatment of intuitions as semantically analogous to demonstrative pronouns.

  18. 18.

    Sellars (1997).

  19. 19.

    Sellars (1997, §§ 14–16).

  20. 20.

    Phen M, Ch 1.

  21. 21.

    See, for example, DeVries (2008).

  22. 22.

    In modern mathematical logic, set theory is employed as a way of conceiving of how the identity of a concept is established entirely in terms of its extension. The distinction between “extension” and “intension” goes back to the Port Royal Logic and was used, although often confused, in the eighteenth century.

  23. 23.

    Modal notions of necessity and possibility provide contexts in which the principle of extensionality does not seem to apply. That is, a term cannot always be replaced with a co-referring term and the truth value of the statement preserved.

  24. 24.

    SL DG, 553.

  25. 25.

    Wittgenstein , (1922, § 3.12).

  26. 26.

    Wittgenstein , (1922, § 3.21).

  27. 27.

    SL DG, 562. Here Hegel is talking of the initial form of the judgment of determinate being, the positive judgment, which is not truly a judgment but only a Satz.

  28. 28.

    SL DG, 553.

  29. 29.

    See Brandom (2002, 2009) and A Spirit of Trust, unpublished, draft available at <http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/spirit_of_trust_2014.html>. I have argued elsewhere, however, that Hegel’s inferentialism is weaker than that defended by Brandom . See my Redding (2015).

  30. 30.

    See SL DG, 553: “It can also be mentioned in this context that a proposition [Satz] can indeed have a subject and predicate in a grammatical sense without however being a judgment [Urteil] for that. The latter requires that the predicate behave with respect to the subject in a relation of conceptual determination, hence as a universal with respect to a particular or singular.”

  31. 31.

    SL DG, 565. Here Hegel draws on features of the logical structure of perceptual judgments later pointed out by the Cambridge logician and Russell-critic, W. E. Johnson (1921, Ch. 11), when he called such predicates the determinants of some general determinable. Arthur Prior notes the non-extensionality of this relation in Prior (1968, 94–95).

  32. 32.

    Moreover, what counts as a determinable of any entity depends up what sort of entity it is. While numbers can be characterized as either odd or even, but not as either red, or blue, or yellow, or …, roses can be characterised as either red, or blue, or yellow, or …, but not as either odd or even.

  33. 33.

    Brandom treats such “incompatibility entailments” as generalizations of modal judgments that do not have classical analogues. See, for example, his Brandom (2000, Ch. 6).

  34. 34.

    Otherwise it would be a Satz rather than a Urteil.

  35. 35.

    For an approach to modal logic along these general lines see Blackburn , de Rijke and Venema (2001).

  36. 36.

    This general conception of the subject of such a perceptual judgment broadly coincides, I suggest, with what Hegel describes as the object of perception [Wahrnehmen] as discussed in the Phenomenology of Spirit, Chap. 2 .

  37. 37.

    See Whitaker (1996, Ch. 7).

  38. 38.

    The textbook used was Ploucquet (2006). On Ploucquet’s treatment of this ambiguity see Aner (1999).

  39. 39.

    We might thus think of such “reflective” properties more on the model of the posited “forces” that explain the fluctuations of appearance as explored by Hegel in Chap. 3 of the Phenomenology of Spirit, Force and the Understanding. See my Redding (2010–2011).

  40. 40.

    That is, “some rose (or roses) is (or are) red” can be regarded as implying “It is not the case that all roses are not red,” and as such it is classed as a reflective judgment. It should be noted here that Hegel’s particularly quantified reflective judgments are what are treated in modern logic as existentially quantified judgments.

  41. 41.

    This is linked to the reversal of which term plays the role of S and which P.

  42. 42.

    Analysis, Hegel tells us in the Encyclopaedia Logic, “consists […] in dissolving [aufzulösen] the concrete that is given, isolating its distinctions and bestowing the form of abstract universality upon them; in other words, it consists in leaving the concrete as ground and making a concrete universal—the genus, or force and law—stand out through abstraction from the particularities that seem to be inessential.” EL, § 229A.

  43. 43.

    In the Encyclopedia Logic, in commenting on empiricism, which “relies on the analytic method,” he notes that it “falls into error” when it assumes that in analysis it leaves such concrete objects of perception—Gegenstanden—“as they are.” In fact, abstraction “transforms what is concrete into something abstract [das Konkrete in ein Abstraktes verwandelt].” EL, § 38A.

  44. 44.

    See Lewis (2001).

  45. 45.

    Some actualists have equally counterintuitive ontological commitments, however. Here I am following approaches like that of Robert Stalnaker who pursues a metaphysically minimal type of actualism. See especially, Stalkaner (2012).

  46. 46.

    See especially, Stalnaker (2012).

  47. 47.

    Appealing to ordinary consciousness he notes that “when we speak of the possible, as distinct from the actual, we call it ‘merely’ possible.” EL, § 143A.

  48. 48.

    Hegel does not see Plato as a Platonist, however. On his strong rejection of transcendentist modes of thought see my Redding (2016).

  49. 49.

    See here especially Knappik (2015).

  50. 50.

    “Possibility is what is essential to reality, but in such a way that it is at the same time only possibility.” EL, § 143R.

  51. 51.

    EL, § 143R.

  52. 52.

    Significantly, C. I. Lewis drew upon the logic of his “absolute idealist” teacher Josiah Royce.

  53. 53.

    Lewis (1918, 333).

  54. 54.

    Modern predicate logic employs the notions of “existential generalization” and “existential instantiation” to capture the inferences involved. Existential instantiation says that one can validly move from an existentially quantified statement to one containing a new constant, ((∃x) Fx :: Fa). Modal actualists must deny the validity of existential instantiation for non-actual worlds.

  55. 55.

    One opponent to this analysis has been Tyler Burge . See Burge (2007a, 2007b, 2009).

  56. 56.

    Work on this topic was facilitated by a Discovery Grant from the Australian Research Council, DP0984296. I am most grateful to John McDowell, Stephen Houlgate , Simon Lumsden, Melissa Merritt, Tom Rockmore , Markos Valaris and Ken Westphal for helpful feedback on various earlier incarnations of this paper.

References

  • Aner, Karl. 1999. Gottfried Ploucquets Leben und Lehren. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Patrick, Maarten de Rijke, and Yde Venema. 2001. Modal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2000. Articulating Reasons. An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Tales of the Mighty Dead. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, Tyler. 2007a. Belief De Re. In Foundations of Mind: Philosophical Essays, Volume 2, 44–64. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. Postscript to ‘Belief De Re’. In Foundations of Mind: Philosophical Essays, Volume 2, 65–81. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes. In The Philosophy of David Kaplan, ed. J. Almog and P. Leonardi, 246–324. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1983. A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge. In Kant oder Hegel, ed. D. Henrich, 423–438. Stuttgart: Klett–Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeVries, Willem. 2008. Sense-Certainty and the ‘This-Such’. In Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Critical Guide, ed. D. Moyar and M. Quante, 63–75. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. 1992. Kant and the Exact Sciences. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, William Ernest. 1921. Logic: Part 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and Trans. P. Guyer and A.W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knappik, Franz. 2015. Hegel’s Modal Argument Against Spinozism. An Interpretation of the Chapter ‘Actuality’ in the Science of Logic. Hegel Bulletin 36 (1): 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, Clarence Irving. 1918. A Survey of Symbolic Logic. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David K. 2001. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ploucquet, Gottfried. 2006. Logik. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, Arthur. 1968. Intentionality and Intensionality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 42: 91–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redding, Paul. 2010–2011. Hegel’s Anticipation of the Early History of Analytic Philosophy. The Owl of Minerva 42(1–2): 18–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redding, Paul. 2015. An Hegelian Solution to a Tangle of Problems Facing Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (4): 657–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The History of Philosophy, Ancient and Medieval. In The Oxford Handbook of Hegel, ed. D. Moyar, 603–622. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert C. 2012. Mere Possibilities: Metaphysical Foundations of Modal Semantics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Manley. 1972–1973. Singular Terms and Intuitions in Kant’s Epistemology. Review of Metaphysics 26: 314–343. https://philpapers.org/rec/STEEOH.

  • Whitaker, C.W.A. 1996. Aristotle’s De Interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Redding .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Redding, P. (2018). Hegel and McDowell on Perceptual Experience and Judgment. In: Sanguinetti, F., Abath, A. (eds) McDowell and Hegel. Studies in German Idealism, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98896-2_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics