Skip to main content

Between Bernays and Carnap

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 399 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 43))

Abstract

Bernays has not drawn scholarly attention that he deserves. Only quite recently, the reevaluation of his philosophy, including the projects of editing, translating, and reissuing his writings, has just started. As a part of this renaissance of Bernays studies, this chapter tries to distinguish carefully between Hilbert’s and Bernays’ views regarding the axiomatic method. We shall highlight the fact that Hilbert was so proud of his own axiomatic method on textual evidence. Bernays’ estimation of the place of Hilbert’s achievements in the history of the axiomatic method will be scrutinized. Encouraged by the fact that there are big differences between the early middle Bernays and the later Bernays in this matter, we shall contrast them vividly. The most salient difference between Hilbert and Bernays will shown to be found in the problem of the uniformity of the axiomatic method. In the same vein, we will discuss the later Bernays’ criticism of Carnap, for Carnap’s project of philosophy of science in the late 1950s seems to be a continuation and an extension of Hilbert’s faith in the uniformity of the axiomatic method.

An earlier version was published in Korean as Park (2011).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Parsons (2006) is a research done in connection with the publication project of the English translation of Bernays’ work. Feferman (2008) can be counted as a study based on the publication of Collected Papers of Gödel, especially his correspondences (Vols. 4 and 5).

  2. 2.

    Corry claims that the expression “assistant” is somewhat misleading (Corry 2004, p. 70).

  3. 3.

    For example, see Specker (1979, p. 385), Zach (1999, pp. 344–345). Zach not only claims that Hilbert and Bernays (1934, 1939) was essentially written by Bernays alone, but also that even in their early collaboration (1917–1918) Bernays contributed at least equally as Hilbert.

  4. 4.

    According to Specker (1979), which is a very brief biography of Bernays, in 1912 Bernays received a doctoral degree for his study on the theory of numbers under the supervision of Landau at Göttingen. And, in the same year he acquired a license for professorship with his study on the theory of function under Zermelo at the University of Zürich. On Hilbert’s invitation, he moved to Göttingen, and received once more the license for professorship with his work on logic. But, when he was an undergraduate student at Berlin, he learned physics from Plank at Berlin, and from Born at Göttingen. On the other hand, he learned philosophy from Riehl, Stumpf, and Cassirer at Berlin, and from Nelson at at Göttingen. Under the influence of Lelson, who was one of the center figures of neo-Friesianism, Bernays wrote a paper on moral philosophies of Sidgwick and Kant in the 1910’s. Bernays’ background in physics, there are useful and important pieces of information in Corry (2004, pp. 295–296). Bernays was deeply involved in mathematical physics and the foundational issues related to it, publishing Bernays (1913). Also, he lectured on gas theory up to 1920 at Göttingen. We cannot simply bypass Corry’s observation that there is an interesting parallel between Zermelo and Bernays in that both showed a transition of interest from mathematical physics to foundations of mathematics.

  5. 5.

    I have in mind the Collected works of Gödel, Zermelo, Carnap, Hilbert-Bernays project, and Bernays project.

  6. 6.

    Parsons (2006) takes 1945 as the starting point for the later Bernays. That seems to be a very safe choice that allows at least 6 years from the period of collaboration with Hilbert. However, such a choice could be a too safe one, since there is virtually an unanimous agreement that the true author of Hilbert and Bernays (1934, 1939) was Bernays. We need to trace the beginning of the period of the later Bernays back to sometime after 1934 when Bernays was expelled to Zürich by Nazis, especially when he was attracted to Ginseth’s thought. For the purpose of this paper, this problem may be ignored.

  7. 7.

    For a detailed study of the examples Hilbert used for deepening the foundations, see Stöltzner (2002, 2003), for he classifies the examples of deepening the foundations in individual sciences suggested by Hilbert (1918) into eight different types. See also Park (2008, pp. 17–23).

  8. 8.

    For example, we have a report of very suggestive episode in Specker (1979, p. 383).

  9. 9.

    The interpretation that counts securing the autonomy of mathematics as the central motivation for Hilbert’s thought has been recently emphasized by Franks (2009). It seems important that Bernays mentioned this point.

  10. 10.

    Hallett also emphasizes the following points. Contrary to the standard view about the axiomatic system before Hilbert, axioms are no longer true in Hilbert. Furthermore, they are not even judgments that can be either true or false. Even the entire axiom system does not express the truth (Hallett 1995, p. 137). Hallett thinks that such a disagreement over whether axioms can have truth values ultimately originates from the disagreement over the status of axioms. In case we assume that axioms are true, since they must be truths about the primitive concepts that appear in the axioms, a universal logic that can determine the primitive concepts would be pursued. On the other hand, if we reject the assumption that axioms are true, there would be no need for invoking primitive concepts before developing a theory (Hallett 1995, p. 141).

  11. 11.

    I discuss the problem of implicit definition in Park (2008). See also Chun (2008), Choi (2007). It is Schlick who made this problem famous, and Friedman discusses it in several writings (see, especially Friedman 1992, 1999). However, interestingly enough, Majer underestimates this problem as subsidiary (Majer 2001, 2002). See also Park (2012). We may continue our interest by turning to Frege/Hilbert controversy. See Choi (2009). For the position of Bernays himself, we need to read Bernays (1942). Usually, based on this review, we say that Frege/Hilbert controversy has not been concluded once and for all.

  12. 12.

    Park (2012) intends to question whether Friedman’s discussion of implicit definition was fair to Hilbert’s axiomatic method. See Friedman (1992, 1994, 1999, 2001, 2002, 2008, 2011).

  13. 13.

    For example, Majer claims that the widespread view that Hilbert separated himself from Euclid’s axiomatic approach, and aimed at an entirely new axiomatics must be wrong (Majer 2006, p. 158).

  14. 14.

    It is interesting that there is Bernays (1922b) among his writings.

  15. 15.

    Parsons also complains about Bernays’ essay style of writing, which lacks systematic approach. Further, he thinks that Bernays’ discretion in discussing different positions and his loyalty to those he had close friendship tend to make his position as close to syncretism (Parsons 2006, p. 148).

  16. 16.

    Above all, Parsons seems to discuss Bernays’ anti-foundationalist position by assuming that Hilbert’s studies in foundations of mathematics at least indirectly makes him a foundationalist. However, the recent study of Franks shows persuasively that there are notably anti-foundationalist elements in Hilbert himself (see Franks 2009, pp. 32–40). The problem of the critique of a priori knowledge is an old problem that provoked in-depth discussion for a long time within the Hilbert school. It shows much more complex modes than one might think. However, if we have in mind Nelson’s criticism of Hilbert, and Bernays’ rebuttal, there is no doubt that there are almost insurmountable difficulties in contrasting Hilbert and Bernays through this problem (see Bernays 1928). The case of structuralism no doubt shows affinities not only with Bernays but also with Hilbert. In fact, many mathematical structuralists of our time trace their views back to Hilbert. Thus, here again it is difficult to highlight the differences between Hilbert and Bernays.

  17. 17.

    The prime examples of this project are Carnap (1956, 1958/1975, 1959/2000), and they were discussed by Carnap (1966/1974) in sufficiently detailed fashion. Carnap (1961) must be extremely important for understanding the relationship between Hilbert and Carnap. Friedman (1992) views Carnap’s later project in philosophy of science was already budding in Carnap (1934, 1939). See Friedman (2008, 2011) for how later Carnap expanded the idea of Ramsey sentence by the impetus from Hempel.

References

  • Bernays, P. (1913). Über die Bedenklichkeiten der neueren Relativitätstheorie. Abhandlungen der Fries’schen Schule, IV(3), 459–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1922a). Die BedeutungHilbertsfṻr die Philosophie der Mathematik. Die Naturwissenschaften 10, 93–99 (English translation as Hilbert’s Significance for the Philosophy of Mathematics 189–197, in Mancosu (1998a)).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1922b). Zur mathematischen Grundlegung der kinetischen Gastheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 85, 242–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1928). Uber Nelsons Stellungnahme in der Philosophie der Mathematik. Die Naturwissenschaften, 16, 142–45 (On Nelson’s Position in the Philosophy of Mathematics, Bernays Project: Text No. 7).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1942). Review of Max Steck, ‘Einunbekannter Brief von Gottlob Gregeṻber Hilbertserste Vorlesungṻber die Grundlagen der Geometrie. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7(2), 92–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1961). Zur Rolloe der Sprache in erkenntnistheoretischer Hisicht. Synthese, 13, 185–200 (On the Role of Language from an Epistemological Point of View. Bernays Project: Text No. 25).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1967). Scope and limits of axiomatics. In M. Bunge (Ed.), Lecture at the Delaware seminar in the foundations of physics (pp. 188–191). Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beth, E. (1963). Carnap’s views on the advantages of constructed systems over natural languages in analytic philosophy. In Schillp (Ed.) (pp. 469–502).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohnert, H. G. (1975). Carnap’s logicism. In Hintikka (Ed.) (pp. 183–216).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1934/1937). The logical syntax of language. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. I: The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1958/1975). Observational language and theoretical language (pp. 75–85). In J. Hintikka (Ed.) (1975) (Translated by H. G. Bohnert from Dialectica, 12(1958), pp. 236–248).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1959/2000). Theoretical concepts in science in Psillos (2000) (pp. 158–172).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1961). On the use of Hilbert’s e-operator in scientific theories. In Y. Bar-Hillel, et al. (Eds.), Essays on the foundations of mathematics (pp. 156–164). Jerusalem: The Magnus Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Replies and systematic expositions, in Schillp (1963) (pp. 859–1013).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1966/1974). An introduction to the philosophy of science. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, W. (2007). Hume’s principle and implicit definition. Korean Journal of Logic, 102, 23–46. (in Korean).

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, W. (2009). Frege-Hilbert controversy about existence and consistency. Philosophy, 99, 127–148. (in Korean).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chu, Y. S. (2008). Hilbert and Carnap in the theory of space. Korean Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 11, 1–134. (in Korean).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chun, Y. S. (2008). Hilbert and Carnap on the theory of space, Korean Journal for the Philosophy of Science,, 11, 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (2004). David Hilbert and the axiomatization of physics (1898–1918). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. (2008). Lieber Herr Bernays!, Lieber Herr Gödel! Gödel on finitism, constructivity, and Hilbert’s program. Dialectica, 62(2), 179–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franks, C. (2009). The autonomy of mathematical knowledge: Hilbert’s program revisited. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1992). Carnap and a priori truth. In D. Bell & W. Vossenkuhl (Eds.) (pp. 47–60).

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1994). Geometry, convention, and the relativized A priori. In W. Salmon & G. Wolters (Eds.) (pp. 21–34) (Reprinted in Friedman (1999), Chap. 3, pp. 59–70).

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1999). Reconsidering logical positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2001). Dynamics of reason. Stanford, California: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2002). Geometry as a branch of physics: Background and context for Einstein’s ‘geometry and experience’. In D. B. Malament (Eds.) (pp. 193–229).

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2008). Wissenschaftslogik: The role of logic in the philosophy of science. Synthese, 164, 385–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2011). Carnap on theoretical terms: Structuralism without metaphysics. Synthese, 180, 249–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallett, M. (1995). Hilbert and logic. In M. Marion & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), Quebec studies in the philosophy of science, Part I (pp. 135–187). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1899/1990). Grundlagen der Geometrie, Teubner, Leibzig (English Translation of the Tenth German edition, Foundations of Geometry, LaSalle: Open Court).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1900). Ueber den Zahlbegriff. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, 8, 180–184. (English translation in Ewald (1996), pp. 1089–1096).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1905). Ueber die Grundlagen der Logik und der Arithmetik. In A. Krazer, (Ed.) Verhandlungen des dritten Internationalen Mathematiker-Kongresses in Heidelberg vom 8. bis 13. August 1904 (pp. 174–85). Leipzig: Teubner (English translation in van Heijenoort (1967), pp. 129–38).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1918). AxiomatischesDenken. MathematischeAnnalen, 78, 405–415. Lecture given at the Swiss Society of Mathematicians, 11 September 1917 (English translation in Ewald (1996), pp. 1105–1115).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1930). Naturerkennen und Logik. Die Naturwissenschaften, 18, 959–963 (English translation in Ewald (1996), pp. 1157–1165).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1934). Grundlagen der Mathematik (Vol. 1). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1939). Grundlagen der Mathematik (Vol. 2). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (Ed.). (1975). Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majer, U. (2001). The axiomatic method and the foundations of science: Historical roots of mathematical physics in Göttingen (1900–1930). In M. Redei & M. Stöltzner (Eds.) (pp. 11–33).

    Google Scholar 

  • Majer, U. (2002). Hilbert’s program to axiomatize physics (in analogy to geometry) and its impact on Schlick, Carnap and other members of the Vienna Circle. In Heidelberger and F. Stadler (Eds.) (pp. 213–224).

    Google Scholar 

  • Majer, U. (2006). Hilbert’s axiomatic approach to the foundations of science—a failed research program? In V. F. Hendricks (2006) (pp. 155–184).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (Ed.). (1998a). From Brouwer to Hilbert. The debate on the foundations of mathematics in the 1920s. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (1998b). Hilbert and Bernays on metamathematics. In P. Mancosu (Ed.) (1998a) (pp. 149–188).

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2008). Zermelo and the axiomatic method. Korean Journal of Logic, 11–2, 1–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2011). Bernays and the axiomatic method. Korean Journal of Logic, 14(2), 1–37. (in Korean).

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2012). Friedman on implicit definition: In search of the Hilbertian heritage in philosophy of science. Erkenntnis, 76(3), 427–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, C. (2006), Paul Bernays’ Later philosophy of mathematics. Logic colloquium 2005. In C. Dimitracopoulos et al. (Eds.), Lecture Notes in Logic 28. Associations for Symbolic Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, C. (1996). Hilbert. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schilpp, P. A. (Ed.). (1963). The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Specker, E. (1979). Paul Bernays, Logic colloquium 78. In M. Boffa et al. (Eds.). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöltzner, M. (2002). How metaphysical is deepening the foundations? Hahn and Frank on Hilbert’s axiomatic method. In M. Heidelberger & F. Stadler (Eds.) (pp. 245–262).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöltzner, M. (2003). The principle of least action as the logical empiricist’s Shibboleth. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, 285–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1985). Axiomatic versus constructive procedures in mathematics. In T. Tonietti (Ed.), The mathematical intelligencer, 7(4), 10–17 and 38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zach, R. (1999). Completeness before post: Bernays, Hilbert, and the development of propositional logic. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 5(3), 331–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Woosuk Park .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Park, W. (2018). Between Bernays and Carnap. In: Philosophy's Loss of Logic to Mathematics. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 43. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95147-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics