Skip to main content

Objects of Nature and Objects of Thought

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics

Part of the book series: Virtues and Economics ((VIEC,volume 3))

Abstract

The subject matter of the economy is unlike that of the natural sciences. It is the product of human intentionality, and as such, it inherently reflects the human judgment that brought it into being. The fundamental ontological diffence between objects found in nature and objects resulting from human intentionality are explored. The domestication of the techniques employed in the natural sciences cannot produce law-like generalisations in economics with the predictive and explanatory power that characterises the laws of the natural sciences. Modern economics has been most convincing when it has paid attention to the problems caused by the lack of homogeneity in the reality it examines. Studies addressing small, spatially and temporally well defined issues offering a generous supply of empirically verifiable evidence have been more effective in guiding us as to what should be than those aiming for the formation of law-like generalisations of universal applicability.

“The art poetic will be weighed in scales”

Aristophanes The Frogs

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As Ayer famously put it, propositions that cannot be verified empirically or by the laws of logic are “neither true nor false but literally senseless”. Ayer, A. J. (1946) Language, Truth and Logic. Dover Press, New York p. 31.

  2. 2.

    For a recapitulation and analysis of the modernist project see Archer, M. (2000) Being Human: The Problem of Agency Cambridge University Press.

  3. 3.

    Plato Republic 522c “I mean number and calculation, for isn’t it true that every craft and science must have a share in that?” Although the ancient Greeks came quite close to devising an instrument with which temperature could be measured, it seems that temperature was not thought to be among the measurables. For a systematic analysis of measurement in ancient Greece see Lloyd, G.E.R. (1987) The Revolutions of Wisdom University of California Press, Chapter V and Nussbaum (2001, 107–110).

  4. 4.

    Lord Robbins famously required only “almost” universal applicability to Karl Popper’s great distress. When and where would that „almost” amount to a falsification, or does that „almost” evade altogether the Popperian falsification test? Hausman’s version of Lord Robbins’ „almost” is reflected in the title of his seminal book. He sees economics as a „separate and inexact” science. (Hausman 1992)

  5. 5.

    In asking this question Polányi follows Adam Smith and Karl Marx , who were serious Hellenists, the first a Stoic and the second an Aristotelian for whom the sharp Platonic distinction between technē and tuchē, described above, was unconvincing.

  6. 6.

    The work of Vivian Walsh, Hilary Putnam , Amartya Sen and Martha C. Nussbaum is a major exception this generalisation, but their work has been largely ignored by mainstream economics. See Putnam, H and Walsh, V.: The End of Value-free Economics. 2012. New York and London, Routledge.

  7. 7.

    For a fine analysis of March’s oeuvre see Jovanovic, F. And Le Gall, P. „March to Numbers: The Statisctical Style of Lucien March ” in Klein, J. L. and Morgan, M. S. (Eds.): The Age of Economic Measurement . 2001. Duke University Press.

  8. 8.

    An examination of the question whether March’s claim that the combination of correlations with graphs salvages spacial and temporal information is beyond the scope of this paper.

  9. 9.

    See for example J. Robinson: What Are the Questions? And Other Essays. (1981.) for the growing concerns of Cambridge UK in its opposition to Cambridge Massachusetts. M.E. Sharpe Inc. New York and the references therein.

  10. 10.

    Mill, J.S. (1843) System of Logic. Longmans, Green & Co. London, Book lll, Ch. Vl. Sec. “Introduction” and Jevons, W. S. The Theory of Political Economy . Palgrave Macmillan pp. xxxviii–xxxix.

  11. 11.

    For a detailed analysis of Jevons’ interest in measuring instruments see Maas, H. „Jevons’ Balancing Acts” in Klein, J. L. and Morgan, M. S. (2001) The Age of Economic Measurement . Duke University Press

  12. 12.

    (13) The U:S: Department of the Navy was an important source of financing for this research.

  13. 13.

    An experiment may, of course, address the phenomena attendant upon separation, but an analysis of these cases is not relevant to economics.

  14. 14.

    A robot could not be made into a rational agent without specifying the terms of its rationality and confining his choices to a limited set.

  15. 15.

    This need to craft a surrogate reality in order to model incorporeal reality also spells trouble for materialism, but that subject is beyond the scope of this paper.

  16. 16.

    For an excellent recounting of this history see Kline, M. (1980) Mathematics; the Loss of Certainty, Oxford University Press.

  17. 17.

    Einstein, A, (1921) Sidelights on Relativity, quoted in Kline, M. (1980) Mathematics ; the Loss of Certainty, Oxford University Press. Some theories deny that mathematical thought is ‘independent of experience’.

  18. 18.

    This is the generally held view. See Morgan, M. S. (2012) The World in the Model; How Economists Work and Think, Cambridge University Press, pp. 138–139.

  19. 19.

    Note that, whereas there are no fewer than ten examples are given for „type-concepts”, ‘ideal-type concepts” are left without any.

  20. 20.

    „I want to emphasise strongly the point about economics being a moral science. I mentioned before that it deals with introspection and with values. I might have added that it deals with motives, expectations, psychological uncertainties.” Letter to Roy Harrod, 10 July 1938 (misdated 16 July) in Collected Letters of John Meynard Keynes .

  21. 21.

    This clause is usually interpreted the same way as in the natural sciences, namely that all other factors remain constant. In the natural sciences this assumption has verifiable truth value. All factors shown to affect the object under study are accounted for and there are means to hold them constant. But in economics we do not know what these other factors might be, there are no means to hold them constant, so the proper interpretation of the clause is that it is assumed that there are no other factors.

  22. 22.

    This clause is usually interpreted the same way as in the natural sciences, namely that all other factors remain constant. In the natural sciences this assumption has verifiable truth value. All factors shown to affect the object under study are accounted for and there are means to hold them constant. But in economics we do not know what these other factors might be, there are no means to hold them constant, so the proper interpretation of the clause is that it is assumed that there are no other factors.

  23. 23.

    Letter to Roy Harrod, ibid.

  24. 24.

    How much of this achievent is due to science and how much of it to economic theory may be the subject of an interminable debate. But there can be little doubt about the subtly corrupting effect on science of having been steered towards the study of subjects that enhance ‘efficiency’ and ‘consumer satisfaction’ as those notions are set out in modern economic theory.

References

  • Arendt, H. 1951. The origins of totalitarianism. Penguin Classics Edition (2017).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A.J. 1946. Language, truth and logic. New York: Dover Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———.1956. The Problem of Knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. The concept of a person. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1989. Nature’s capacities and their measurement. UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. 2002. Modern economics and its critics. In Fact and fiction in economics, ed. U. Mäki. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1953. Essays In Positive Economics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A., and H. Varian. 1978. Economic models. The Journal of Philosophy 75 (11): 664–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamminga, B., and N. DeMarchi. 1994. Idealisation in economics. Amsterdam: Rodopi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D.M. 1992. The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. 1887. Counting and measuring. New York: D. Van Nostrand Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jevons, W.S. 1911. The Theory of Political Economy. Fourth, (reprinted 2013). UK: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jovanovic, F., and P. LeGall. 2001. March to numbers: The statistical style of lucien March. In The Age of Economic Measurement, ed. J. Klein and M.S. Morgan. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, M. 1974. What is wrong with economics? In Further essays in economic theory. (1978). New York: Holmes & Meier Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, M. 1980. Mathematics: The loss of certainty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. 2002. Kinds of assumptions and their truth: Shaking an untwisted F-twist. Kyklos 53 (3).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———., ed. 2009. The methodology of positive economics: Reflections on the Milton Friedman legacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, D.N. 1985. The rhetoric of economics. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1843. System of logic. Longmans: Green & Co. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M.S. 2012. The world in the model: How economists work and think. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. 1991. Unreal assumptions in economic theory and their truth: The F-twist untwisted. Kyklos 34 (3).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 2016. What is it Like to Be a Bat? Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 2001. The fragility of goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. 1958. Personal knowledge. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poovey, M. 1998. A history of the modern fact: Problems of knowledge in the sciences of wealth and society. Choicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1975. Philosophical papers. Vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 2002. The collapse of the fact/value Dichotomy and other essays. US: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H., and V. Walsh. 2012. The end of value-free economics. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. (1951/1976). The Ways of Paradox and other Essays. US: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J. 1981. What are the Questions? And Other Essays. New York: M:E: Sharpe Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1919. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. (2008) ed. Spokesman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1776. The wealth of nations. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, D. 1792. Elements of the philosophy of the human mind in the collected works of Dugald Stewart. Vol. 1. Edinburgh: T. Constable and Co. 1854.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walras, L. 1926 Elements of pure economics. Trans. W. Jaffe (1954). George Allen and Unwin Ltd. London.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Róna .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Róna, P. (2018). Objects of Nature and Objects of Thought. In: Róna, P., Zsolnai, L. (eds) Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics. Virtues and Economics, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94529-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics