Skip to main content

Necrocracy or Democracy? Assessing Objections to Constitutional Unamendability

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
An Unamendable Constitution?

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 68))

Abstract

Unamendability is a growing trend in global constitutionalism. Yet, unamendability, as a constitutional mechanism, raises various challenges and objections. Mainly, by perpetuating certain constitutional rules, values and institutions, unamendability exacerbates the ‘dead hand’ of the past, and by restricting all constitutional possibilities available to the people to revise their constitution, unamendability is seen as undemocratic and dangerous as it encourages extra-constitutional and revolutionary means in over to modify unamendable principles. Furthermore, the judicial enforcement of unamendability grants courts vast powers over other governmental branches, turning the judiciary into the final arbitrator of society’s values. This chapter identifies and analyses the main theoretical, practical and textual challenges to unamendability. It demonstrates that unamendability is a complex mechanism which ought to be applied with great care. Yet, it also argues that if the theory of unamendability is correctly construed as a mechanism which reserves a constitutional space for the decision-making of ‘the people’ in their capacity as holders of the primary constituent power (in contrast with the limited amendment power), this mitigates many of the challenges raised by unamendability.

An earlier version of this chapter was presented at the Koç-BC-Icon·S Workshop on Unamendable Constitutional Provisions held at Koç University Law School on 9 June 2015. I would like to thank the organisers of the workshop—Bertil Emrah Oder and Richard Albert and the participants for their valuable comments, especially to Serkan Köybaşi for his discussion. I would also like to thank Martin Loughlin, Thomas Poole, Ida Koivisto and the anonymous reviewer for useful remarks. An elaborated argument appears in Yaniv Roznai, Unconstitutional Constitutional AmendmentThe Limits of Amendment Powers (OUP 2017).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Albert (2008), pp. 37–44. Unamendability can also be informal when the social or political climate is such that although legally permissible, it is unimaginable that political or public agreement on amending certain constitutional subjects would be achieved. See Albert (2014a), p. 181, (2014b), pp. 1029, 1043. Likewise, unamendability can be ‘covert’, especially in politically enforced constitutions, when there is a convention that certain constitutional arrangements shall not be abolished or significantly altered; a convention which is enforced through disobedience of governmental branches, including the courts. See Geertjes and Uzman (this volume).

  2. 2.

    See Roznai (2013b), p. 557. Whereas unamendability can limit the constitutional amendment power, it cannot limit the primary constituent power which is unbound by prior constitutional rules. See Roznai (2017b), p. 23. This of course does not mean that the primary constituent power is unbound by any restrictions. See e.g., Widner and Contiades (2013), pp. 57, 58 (‘Today, the prevailing view is that there are implicit substantive limits built into the concept of constituent power…’).

  3. 3.

    See Roznai (2015), p. 775.

  4. 4.

    Roznai (2012), p. 240.

  5. 5.

    See Roznai (2013c), p. 657, Roznai and Yolcu (2012), p. 175, Roznai (2014b), p. 29.

  6. 6.

    Roznai (2017c), p. 5, see also Cahill (2016), pp. 245, 249–258 (argues that unamendability exists not only to defend specific content but also to defend the constituent power). A brief review of this distinction as the basis for unamendability appears in Yap (2015), pp. 114, 116–118. This distinction raises its own complications such as how do we recognise a genuine expression of primary constituent power? And where do we draw the line between amending a constitution and its replacement? These challenges are beyond the limited scope of this chapter which focuses on the main objections to unamendability. For an analytical description of the separation between primary and secondary constituent powers see also Köybaşi (this volume). Indeed, not everyone accept the distinction between primary and secondary constituent power. For example, Loughlin (2014), pp. 218, 231–232 argues that in light of the reflexive and relational nature of constituent power, this distinction is flawed. However, this is still the best explanatory theory for the constitutional phenomenon of unamendability, and therefore it is this premise for the analysis in this chapter.

  7. 7.

    Griffin (2007), p. 49.

  8. 8.

    See e.g., Amar (1988), pp. 1043, 1054–1058, Harris (1993), pp. 167, 193.

  9. 9.

    Albert (2008), pp. 47–48.

  10. 10.

    Albert (2010), pp. 663, 698.

  11. 11.

    Albert (2015), p. 655.

  12. 12.

    Sapir (2010), pp. 178–179.

  13. 13.

    On this problem, see e.g. Ely (1980), p. 11, Klarman (1997), pp. 381, 382, McConnell (1998), pp. 1127–1128, Samaha (2008), p. 606.

  14. 14.

    Sager (19951996), p. 275, Pettys (2008), pp. 313, 332.

  15. 15.

    Albert (2010), p. 667.

  16. 16.

    For an analytical elaboration of the people’s role in the French amendment process, see Derosier (2017), p. 315.

  17. 17.

    In a famous correspondence between James Madison and Thomas Jefferson from 6 September 1789, Jefferson argued that constitutions should be rewritten every generation, declaring that the dead should not govern the living, since ‘the earth belongs always to the living generation’. For an analysis, see Rubenfeld (19971998), p. 1085. In contrast, in Federalist No. 49, Madison contended that frequent ‘recurrence to the people’ would endanger ‘the public tranquillity by interesting too strongly the public passions’ and ‘deprive the government of that veneration which time bestows’ and on which every government depends for stability. See Hamilton et al. (1817), pp. 233, 274.

  18. 18.

    Paine and Philp (1998), pp. 91–92 (‘every age and generation must be as free to act for itself … [I]t is the living, and not the dead, that are to be accommodated’).

  19. 19.

    Fombad (2007), pp. 27, 57–58.

  20. 20.

    Mulford (1870), p. 155.

  21. 21.

    See Linder (1981), p. 717.

  22. 22.

    See Elster (2000), p. 102.

  23. 23.

    See debate in Da Silva (2004), pp. 454, 456–458, Smith (2011), pp. 369, 375, Tribe (2000), pp. 111–114, Orfield (1942), p. 85.

  24. 24.

    See e.g. Joseph and Walker (1987), pp. 155, 159.

  25. 25.

    On this maxim see Singh (1966), p. 273.

  26. 26.

    See Roznai (2014a), see also Mazzone (2005), pp. 1747, 1818, Klein (1999), pp. 31, 37–38, Albert (2014a), 209–215.

  27. 27.

    See Roznai (2017b).

  28. 28.

    Jackson (2013), p. 47. See also Goerlich (2008), pp. 397, 404, Hutchinson and Colón-Ríos (2011), p. 43.

  29. 29.

    Compare with Eisgruber (1997), pp. 1611, 1616.

  30. 30.

    Mazzone (2005), p. 1843. Moreover, when considering the fact that a national constitution’s median lifespan is a mere 19 years, any arguments regarding unamendability as binding future generations to the ‘dead hand of the past’ are relaxed. On the lifespan of constitutions, see Elkins et al. (2009), p. 129.

  31. 31.

    Michel and Cofone (this volume). The authors give as an example for the high costs of constitution-making bargaining the failed constitution-making process in Turkey as described in Yegen (this volume).

  32. 32.

    On the constitution as a means for ensuring respect-worthiness in the legal system, see e.g. Balkin (2003), pp. 485, 486. Of course, Balkin himself acknowledges that ‘The legitimacy of the constitutional/legal system … is not simply a matter of its current content. It is always imbricated with the past and projected toward the future. It is always premised on an interpretation of and selective identification with the past, the creation of a transtemporal “us,” whom we revere and of whom our present selves are merely the latest installment’. This idea of a transtemporal people actually supports unamendability which seeks to protect a certain constitutional identity superior to the present temporary political majority. In other words, unamendability seems compatible with the transcendental understanding of primary constituent power, which aims to link diverse generations and unite the nation under common basic principles. It invites the people to see themselves as part of something greater than their individuals—having a superior unamendable constitutional identity.

  33. 33.

    For such claims of inconsistency, see Orfield (19291930), pp. 550, 581, McGovney (1920), pp. 499, 511–513, Albert (2010), p. 676.

  34. 34.

    Ingham (19281929), pp. 161, 165–166.

  35. 35.

    Case No U-5/04 Request of Mr Sulejman Tihić, Decision of 31 March 2006 http://www.codices.coe.int/NXT/gateway.dll/CODICES/full/eur/bih/eng/bih-2006-1-003, Case No U-13/05, Request of Mr Sulejman Tihić, Decision of 26 May 2006 http://www.codices.coe.int/NXT/gateway.dll/CODICES/full/eur/bih/eng/bih-2006-2-005. Accessed 14 August 2016. See Feldman (2011), pp. 117, 142–144, (2012), pp. 151, 164. Contrary to the Constitutional Court, the European Court of Human Rights held that it has the jurisdiction to decide upon the issue, and that the abovementioned constitutional provision is discriminatory and constitutes a breach of the European Convention of Human Rights. See Sejdić and Finci v. Bosnia and Herzegovina, App. No. 27996/06, Eur. Ct. H. R., Judgment of Dec. 22, 2009. See e.g., Bardutzky (2010), p. 309.

  36. 36.

    Re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South-Africa, 1996(4) SALR 744. See Sachs (19961997), p. 1249.

  37. 37.

    Suksi (1995), p. 6.

  38. 38.

    Beaud (1994), p. 345.

  39. 39.

    See e.g., Roznai and Suteu (2015), p. 542.

  40. 40.

    Albert (2016), p. 13.

  41. 41.

    Bernal (2013), pp. 339, 349.

  42. 42.

    Schwartzberg (2009), p. 2.

  43. 43.

    Albert (2010), p. 667.

  44. 44.

    Nogueira (2005), pp. 79, 84.

  45. 45.

    Earlier thoughts appeared in Roznai (2013a).

  46. 46.

    Dworkin (1990), pp. 14, 35, (1995), p. 2, Barak (2009), pp. 23–26, Rostow (1952), pp. 193, 195, Bishin (19771978), p. 1099, Michelman (1998), pp. 399, 419.

  47. 47.

    Rousseau (1994), pp. 261, 273–282.

  48. 48.

    Mohallem (2011), pp. 765, 766–767. Therefore, Oran Doyle argues that ‘The further that a constraint moves power away from a contemporary majority, the stronger the justification that is needed’. See Doyle (2017), p. 73.

  49. 49.

    Albert (2010), p. 675.

  50. 50.

    Cf. Holmes (1993), pp. 195, 239. Especially in weak democracies, judicial review of constitutional amendments may strengthen democracy from collapsing into autocracy rather than be deemed undemocratic. See Issacharoff (2012), pp. 33, 45.

  51. 51.

    See e.g., McIlwain (1975), p. 132.

  52. 52.

    Roznai (2017c), Keshavamurthy (1982), p. 89.

  53. 53.

    For example, art. 288(e) Const. (1976) (Portugal) entrenches ‘The rights of the workers, workers’ committees, and trade unions’.

  54. 54.

    See e.g., Christopher Bryant (2003), p. 501, Brandon (1995), see also Albert (2013b) (arguing that another way of reading the Corwin Amendment is not as making slavery absolutely unamendable but only as restricting congressional power).

  55. 55.

    Michel and Cofone (this volume).

  56. 56.

    See Masri (this volume).

  57. 57.

    For example, the unamendable provision which was inserted in the Constitution of Bangladesh is extremely broad as it protects nearly third of the constitution (the preamble, all fundamental rights provisions and ‘the provisions of articles relating to the basic structure’) from any amendment. See Hoque (this volume).

  58. 58.

    Sapir (2010), p. 79.

  59. 59.

    Tushnet (2018), p. 332.

  60. 60.

    See generally Bickel (1962), pp. 16–23.

  61. 61.

    O’Connell (1999), pp. 48, 51. Of course, at least with regard to explicit unamendable provisions, Michel Rosenfeld was right to state that ‘any countermajoritarian difficulty would have to be ascribed to the constitution itself rather to judicial interpretation’. See Rosenfeld (2005), pp. 165, 186.

  62. 62.

    Cf Freeman (19901991), pp. 327, 353–354 and echoing Hamilton (1817), pp. 418, 421.

  63. 63.

    I elaborate on this point in Roznai (2017c).

  64. 64.

    See Fombad (2007), p. 57, Friedrich (1968), pp. 138, 143–146, Suber (1999), pp. 31–32, Tushnet (20122013), pp. 1983, 2007.

  65. 65.

    Albert (2010), pp. 684–685.

  66. 66.

    Mendes (2005), pp. 449, 461, 721.

  67. 67.

    Vanossi (2000), p. 188.

  68. 68.

    Elster (2000), pp. 95–6.

  69. 69.

    See Friedman (2011), pp. 77, 93–96.

  70. 70.

    Linder (1981), p. 723. As Tushnet (20122013) 2007 suggests, ‘perhaps constitutional theory should treat an unconstitutional amendment as a pro tanto exercise of the right to revolution through the form of law, a form that allows fundamental change to occur without violence’; See also Tushnet (2015), pp. 639, 642–643.

  71. 71.

    See, on this, Roznai (2017b); Roznai (2017a).

  72. 72.

    Lawrence Lowell (1918), p. 103.

  73. 73.

    Akzin (1967), pp. 1, 12.

  74. 74.

    Tushnet (20122013), p. 2007.

  75. 75.

    Roznai and Suteu (2015).

  76. 76.

    Akzin (1956), pp. 313, 332. See also Vile (19901991), pp. 271, 295: ‘No mere parchment barrier can prevent the people from exercising the right to propose a new constitution if sufficient numbers insist upon doing so and have the necessary power to back up their demands’.

  77. 77.

    Arendt (2006), p. 142.

  78. 78.

    Roel (1968), pp. 251, 256–259, Moses (1891), pp. 1, 4.

  79. 79.

    Spiliotopoulos (1983), pp. 463, 466–467.

  80. 80.

    Muñiz-Fraticelli (2009), pp. 379–380.

  81. 81.

    Murphy (1992), pp. 337, 348.

  82. 82.

    On sham constitutions, see recently Law and Versteeg (2013), p. 863.

  83. 83.

    Pilpilidis (this volume).

  84. 84.

    Maia (2000), pp. 54, 60.

  85. 85.

    See e.g. Wright (1994), pp. 35, 72.

  86. 86.

    See e.g., Tribe (1983), pp. 433, 440–443, Ingham (19281929), p. 168.

  87. 87.

    See e.g. Smith (2011), p. 369.

  88. 88.

    See e.g. French Constitutional Council No. 2003-469DC, March 26, 2003; Wright (2005), p. 495, Baranger (2011), pp. 389, 396.

  89. 89.

    Ibid., p. 398.

  90. 90.

    Pakistan Lawyers Forum v. Federation of Pakistan, repored as PLD 2005 SC 719; Conrad (2003), pp. 186, 192.

  91. 91.

    Vile (1995), pp. 191, 198–199.

  92. 92.

    Zweig (1909), p. 324.

  93. 93.

    Roznai (2017c), Roznai and Suteu (2015).

  94. 94.

    Lowernstein (1972), pp. 180–181.

  95. 95.

    Conrad (1970), pp. 380, 394.

  96. 96.

    Fox and Nolte (1995), pp. 1, 19.

  97. 97.

    Ackerman (1993), pp. 20–21.

  98. 98.

    Schwartzberg (2009), pp. 3, 22, 184–189.

  99. 99.

    Mohallem (2011), p. 781.

  100. 100.

    Schwartzberg (2009), pp. 15–16, Landau (2013), p. 189.

  101. 101.

    Madhava Menon (2006), pp. 59, 137, 138.

  102. 102.

    Mohallem (2011), p. 766.

  103. 103.

    See Dixon (2011), pp. 96, 98, Sweet (2000), p. 89, Yap (20062007), pp. 99, 104–105, Dellinger (19831984), pp. 386, 414–415, Comella (2009), pp. 104–107, Kyvig (1996), p. 106. On how constitutional amendments are used in order to nullify effects of courts’ judgments in India see Chandrachud (this volume).

  104. 104.

    Vedel (1992), p. 173, cited in Troper (2003), pp. 99, 113, Baranger (2011), p. 407. On ‘lit de justice’ see Radin (19341935), pp. 112, 115.

  105. 105.

    Tribe (1983), pp. 442–443.

  106. 106.

    Ponthoreau and Ziller (2002), pp. 119, 140.

  107. 107.

    See Roznai (2014b), pp. 38–40. Cf Yap (2015), p. 132 (argues that in easily amended constitutions, ‘judges may interfere with the substance of the amendment only when its passage would substantially destroy the pre-existing constitution, i.e. the constitutional change in question must be manifestly unreasonable’.).

  108. 108.

    Dellinger (19831984), pp. 414–416.

  109. 109.

    Roznai (2017b).

  110. 110.

    Baranger (2011), p. 414. Even in Hungary, where the constitution explicitly prohibits the constitutional court from conducting a substantive judicial review of amendments, the Hungarian Constitutional Court has emphasised in decision 12/2013 that as guardian of the constitution, it will continue to interpret and apply the Fundamental Law as a ‘coherent system’, which might lead to a ‘de facto substantive review of constitutional amendments’. See Gárdos-Orosz (this volume).

  111. 111.

    Otto Pfersmann describes provisions that were given a different meaning from what they actually mean (because otherwise they would be invalidated by the court) as ‘norms without texts’. See Pfersmann (2009), pp. 81, 88. Of course, such application of interpretation may conflict with principles of legal certainty and separation of powers. See Tobisch (2011), pp. 424, 427.

  112. 112.

    Landfried (1988), p. 154.

  113. 113.

    Kyvig (2000), pp. 9, 10 (arguing that ‘removing an amendment from the constitution requires the same supermajority approval as its initial adoption, thus a reversal of political sentiment of enormous magnitude’).

  114. 114.

    Baranger (2011), p. 421.

  115. 115.

    Opsahl (19911992), pp. 181, 185–186.

  116. 116.

    See Rosenfeld (19941995), p. 1049, Jacobsohn (2006), pp. 361, 363, Jacobsohn (2010a), pp. 133, 335, Jacobsohn (2010b), p. 47.

  117. 117.

    Gören (2009), pp. 1, 12–13.

  118. 118.

    Abraham (2000), pp. 195, 204, Issacharoff (2012), p. 45, Stith (1996), pp. 65–66.

  119. 119.

    McGovney (1920), p. 514. See also Orfield (1942), p. 108.

  120. 120.

    Gözler (2008), pp. 69–71.

  121. 121.

    Schweber (2007), p. 137, Kay (1997), pp. 161, 163, Yap (2015), pp. 118–120.

  122. 122.

    Murphy (1995), pp. 163, 177. See also Murphy (1992), p. 14.

  123. 123.

    Murphy (1987), pp. 1, 12–13.

  124. 124.

    Cf, Child (1926), pp. 27, 28, Machen (19091910), pp. 169–170, Morris (1909), pp. 82, 85, Marbury (19191920), pp. 223, 225, Holding (1923), pp. 481, 487, Schaffner (2005), pp. 1487, 1493, Han (2010), pp. 71, 82, Murphy (2007), p. 506.

  125. 125.

    Barber (1984), p. 43.

  126. 126.

    See, for example, Davis (1881), p. 197; Livermore v. Waite, 36 P. 424,426 (Cal. 1894); and the briefs presented before the U.S. Supreme Court against the validity of the 18th Amendment (see Dodd (1921), pp. 321, 330–332).

  127. 127.

    Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala, AIR 1973 SC 1461 (J. Khanna at 1426-7).

  128. 128.

    Anwar Hossain Chowdhury v. Bangladesh, 41 DLR 1989 App. Div. 165 (Judge B.H. Chowdhury, para 196; Shahabuddin, J, id., at paras. 336, 417).

  129. 129.

    Cf Yap (2015), p. 121 (‘in such instances where the constitution explicitly authorizes the repeal of any of its provisions via the amendment process, the textual argument in favour of giving a narrow reading to the word “amend” loses its force’).

  130. 130.

    Schmitt (2008), p. 152.

  131. 131.

    Borucka-Arctowa (1991), pp. 79, 80.

  132. 132.

    Murphy (1992), pp. 351–352. See also Nielsen (1979), pp. 155, 157.

  133. 133.

    Dhamija (2007), p. 223.

  134. 134.

    The rejection of the Indian basic structure doctrine in Singapore was based upon this argument. See Teo Soh Lung v. The Minister for Home Affairs [1989] 2M.L.J. 449, 456–457.

  135. 135.

    See Pillsbury (1909), pp. 741, 742–743, Williams (1928), pp. 529, 544, Orfield (1942), pp. 115–116, Orfield (19291930), pp. 553–555; Linder (1981), p. 730, Da Silva (2004), p. 459.

  136. 136.

    Vile (1985), pp. 373, 383.

  137. 137.

    Yeaman (1871), pp. 710–711.

  138. 138.

    Dow (19901991), p. 1, Dow (1995), p. 127. See also Baker (2000), pp. 1, 3.

  139. 139.

    Gözler (2008), p. 102.

  140. 140.

    Pfersmann (2012), pp. 81, 103.

  141. 141.

    Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala, AIR 1973 SC 1461, para 210.

  142. 142.

    Roznai (2017c), Keshavamurthy (1982), p. 51.

  143. 143.

    Conrad (1970), p. 379, Schmitt (2008), p. 152. Compare with Fleming (19941995), pp. 355, 366 (entrenchment of certain compromises should not deny unalienable rights held by the people).

  144. 144.

    Article 9 Const. (1961) (Turkey). See Olcay (this volume).

  145. 145.

    Turkish Constitutional Court, decision No 1965/40, 4 AMKD 290, 329 (26 September 1965) (obiter dicta), cited in Olcay (this volume). See also Gözler (2008), pp. 95–96, Yegen (this volume).

  146. 146.

    Turkish Constitutional Court, decision No 1970/37, 9 AMKD 416, 428–429 (3 April 1971), cited in Olcay (this volume) and Gözler (2008), pp. 96–97.

  147. 147.

    Art. 139 Const. (1947) (Italy).

  148. 148.

    See in Carrozza (2007), pp. 168, 174–175, Groppi (2012), pp. 203, 210, Galizzi (2000), pp. 235, 241, Fusaro (2011), pp. 211, 215, Comella (2009), p. 107.

  149. 149.

    Corte Const. judgment no. 1146 of Dec. 15, 1988, quoted in Del Duca and Del Duca (2006), pp. 799, 800–801.

  150. 150.

    Escarras (1993), pp. 105, 112–116; 117, 130–138, Scotti (this volume).

  151. 151.

    Hauriou (1923), p. 297 (my translation).

  152. 152.

    Burdeau (1930), pp. 78–83.

  153. 153.

    Burdeau (1983), pp. 231–232, quoted in Gözler (2008), p. 94 (my translation).

  154. 154.

    Williams (1928), p. 543.

  155. 155.

    As Black once wrote, ‘these are (in part at least) cartoon illustrations. But the cartoon accurately renders the de jure picture, and seems exaggerated only because we now conceive that at least some of these actions have no appeal to anybody’. See Black (1963), pp. 957, 959.

  156. 156.

    Roznai (2017c).

  157. 157.

    Cf., Judge Landau opinion in Israeli Supreme Court decision Yeredor v. Chairman, Central Election Committee for the Sixth Knesset, 19 P.D. 365. (1965). See Guberman (1967), pp. 455, 457. On this case, see Masri (this volume) at 9–10.

  158. 158.

    Harris (1993), p. 183.

  159. 159.

    Iyer (2003), pp. 1, 2. As Ringera J stated in the case which adopted the basic structure doctrine in Kenya: ‘Parliament has no power to and cannot in the guise or garb of amendment either change the basic features of the Constitution or abrogate and enact a new Constitution. In my humble view, a contrary interpretation would lead to a farcical and absurd spectacle’. See Njoya & Others v. Attorney General & Others, [2004] LLR 4788 (HCK), high Court of Kenya at Nairobu, 25 March 2004, para 61 http://www.chr.up.ac.za/index.php/browse-by-subject/336-kenya-njoya-and-others-v-attorney-general-and-others-2004-ahrlr-157-kehc-2004-.html.

  160. 160.

    Da Silva (2004), p. 459.

  161. 161.

    Orfield (1942), pp. 123–124.

  162. 162.

    I elaborate on this in Roznai (2017c).

  163. 163.

    Katz (19951996), pp. 251, 273, Lakshminath (1978), pp. 144, 159, Keshavamurthy (1982), p. 82, Sripati (1998), pp. 413, 480, Nahar and Dadoo (2008), pp. 559, 571.

  164. 164.

    Garlicki and Garlicka (2012), p. 185.

  165. 165.

    Michel and Cofone (this volume). On the expressive function of unamendability, see Albert (2013a), pp. 225, 254.

  166. 166.

    Pilpilidis (this volume), p. 21.

  167. 167.

    Hickory (17871788), pp. 138–139, 140–141, cited in Wood (1998), pp. 377, 379.

  168. 168.

    ‘Report on Constitutional Amendment’, European Commission for Democracy Through Law (Venice Commission), adopted by the Venice Commission at its 81st Plenary Session (Venice, Dec 11–12 2009) para 218 www.venice.coe.int/docs/2010/CDL-AD(2010)001-e.asp?PrintVersion=True&L=E#P768_153923. Accessed 14 August 2016.

References

  • Abraham M (2000) In: Andenas M (ed) Judicial role in constitutional amendments in India: the basic structure doctrine, pp 195, 204

    Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman B (1993) We the people: foundations. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 20–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Akzin B (1956) On the stability and reality of constitutions. Scripta Hierosolymitana 3:313, 332

    Google Scholar 

  • Akzin B (1967) The place of the constitution in the modern state. Isr Law Rev 2(1):1, 12

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2008) Counterconstitutionalism. Dalhousie Law J 31:1, 37–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2010) Constitutional handcuffs. Ariz State Law Rev 42:663, 698

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2013a) The expressive function of constitutional amendment rules. McGill Law J 59(2):225, 254

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2013b) The unamendable Corwin amendment (27.02.2013). Available via ICONnect. www.iconnectblog.com/2013/02/the-unamendable-corwin-amendment

  • Albert R (2014a) Constructive unamendability in Canada and the United States. Supreme Court Law Rev 67:181

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2014b) Constitutional disuse or desuetude. Boston Univ Law Rev 94:1029, 1043

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2015) Amending constitutional amendment rules. Int J Const Law 13(3):655

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert R (2016) The unamendable core of the United States constitution. In: Koltay A (ed) Comparative perspectives on the fundamental freedom of expression. Wolters Kluwer, Netherlands, p 13

    Google Scholar 

  • Amar AR (1988) Philadelphia revisited: amending the constitution outside article V. Univ Chicago Law Rev 55:1043, 1054–1058

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H (2006) [1963] On revolution, rev. edn. Penguin Classics, London, p 142

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker TE (2000) Towards a more perfect union: some thoughts on amending the constitution. Widener J Public Law 10:1, 3

    Google Scholar 

  • Balkin JM (2003) Respect-worthy: Frank Michelman and the legitimate constitution. Tulsa Law Rev 39:485, 486

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2009) The judge in a democracy. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 23–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Baranger D (2011) The language of eternity: constitutional review of the amending power in France (Or the absence thereof). Isr Law Rev 44(3):389, 396

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber SA (1984) On what the constitution means. Johns Hopkins University Press, USA, p 43

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardutzky S (2010) The Strasbourg court on the Dayton constitution: judgment in the case of Sejdić and Finci v. Bosnia and Herzegovina, 22 December 2009 (October 19, 2010). Eur Const Law Rev 6(2):309

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaud O (1994) La puissance de l’état. Presses Universitaires de France, France, p 345

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernal C (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments in the case study of Colombia: an analysis of the justification and meaning of the constitutional replacement doctrine. Int J Const Law 11:339, 349

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickel AM (1962) The least dangerous branch: the Supreme Court at the bar of politics. Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis, pp 16–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishin WR (1977–1978) Judicial review in democratic theory. South Calif Law Rev 50:1099

    Google Scholar 

  • Black CL Jr (1963) The proposed amendment of article V: a threatened disaster. Yale Law J 72:957, 959

    Google Scholar 

  • Borucka-Arctowa M (1991) Innovation and tradition against the background of revolutionary changes of law—a conceptual and functional analysis. In: Bankowski Z (ed) Revolutions in law and legal thought. Aberdeen University Press, Aberdeen, pp 79, 80

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon M (1995) The “Original” thirteenth amendment and the limits to formal constitutional change. In: Levinson S (ed) Responding to imperfection: the theory and practice of constitutional amendment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Burdeau G (1930) Essai d’une Théorie de la Révision des Lois Constitutionnelles en Droit Français. Thèse, Faculté de droit de Paris, pp 78–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Burdeau G (1983) Traite de Science Politique, 3rd édn. LGDJ, pp 231–232

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahill M (2016) Ever closer remoteness of the peoples of Europe? Limits on the power of amendment and national constituent power. Camb Law J 75(2):245, 249–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrozza P (2007) In: Loughlin M, Walker N (eds) Constitutionalism’s post-modern opening. pp 168, 174–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandrachud C (this volume) Constitutional falsehoods: the fourth judges case and the basic structure doctrine in India

    Google Scholar 

  • Child SR (1926) Revolutionary amendments to the constitution. Const Rev 10:27, 28

    Google Scholar 

  • Christopher Bryant A (2003) Stopping time: the pro-slavery and “irrevocable” thirteenth amendment. Harvard J Law Pub Policy 26:501

    Google Scholar 

  • Comella VF (2009) Constitutional courts & democratic values—a European perspective. Yale University Press, USA, pp 104–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad D (1970) Limitation of amendment procedures and the constituent power. Indian Yearb Int Aff 15–16:380, 394

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad D (2003) Basic structure of the constitution and constitutional principles. In: Sorabjee SJ (ed) Law and justice: an anthology. Universal Law Publishing, Uttar Pradesh, pp 186, 192

    Google Scholar 

  • Da Silva VA (2004) A fossilised constitution? Ratio Juris 17(4):454, 456–458

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis J (1881) The rise and fall of the confederate government. D. Appleton, USA, p 197

    Google Scholar 

  • Del Duca LF, Del Duca P (2006) An Italian federalism? the state, its institutions and national culture as rule of law guarantor. Am J Comp Law 54:799, 800–801

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellinger W (1983–1984) The legitimacy of constitutional change: rethinking the amendment process. Harvard Law Rev 97:386, 414–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Derosier JP (2017) In: Albert R, Contiades X, Fotiadou A (eds) The French people’s role in amending the constitution. p 315

    Google Scholar 

  • Dhamija A (2007) Need to amend a constitution and doctrine of basic features. Wadhwa, Nagpur, p 223

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon R (2011) Constitutional amendment rules: a comparative perspective. In: Ginsburg T, Dixon R (eds) Comparative constitutional law. Edward Elgar Publishing, UK, pp 96, 98

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd WF (1921) Amending the federal constitution. Yale Law J 30(4):321, 330–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow DR (1990–1991) When the words mean what we believe they say: the case of article V. Iowa Law Rev 76:1

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow DR (1995) In: Levinson S (ed) The plain meaning of article V. p 127

    Google Scholar 

  • Doyle O (2017) In: Albert R, Contiades X, Fotiadou A (eds) Constraints on constitutional amendment powers. p 73

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1990) A bill of rights for Britain. Chatto & Windus, UK, pp 14, 35

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1995) Constitutionalism and democracy. Eur J Philos 3(1):2

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisgruber CL (1997) The living hand of the past: history and constitutional justice. Fordham Law Rev 65:1611, 1616

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkins Z, Ginsburg T, Melton J (2009) The endurance of national constitutions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 129

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (2000) Ulysses unbound—studies in rationality, precommitment, and constraints. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 102

    Google Scholar 

  • Ely JH (1980) Democracy and distrust: a theory of judicial review. Harvard University Press, USA, p 11

    Google Scholar 

  • Escarras JC (1993) Presentation Du Rapport Italien De Massimo Luciani’ and Massimo Luciani, ‘La Revision Constituzionale in Italia’ in La Revision De La Constitution. Economica, pp 105, 112–116, 117, 130–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman D (2011) ‘“Which in your case you have not got”: constitutionalism at home and abroad’. Curr Legal Probl 64(1):117, 142–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman D (2012) The nature and effect of constitutional rights in post-conflict Bosnia and Herzegovina. In: Harvey C, Schwartz A (eds) Rights in divided societies. Hart Publishing, UK, pp 151, 164

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleming JE (1994–1995) We the exceptional American people. Const Comment 11:355, 366

    Google Scholar 

  • Fombad CM (2007) Limits on the power to amend constitutions: recent trends in Africa and their potential impact on constitutionalism. Univ Botswana Law J 6:27, 57–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox GH, Nolte G (1995) Intolerant democracies. Harvard Int Law J 36:1, 19

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman S (1990–1991) Constitutional democracy and the legitimacy of judicial review. Law Philos 9(4):327, 353–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman A (2011) Dead hand constitutionalism: the danger of eternity clauses in new democracies. Mexican Law Rev 4:77, 93–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedrich CJ (1968) Constitutional government and democracy—theory and practice in Europe and America, 4th edn. Blaisdell Publishing Company, New York, pp 138, 143–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusaro C (2011) ‘Italy’. In: Oliver D, Fusaro C (eds) How constitutions change—a comparative study. Hart Publishing, UK, pp 211, 215

    Google Scholar 

  • Galizzi P (2000) In: Andenas M (ed) Constitutional revisions and reforms: the Italian experience. pp 235, 241

    Google Scholar 

  • Gárdos-Orosz F (this volume) The role of non-amendable clauses in judicial review of constitutional amendments: theoretical considerations inspired by Hungarian Constitutional Court case law

    Google Scholar 

  • Garlicki L, Garlicka ZA (2012) Review of constitutionality of unconstitutional amendments (an imperfect response to imperfections?) Anayasa Hukuku Dergisi: J Const Law 1:185

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertjes GJ, Uzman J (this volume) Conventions of unamendability; unamendable constitutional law in politically enforced constitutions

    Google Scholar 

  • Goerlich H (2008) Concept of special protection for certain elements and principles of the constitution against amendments and article 79(3), Basic law of Germany. NUJS Law Rev 1:397, 404

    Google Scholar 

  • Gören Z (2009) Anayasa Koyan Erk Ve Anayasa - Değişikliklerinin Sinirlari’. İstanbul Ticaret Üniversitesi Sosyal Bilimler Dergisi 16:1, 12–13 [The constitution-making power and the limitations on constitutional amendments]. http://siyasaliletisim.org/pdf/anayasadegisikligi.pdf

  • Gözler K (2008) Judicial review of constitutional amendments—a comparative study. Ekin, Bursa, pp 69–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin SM (2007) Constituent power and constitutional change in American constitutionalism. In: Loughlin M, Walker N (eds) The paradox of constitutionalism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 49

    Google Scholar 

  • Groppi T (2012) Constitutional revision in Italy—a marginal instrument for constitutional change. In: Contiades X (ed) Engineering constitutional change: a comparative perspective on Europe, Canada and the USA. Routledge, London, pp 203, 210

    Google Scholar 

  • Guberman S (1967) Israel’s supra-constitution. Isr Law Rev 2:455, 457

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton A (1817) In: Hamilton A, Jay J, Madison J (eds) The federalist no. LXXVIII. pp 418, 421

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton A, Jay J, Madison J (1817) [1788] Federalist, on the new constitution. Benjamin Warner, Philadelphia, pp 233, 274

    Google Scholar 

  • Han WT (2010) Chain novels and amendments outside article V: a literary solution to a constitutional conundrum. Hamline Law Rev 33:71, 82

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris WF II (1993) The interpretable constitution. Johns Hopkins University Press, USA, pp 167, 193

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauriou M (1923) Precis de Droit Constitutionnel, 1st edn. Sirey, Paris, p 297 (my translation)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hickory G [Webster N] (1787–1788) Government. I Am Mag 138–139, 140–141

    Google Scholar 

  • Holding AM (1923) Perils to be apprehended from amending the constitution. Am Law Rev 57:481, 487

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes S (1993) Precommitment and the paradox of democracy. In: Elster J, Slagstad R (eds) Constitutionalism and democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 195, 239

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoque R (this volume) Eternal provisions in the constitution of Bangladesh: a constitution once and for all?

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson AC, Colón-Ríos J (2011) Democracy and constitutional change. Theoria 43

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingham JF (1928–1929) Unconstitutional amendments. Dickinson Law Rev 33:161, 165–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Issacharoff S (2012) In: Harvey C, Schwartz A (eds) Managing conflict through democracy. pp 33, 45

    Google Scholar 

  • Iyer K (2003) A constitutional miscellany, 2nd edn. Eastern Book Company, Uttar Pradesh, pp 1, 2

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson V (2013) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments: a window into constitutional theory and transnational constitutionalism. In: Wallrabenstein A, Dann P, Bäuerle M (eds) Demokratie-Perspektiven Festschrift für Brun-Otto Bryde zum 70, Mohr Siebeck, Germany, p 47

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsohn GJ (2006) Constitutional identity. Rev Politics 68:361, 363

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsohn GJ (2010a) Constitutional identity. Harvard University Press, USA, pp 133, 335

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsohn GJ (2010b) The disharmonic constitution. In: Tulis JK, Macedo S (eds) The limits of constitutional democracy. Princeton University Press, Princeton, p 47

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph PA, Walker GR (1987) A theory of constitutional change. Oxford J Legal Stud 7:155, 159

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz E (1995–1996) On amending constitutions: the legality and legitimacy of constitutional entrenchment. Columbia J Law Soc Probl 29:251, 273

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay RS (1997) Legal rhetoric and revolutionary change. Caribbean Law Rev 7:161, 163

    Google Scholar 

  • Keshavamurthy CV (1982) Amending power under the Indian constitution—basic structure limitations. Deep & Deep, New Delhi, p 89

    Google Scholar 

  • Klarman MJ (1997) Antifidelity. South Calif Law Rev 70:381, 382

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein C (1999) A propos constituent power: some general views in a modern context. In: Jyränki A (ed) National constitutions in the era of integration. Kluwer Law International, pp 31, 37–38

    Google Scholar 

  • Köybaşi S (this volume) Amending the unamendable: the case of article 20 of the German basic law

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyvig DE (1996) Appealing Supreme Court decisions: constitutional amendments as checks on judicial review. J Supreme Court Hist 21(2):106

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyvig DE (2000) Arranging for amendment: unintended outcome of constitutional design. In: Kyvig DE (ed) Unintended consequences of constitutional amendment. University of Georgia Press, USA, pp 9, 10

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakshminath A (1978) Justiciability of constitutional amendments. In: Dhavan R, Jacob A (eds) Indian constitution—trends and issues. N.M. Tripathi Private Ltd., Mumbai, pp 144, 159

    Google Scholar 

  • Landau D (2013) Abusive constitutionalism. UC Davis Law Rev 47(1):189

    Google Scholar 

  • Landfried C (1988) Constitutional review and legislation in the federal Republic of Germany. In: Landfried C (ed) Constitutional review and legislation: an international comparison. Nomos, Germany, p 154

    Google Scholar 

  • Law DS, Versteeg M (2013) Sham constitutions. Calif Law Rev 101(4):863

    Google Scholar 

  • Linder D (1981) What in the constitution cannot be amended? Ariz Law Rev 23:717

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowernstein K (1972) Constitutions, constitutional law. In: Kenig CD (ed) Marxism, communism, and western society: a comparative encyclopedia (Herder and Herder 1972), p 169

    Google Scholar 

  • Loughlin M (2014) The concept of constituent power. Eur J Polit Theor 13(2):218, 231–232

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowell L (1918) Greater European governments. Harvard University Press, USA, p 103

    Google Scholar 

  • Machen AW (1909–1910) Is the fifteenth amendment void? Harvard Law Rev 23:169–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Madhava Menon NR (2006) Basic structure: after 30 years’ and R.K.P, Shankardass, ‘anomalies of the ‘doctrine’’. In: Chopra P (ed) The Supreme Court versus the constitution: a challenge to federalism. Sage, USA, pp 59, 137, 138

    Google Scholar 

  • Maia L (2000) The creation and amending process in the Brazilian constitution. In: Andenas M (ed) The creation and amendment of constitutional norms. BIICL, London, pp 54, 60

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbury WL (1919–1920) The limitations upon the amending power. Harvard Law Rev 33:223, 225

    Google Scholar 

  • Masri M (this volume) Unamendability in Israel: a critical perspective

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazzone J (2005) Unamendments. Iowa Law Rev 90:1747, 1818

    Google Scholar 

  • McConnell MW (1998) Textualism and the dead hand of the past. Geo Wash Law Rev 60:1127–1128

    Google Scholar 

  • McGovney DO (1920) Is the eighteenth amendment void because of its contents? Columbia Law Rev 20:499, 511–513

    Google Scholar 

  • McIlwain CH (1975) Constitutionalism: ancient and modern. Liberty Fund Inc., Indianapolis, p 132

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendes CH (2005) Judicial review of constitutional amendments in the Brazilian Supreme Court. Fla J Int Law 17:449, 461, 721

    Google Scholar 

  • Michel S, Cofone IN (this volume) Credible commitment or paternalism? the case of unamendability

    Google Scholar 

  • Michelman FI (1998) Brennan and democracy. Calif Law Rev 86:399, 419

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohallem MF (2011) Immutable clauses and judicial review in India, Brazil and South Africa: expanding constitutional courts’ authority. Int J Hum Rights 15(5):765, 766–767

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris JMF (1909) The fifteenth amendment to the federal constitution. North Am Rev 189:82, 85

    Google Scholar 

  • Moses B (1891) Constitution of the United States of Mexico: antecedents. Ann Am Acad Polit Soc Sci 2:1, 4

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulford E (1870) The nation: the foundations of civil order and political life in the United States. Hurd and Houghton, New York, p 155

    Google Scholar 

  • Muñiz-Fraticelli VM (2009) The problem of a perpetual constitution. In: Gosseries A, Meyer L (eds) Intergenerational justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 379–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy WF (1987) Slaughter-house, civil rights, and limits on constitutional change. Am J Juris 32:1, 12–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy WF (1992) Staggering toward the new jerusalem of constitutional theory: a response to ralph F. Gaebler. Am J Juris 37:337, 348

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy WF (1995) In: Levinson S (ed) Merlin’s memory: the past and future imperfect of the once and future polity. pp 163, 177

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy WF (2007) Constitutional democracy: creating and maintaining a just political order. Johns Hopkins University Press, USA, p 506

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahar S, Dadoo A (2008) Constituent power & sovereignty: in light of amendments to the Indian constitution. NUJS Law Rev 1:559, 571

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen K (1979) On the choice between reform and revolution. In: Johnson HJ, Leach JJ, Muehlmann RG (eds) Revolutions, systems, and theories—essays in political philosophy. D. Reidel Publishing Company, USA, pp 155, 157

    Google Scholar 

  • Nogueira CG (2005) A Impossibilidade de as cláusulas pétreas vincularem as gerações futuras. Revista de Informação Legislativa 42(166):79, 84

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell R (1999) Guardians of the constitution: unconstitutional constitutional norms. J Civ Liberties 4:48, 51

    Google Scholar 

  • Olcay T (this volume) Unamendability of amendable clauses: the case of the Turkish constitution

    Google Scholar 

  • Opsahl T (1991–1992) The reflection of social values in the constitutional history of Norway—some illustrations. Holdsworth Law Rev 15:181, 185–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Orfield LB (1929–1930) The scope of the federal amending power. Mich Law Rev 28:550, 581

    Google Scholar 

  • Orfield LB (1942) The amending the federal constitution. Callaghan & Company, Pennsylvania, p 85

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine T, Philp M (1998) In: Philp M (ed) Rights of man, common sense, and other political writings. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 91–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettys TE (2008) Popular constitutionalism and relaxing the dead hand: can the people be trusted? Wash Univ Law Rev 86:313, 332

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfersmann O (2009) Ontological and epistemological complexity in comparative constitutional law. In: Engelbrekt AB, Nergelius J (eds) New directions in comparative law. Edward Elgar Publishing, UK, pp 81, 88

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfersmann O (2012) Unconstitutional constitutional amendment: a normativist approach. Zeitschrift für öffentliches Recht 67:81, 103

    Google Scholar 

  • Pillsbury AE (1909) The war amendment. North Am Rev 189:741–743

    Google Scholar 

  • Pilpilidis K (this volume) A constitution for eternity: an economic theory of explicit unamendability

    Google Scholar 

  • Ponthoreau MC, Ziller J (2002) The experience of the French Conseil Constitutionnel: political and social context and current legal-theoretical debates. In: Wojciech S (ed) Constitutional justice, east and west: democratic legitimacy and constitutional courts in post-communist Europe in a comparative perspective. Springer, Berlin, pp 119, 140

    Google Scholar 

  • Radin M (1934–35) The judicial review of statutes in continental Europe. W Va Law Q 41:112, 115

    Google Scholar 

  • Roel S (1968) History of Mexican constitutional experience: from Zitacuaro, 1811, to Queretaro, 1917. Calif W Law Rev 4(2):251, 256–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld M (1994–1995) The identity of the constitutional subject. Cardozo Law Rev 16:1049

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld M (2005) Constitutional adjudication in Europe and the United States: paradoxes and contrasts. In: European and US constitutionalism. Council of Europe, pp 165, 186 fn 80

    Google Scholar 

  • Rostow EV (1952) The democratic character of judicial review. Harvard Law Rev 66(2):193, 195

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau D (1994) The constitutional judge: master or slave of the constitution? In: Rosenfeld M (ed) Constitutionalism, identity, difference, and legitimacy: theoretical perspectives. Duke University Press, USA, pp 261, 273–282

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2012) The migration of the indian basic structure doctrine. In: Lokendra M (ed) Judicial activism in India—a festschrift in honour of justice V. R. Krishna Iyer. Universal Law Publishing Co., Uttar Pradesh, p 240

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2013a) Is judicial review of constitutional amendments undemocratic? (17.10.2013) ICONnect. http://www.iconnectblog.com/2013/10/article-review-response-carlos-bernal-pulido-and-yaniv-roznai-on-unconstitutional-constitutional-amendments

  • Roznai Y (2013b) The theory and practice of ‘supra-constitutional’ limits on constitutional amendments. ICLQ 62(3):557

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2013c) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments—the migration and success of a constitutional idea. Am J Com Law 61(3):657

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2014a) Amending “unamendable” provisions’ (20 October 2014) constitution-making & constitutional change blog. http://constitutional-change.com/amending-unamendable-provisions/

  • Roznai Y (2014b) Legisprudence limitations on constitutional amendments? reflections on the czech constitutional court’s declaration of unconstitutional constitutional act. ICL 8(1):29

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2015) Unamendability and the genetic code of the constitution. Eur Rev Public Law 27(2):775

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2017a) ‘We the people’, ‘oui, the people’ and the collective body: perceptions of constituent power. In: Jacobsohn G, Schor M (eds) Comparative constitutional theory. Edward Elger, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2017b) Constituent powers, amendment powers and popular sovereignty: linking unamendability and amendment procedures. In: Albert R, Contiades X, Fotiado A (eds) The foundations and traditions of constitutional amendment. Hart Publishing, UK, p 23

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y (2017c) Towards a theory of constitutional unamendability: on the nature and scope of the constitutional amendment powers. Jus Politicum – Revue de Droit Politique 18:5

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y, Suteu S (2015) Eternal territory? The crimean crisis and Ukraine’s territorial integrity as an unamendable principle. German Law J 16(3):542

    Google Scholar 

  • Roznai Y, Yolcu S (2012) An unconstitutional constitutional amendment—the Turkish perspective: a comment on the Turkish constitutional court’s headscarf decision. Int J Const Law 10(1):175

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubenfeld J (1997–1998) The moment and the millennium. George Wash Law Rev 66:1085

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachs A (1996–1997) South Africa’s unconstitutional constitution: the transition from power to lawful power. Saint Louis Univ Law J 41:1249

    Google Scholar 

  • Sager LG (1995–1996) The dead hand and constitutional amendment. Harvard J Law Public Policy 19:275

    Google Scholar 

  • Samaha AM (2008) Dead hand arguments and constitutional interpretation. Columbia Law Rev 108:606

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapir G (2010) The constitutional revolution—past, present and future. Miskal, Yedioth Ahronoth Books, pp 178–179 [Heb]

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner J (2005) The federal marriage amendment: to protect the sanctity of marriage or destroy constitutional democracy? Am Univ Law Rev 54:1487, 1493

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt C (2008) Constitutional theory (trans: Seitrzer J). Duke University Press, Durham, p 152

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzberg M (2009) Democracy and legal change, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 2

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweber H (2007) The language of liberal constitutionalism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 137

    Google Scholar 

  • Scotti VR (this volume) Unamendable constitutional provisions and the European common constitutional heritage. A comparison among three waves of constitutionalism

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh DK (1966) “What cannot be done directly cannot be done indirectly”: its meaning and logical status in constitutionalism. Mod Law Rev 29:273

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith E (2011) Old and protected? on the “supra-constitutional” clause in the constitution of Norway. Isr Law Rev 44(3):369, 375

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiliotopoulos E (1983) Judicial review of legislative acts in Greece. Temp Law Q 56:463, 466–467

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripati V (1998) Toward fifty years of constitutionalism and fundamental rights in India: looking back to see ahead (1950–2000). Am Univ Int Law Rev 14(2):413, 480

    Google Scholar 

  • Stith R (1996) Unconstitutional constitutional amendments; The extraordinary power of Nepal’s supreme court. Am UJ Intl L Pol’y 11:47

    Google Scholar 

  • Suber P (1999) Amendment. In: Gray CB (ed) Philosophy of law: an encyclopaedia I. Garland Pub. Co, New York and London, pp 31–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Suksi M (1995) Making a constitution: The outline of an argument. Rättsvetenskapliga Institutionen, p 6

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet AS (2000) Governing with judges: constitutional politics in Europe. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 89

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobisch K (2011) Public procurement law and effective legal protection. Vienna J Int Const Law 424, 427

    Google Scholar 

  • Tribe LH (1983) A constitution we are amending: in defense of a restrained judicial role. Harvard Law Rev 97:433, 440–443

    Google Scholar 

  • Tribe LH (2000) American constitutional law, 3rd edn. Foundation Press, pp 111–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2003) The logic of justification of judicial review. Int J Const Law 1(1) :99, 113

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (2012–2013) Constitution-making: an introduction. Tex Law Rev 91:1983, 2007

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (2015) Peasants with pitchforks, and toilers with twitter: constitutional revolutions and the constituent power. ICON 13(3):639, 642–643

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (2018) Amendment theory. In: Jacobsohn G, Schor M (eds) Comparative constitutional theory. Edward Elger, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanossi JRA (2000) Teoria constitutional, 2nd edn. Depalma, p 188

    Google Scholar 

  • Vedel G (1992) Schengen et Maastricht (à propos de la décision n°91-294 DC du Conseil constitutionnel du 25 juillet 1991). Revue Française de Droit Administratif 8(2):173

    Google Scholar 

  • Vile JR (1985) Limitations on the constitutional amending process. Const Comment 2:373, 383

    Google Scholar 

  • Vile JR (1990–1991) Legally amending the united states constitution: the exclusivity of article V’s mechanisms. Cumberland Law Rev (1990-1991) 21:271, 295

    Google Scholar 

  • Vile JR (1995) In: Levinson S (ed) The case against implicit limits on the constitutional amending process. pp 191, 198–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Widner J, Contiades X (2013) Constitution-writing process. In: Tushnet M, Fleiner T, Saunders C (eds) Routledge handbook of constitutional law. Routledge, London, pp 57, 58

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams GW (1928) What, if any, limitations are there upon the power to amend the constitution of the United States? Am Law Rev 62:529, 544

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood GS (1998) The creation of the American Republic 1776–1787. University of North Carolina Press, USA, pp 377, 379

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1994) The constitutional implications in France of the Maastricht treaty. Tulane Eur Civ Law Forum 9:35, 72

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (2005) The self-restraint of the French Conseil Constitutionnel in 2003 and 2004. Eur Pub Law 11(4):495

    Google Scholar 

  • Yap PJ (2006–2007) Rethinking constitutional review in America and the commonwealth: judicial protection of human rights in the common law world. Georgia J Int Comp Law 35:99, 104–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Yap PJ (2015) The conundrum of unconstitutional constitutional amendments. Global Constitutionalism 4:114, 116–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeaman GH (1871) The study of government. Little, Brown and co., USA, pp 710–711

    Google Scholar 

  • Yegen O (this volume) Debates on unamendable articles: deadlock on Turkey’s constitution-making process

    Google Scholar 

  • Zweig E (1909) Die Lehre vom Pouvoir Constituant. Tiibingen, p 324

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yaniv Roznai .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Roznai, Y. (2018). Necrocracy or Democracy? Assessing Objections to Constitutional Unamendability. In: Albert, R., Oder, B. (eds) An Unamendable Constitution?. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 68. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95141-6_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95141-6_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-95140-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-95141-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics