Skip to main content

Modular, Expandable Typologies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover A Knowledge Representation Practionary
  • 902 Accesses

Abstract

The idea of a SuperType is exactly equivalent to the root node of a typology, wherein multiple entity types with similar essences and characteristics are related to one another via a natural classification. In this chapter, we discuss the use of types as our general classification structure, and then typologies as modular ways to further organize those types. Further, Peirce was expansive in his recognition of what kinds of objects could be classified, explicitly including ideas, with application to areas such as social classes, human-made objects, sciences, chemical elements, and living organisms. Our typology design has arisen from the intersection of (1) our efforts with SuperTypes to create a computable structure that uses powerful disjoint assertions; (2) an appreciation of the importance of entity types as a focus of knowledge base terminology; and (3) our efforts to segregate entities from other constructs of knowledge bases, including attributes, relations, and annotations. Unlike more interconnected knowledge graphs (which can have many network linkages), typologies are organized strictly along these lines of shared attributes, which both is simpler and provides an orthogonal means for investigating type-class membership. The idea of nested, hierarchical types organized into broad branches of different entity typologies also offers a flexible design for interoperating with a diversity of worldviews and degrees of specificity. The best perspective to see the full listing of the typologies in KBpedia is to inspect the Generals branch of the KKO knowledge graph, which contains about 85 SuperTypes (typologies).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some material in this chapter was drawn from the author’s prior articles at the AI3:::Adaptive Information blog: “Climbing the Data Federation Pyramid” (May 2006); “‘Structs’: Naïve Data Formats and the ABox” (Jan 2009); “Advantages and Myths of RDF” (Apr 2009); “structWSF: A Framework for Data Mixing” (Jun 2009); “Big Structure and Data Interoperability” (Aug 2014); “Logical Implications of Interoperability” (Jun 2015); “How Fine Grained Can Entity Types Get?” (Mar 2016); “Rationales for Typology Designs in Knowledge Bases” (Jun 2016); “Threes All of the Way Down to Typologies” (Oct 2016).

  2. 2.

    From a vocabulary standpoint, we describe the role of nouns and relations in Chap. 7; I also speculate on parts of speech in relation to Peircean terminology in Chap. 16 (esp. Table 16.2).

  3. 3.

    Aspects of Peirce’s definition of types have some interesting parallels to type theory (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Type_theory), especially homotopy type theory (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Homotopy_type_theory), that we do not have time to pursue further here. In type theory, well-founded types are ones where we can define objects by primitive recursion and prove properties by induction (see Thompson, S., Type Theory and Functional Programming, Addison Wesley, 1991). Primitive recursion over Boolean properties (which is why dichotomous keys for classification are so useful) is an interesting link to type theory, as are type families and creating new types. Further, some proposed resolutions to improve the representation of subsets in type theories involve representing propositions distinct from types or as types.

  4. 4.

    Philosophers often contrast realism to idealism, nominalism, or conceptualism, wherein how the world exists is a function of how we think about or name things. Descartes, for example, summarized his conceptualist view with his aphorism “I think, therefore I am.”

  5. 5.

    For example, try this query, https://scholar.google.com/scholar?q=“fine-grained+entity,” also without quotes.

  6. 6.

    However, like the Chevy Malibu case described earlier, items that appear as instances in the putative typology may be expanded to become an eventual class (type), with its own instances, akin to the punning discussion in the prior chapter.

  7. 7.

    For best interoperability with KBpedia, the SKOS reference should include the SKOS DL version; see M.K. Bergman, “SKOS Now Interoperates with OWL 2,” AI3:::Adaptive Information blog, February 10, 2011.

  8. 8.

    UMBEL was a precursor to KBpedia first begun in 2006 and first released in 2008. KBpedia has now supplanted its earlier design.

  9. 9.

    See http://kbpedia.org.

  10. 10.

    For example, using the open-source Protégé ontology development environment (https://protege.stanford.edu/).

  11. 11.

    The remaining portions of the upper KKO are shown in Chap. 8.

  12. 12.

    Jack Park has questioned why chemistry appears in this schema, while physics and quantum phenomena do not. I agree those topics are worthy, likely under the Natural Matter node at the interface between Firstness and Secondness. Peirce does address these ideas a bit, and even posited something like the Big Bang (1888, CP 1.411–2). These fundamental perspectives on matter are an active area of research, though there are not many crumbs from Peirce on these topics. Still, as we learn more, I can readily see including such topics in the schema. As for the inclusion of chemistry and organic chemistry, we understand them better at present and they importantly demark the transition from natural matter to life. Chemistry is the laws or “habits” (Peirce’s term) for how matter interacts and what products (compounds) may result, so is a natural Thirdness with respect to matter. Organic chemistry provides the building blocks or possible compounds or substrates to life, so is equivalent to a Firstness regarding organic matter and life.

References

  1. A. Marradi, Classification, typology, taxonomy. Qual. Quant. 24(2), 129–157 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. L. Wetzel, Types and tokens, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by E.N. Zalta (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  3. M. Hulswit, Natural classes and causation, in The Online Digital Encyclopedia of, Charles S. Peirce (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  4. N. Chinchor, Overview of MUC-7, in MUC-7 Proceedings (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  5. A. Brunstein, Annotation Guidelines for Answer Types. Linguistic Data Consortium (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  6. S. Sekine, Extended named entity ontology with attribute information, in Proceedings of the Sixth International Language (2008), pp. 52–57

    Google Scholar 

  7. X. Ling, D.S. Weld, Fine-grained entity recognition, in Proceedings of the 26th AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  8. D. Gillick, N. Lazic, K. Ganchev, J. Kirchner, D. Huynh, Context-dependent fine-grained entity type tagging. arXiv:1412.1820 [cs] (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  9. S. Murty, P. Verga, L. Vilnis, A. McCallum, Finer grained entity typing with TypeNet. arXiv:1711.05795 [cs] (2017)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bergman, M.K. (2018). Modular, Expandable Typologies. In: A Knowledge Representation Practionary. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98092-8_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98092-8_10

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-98091-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-98092-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics