Skip to main content

Nationalism and Internationalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Marx on Emancipation and Socialist Goals

Part of the book series: Marx, Engels, and Marxisms ((MAENMA))

Abstract

Marx was an internationalist, who believed in the primacy of the productive forces and the centrality of class struggle. He wrote little directly on nations and nationality, but what he did write was with clarity and common sense. His most widely quoted passages, unfortunately, have been mistranslated and misinterpreted. Interpreters’ confusions about internationalism, universalism, the state, and globalization continue to affect the understanding of nationalism in Marx’s work and elsewhere.

For Marx, nations were important in capitalism and in transitional societies and would be in future communism. Some aspects of nations were made explicit by Marx, while others clearly fit his developed ideas. There is no reason to think that Marx would expect people to abandon their nation and nationality in seeking communism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Marx himself draws a similar analogy in his Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 where he talked about a renter finding “himself in someone else’s house” (MECW 3, p. 314). Benner also points out that Marx was probably disavowing the “highly charged political connotations” of the word Vaterland which “was used by both defenders of the traditional state and the Romantic prophets of ethnic nationality” ( Benner 1995, p. 54).

  2. 2.

    Norman Davies does write about many particular nations having vanished, but not all nations. Davies “remind[s us] of the transience of power, [a] fundamental characteristic both of the human condition and the political order…. All states and nations, however great, bloom for a season and are replaced” ( Davies 2012, p. 5), although this does not apply to communist futures. In Davies’ view, it is an underestimate that there are 207 “extinct states in Europe’s past” (p. 732).

    There are also nations that may be in the process of being born, such as those of the former Yugoslavia, Quebec, Scotland, Wales, Catalonia, Tibet, Palestine, Kurdistan, Cyprus.

  3. 3.

    Michael Löwy notes the idea of antagonisms in this passage, but still finds in “Marx and Engels’ writings … the hope of a future communist cosmopolis, a ‘world city’ without frontiers, a universal Gemeinshaft, an international socialist federation, in which not only national antagonisms and conflicts would disappear but also the economic, social and political (but not cultural) differences between nations” ( Löwy 1989, p. 222). National characteristics should be more enriched and could have the other characteristics in the right forms, as I argue below.

  4. 4.

    In this case the unnoted shift (in German) from abschaffen (abolish) to aufheben (transcend dialectically) appears of no significance compared to other unmarked occurrences in this part. For example, in the Manifesto (MECW 6, p. 498), Marx and Engels wrote about the communists abolishing (aufheben, i.e. transcending) private property when they were reproached with wanting to abolish (abschaffen, i.e. do away with) it. For some purposes this distinction can be crucial.

  5. 5.

    Much of what I say here is discussed and elaborated in Ware (1998). See also the other essays in Couture, et al. 1998.

  6. 6.

    The exception is the useful discussion by Forman (1999, esp. pp. 241–246).

  7. 7.

    Several years ago many Cypriots told me that the native Cypriots are one people, even though most are monolingual speakers of either Turkish or Greek. In Wales there are Welsh nationalists (for the nation and the nationality) who do not speak Welsh, but are united, as I heard in a couple of cases, through rugby.

  8. 8.

    The case of Africa in general is well discussed by Basil Davidson (1992). See Mahmoud Mamdani (1996) for an excellent discussion of the political determination of “national” differences in Rwanda. For a good discussion of the complex issues of nationality in India, see Chatterjee (1995) and Jangam (2017).

  9. 9.

    See, for example, Barry (1987).

  10. 10.

    Liah Greenfeld argues that German “[n]ationalism molded by the Romantic vision and widely shared, formed the foundation of Marx’s thought” ( Greenfeld 1992, p. 390). Greenfeld’s subsequent discussion of Marx replacing the idea of a nation with that of a class is marred by misinterpretations, but there is useful discussion about nationalism in Germany at the time. I find similar problems in Szporluk’s (1988) otherwise useful study.

  11. 11.

    For the German, I have used “Karl Marx – Friedrich Engels, Werke” (Berlin: Dietz Verlag). This quote comes from volume 3 (1969), p. 458.

  12. 12.

    There is an occurrence of the word in a letter of Engels, but the German was Internationalität rather than Internationalismus (MECW 27, p. 402). Marx never used the term “historical materialism” although it is appropriate for his “ materialist conception of history.” The absence of a term is not decisive.

  13. 13.

    On Connor’s (questionable) interpretation of nationalism as being about “the most fundamental divisions of humankind” ( Connor 1984, p. 5), Marx would not be a nationalist.

  14. 14.

    V. I. Lenin , “Critical Remarks on the National Question” quoted in Nimni (1991, p. 87). See also Löwy (1993) and Elster (1985, p. 397), but the view is widely expressed. It would be much different to advance it along with (virtually) all forms of nationalism.

  15. 15.

    On the importance of the national question in Ireland, about which Marx confessed to Engels (MECW 43, p. 398) that he had changed his mind, see MECW (21, pp. 84–91 and 112–124) and MECW (43, pp. 389–399). See also Benner (1995, pp. 186–187).

  16. 16.

    Marx focused on cooperating internationally rather than giving aid to people of other nations, as did, for example, Albert Schweitzer and Norman Bethune.

  17. 17.

    In an early (1845) piece, Engels did talk about proletarians being “antinational,” not antinationalist, as in the translation (MECW 6, p. 6).

  18. 18.

    For a more measured argument for this conclusion, see van der Linden (1996). See Chap. 6 for a discussion of Marx on working-class consciousness and worker organization.

  19. 19.

    Cocks sees this as a question and a conundrum for Marx, but I think her vision is clouded by a restrictive account of Marx as an antinationalist and universalizing internationalist .

  20. 20.

    See, for example, Cocks (1997), Sypnowich (1996), and van der Linden (1996). Of course, which characteristics and interests are universal and which particular depends on the details of the broader issues. For a good discussion of Marx’s pluralism, see Kain (1993, Chap. 7 “Marxism and Pluralism”).

  21. 21.

    That Marx did not talk about “ false consciousness” and would not think of nationalism in this way is nicely discussed by Cocks (1997).

  22. 22.

    Löwy uses “ideology” as necessarily negative, while I think it is better understood in an epistemologically neutral and political sense.

  23. 23.

    The speaker “addressed [the International Council] in ‘French’, i.e., in a language which 9/10 of the audience did not understand” (MECW 42, p. 287; Marx to Engels in 1866).

  24. 24.

    But it should be noted that Anderson also gives weight to the importance of functionaries, the media, and various structures of the state. These make it sound more objective and not simply a matter of subjective imagination (see, e.g. Anderson 1991, pp. 65 and 160).

  25. 25.

    It may be true of some Marxists, but not of Marx, that there was a “fetish of making sense of every significant social phenomenon by subsuming it within the logic of the universal development of the forces of production” ( Nimni 1991, p. 3). Munck (1986, pp. 163–166) agrees with Nimni on this. For some criticism of Nimni’s interpretation of Marx as an economic reductionist, see Purvis (1996, pp. 42ff).

  26. 26.

    This is precisely the view that Cohen approves of but withholds from Marx: that “locally produced cultural objects become globally available.” On the other hand, I see no evidence that Marx thought that the relation of people will be “on a world scale, not in addition to but instead of finding special fellowship in particular cultures” ( Cohen 2001, p. 354).

  27. 27.

    Again Marx has been badly translated. In his Critique of the Gotha Programme , Marx spoke of the Staatswesen, which is the essence of the state rather than the state itself.

  28. 28.

    For my discussion of some of these views and charges, I have relied on Munck (1986, pp. 9–28) and especially Benner (1995, pp. 159–170). See also Nimni (1991) and Purvis (1996).

  29. 29.

    See Davies (2012) on the death of nations and vanished kingdoms. A common giveaway of English prejudice is to say that Wales does not have a history as a nation. The response is that they have a long history that any Welsh text will adumbrate about the people’s language, culture, and community.

  30. 30.

    Benner (1995, pp. 165f) does give reason to doubt that Marx followed his close collaborator in these attitudes.

  31. 31.

    Marx’s remarks about the future society are elaborated and discussed in Chap. 10 on “Marx on State and Society in the Future” and in Ware (1992).

References

  • Note: References to the work of Frederick Engels and Karl Marx are from Karl Marx, Frederick Engels, Collected Works. 50 Volumes, 1975–2004. New York, NY: International Publishers. (Referred to in text as “MECW” with volume and page).

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. Rev. ed. London, UK: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Kevin B. 2010. Marx at the Margins: On Nationalism, Ethnicity, and Non-Western Societies. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian. 1987. Nationalism. In The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Political Thought, ed. David Miller, 352–354. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner, Erica. 1995. Really Existing Nationalisms: A Post-Communist View from Marx and Engels. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatterjee, Partha. 1995. The Nation and Its Fragments. New Delhi, India: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cocks, Joan. 1997. Touché! Marx on Nations and Nationalism. Socialism and Democracy 11 (2): 47–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2001 [1978]. Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence. Expanded ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Published in 1978 by Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Connor, Walker. 1984. The National Question in Marxist-Leninist Theory and Strategy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Couture, Jocelyne, Kai Nielsen, and Michel Seymour, eds. 1998. Rethinking Nationalism. Supplementary Volume 23 of Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Calgary, AB: University of Calgary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Basil. 1992. The Black Man’s Burden: Africa and the Curse of the Nation-State. New York, NY: Times Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Norman. 2012. Vanished Kingdoms: The History of Half-Forgotten Europe. London, UK: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1985. Making Sense of Marx. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press and Paris, France: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, Michael. 1999. Engels’s Internationalism and Theory of the Nation. In Engels after Marx, ed. Manfred B. Steger and Terrell Carver, 233–251. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenfeld, Liah. 1992. Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jangam, Chinnaiah. 2017. Dalits and the Making of Modern India. New Delhi, India: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kain, Philip J. 1993. Marx and Modern Political Theory: From Hobbes to Contemporary Feminism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwy, Michael. 1989. Revolution Today: Aspirations and Realities. In Socialist Register, 1989, ed. Ralph Miliband, Leo Panitch, and John Saville. London: The Merlin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Why Nationalism? In Real Problems; False Solutions (Socialist Register 1993), ed. Ralph Miliband and Leo Panitch. London, UK: The Merlin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mamdani, Mahmoud. 1996. From Conquest to Consent as the Basis of State Formation: Reflections on Rwanda. New Left Review 216: 3–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, David. 1995. On Nationality. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munck, Ronaldo. 1986. The Difficult Dialogue: Marxism and Nationalism. London, UK: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, Kai. 1998. Socialism and Nationalism. Imprint 2 (3): 208–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nimni, Ephraim. 1991. Marxism and Nationalism: Theoretical Origins of a Political Crisis. London, UK: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purvis, Trevor. 1996. Marxism and the Problem of the Nation. Socialist Studies Bulletin 44. Winnipeg, MB: Society for Socialist Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Philip. 1994. Siqueiros: His Life and Works. New York, NY: International Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sypnowich, Christine. 1996. Equality and Nationality. Politics and Society 24 (2): 93–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szporluk, Roman. 1988. Communism and Nationalism: Karl Marx Versus Friedrich List. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szymanski, Albert. 1983. Class Structure: A Critical Perspective. Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Linden, Harry. 1996. Marx’s Political Universalism. Topoi 15: 235–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ware, Robert. 1992. Marx on Some Phases of Communism. In On the Track of Reason: Essays in Honor of Kai Nielsen, ed. Rodger Beehler, David Copp, and Béla Szabados, 135–153. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Nations and Social Complexity. In Rethinking Nationalism, ed. Jocelyne Couture et al., 133–157. Calgary: University of Calgary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, Lois A., ed. 1997. Feminist Nationalism. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ware, R.X. (2019). Nationalism and Internationalism. In: Marx on Emancipation and Socialist Goals. Marx, Engels, and Marxisms. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-97716-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics