Advertisement

Why, Perhaps, Philosophers of Education (and Other Educational Researchers) “Leave Everything as It Is”

Chapter
  • 279 Downloads

Abstract

It has long been a complaint of philosophers of education and other educational researchers that, in particular policy makers pay little heed to their arguments and evidence. Equally, policy makers complain that too much educational research is irrelevant or uninformative or fails to dress their concerns. Despite the almost exponential growth in the quantity of educational research, this seems to have little impact, to “leave everything as it is”.

This paper will explore this problem through four lines of thought:
  1. (i)

    by looking at the role of the communicative and social practices that take philosophy and other forms of educational inquiry into practice and policy;

     
  2. (ii)

    by looking at the logic of arguments that might take us from philosophical work (in particular) to convincing prescriptions for educational policy and practice;

     
  3. (iii)

    by looking at the controversy and uncertainty that is intrinsic to research endeavour as a barrier to its impact on policy and practice;

     
  4. (iv)

    by looking at philosophical interest as something detached from engagement with policy or practice.

     

It will conclude that there are a number of compelling reasons why we should have low expectations of the impact on policy or practice of philosophical and other work characterised and communicated in the ways set out here.

Keywords

Left Everything Educational Researcher Philosophical Work Paul Smeyers Speculative Doubting 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Bridges, D. (2015). Working without shame in international education: From consequentialism to casuistry? Ethics and Education, 10(3), 271–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bridges, D., & Watts, M. (2008). Educational research and policy: Epistemological considerations. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 42(Supplement1), 41–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Edwards, A., Sebba, J., & Rickinson, M. (2007). Working with users: Some implications for educational research. British Educational Research Journal, 35(5), 647–661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Horsthemke, K. (2017). #Facts MustFall–Education in a post-truth, post-truthful world. Ethics and Education, 12(3), 273–289.Google Scholar
  5. Keyes, R. (2004). The post-truth era: Dishonesty and deception in contemporary life. New York: St Martins.Google Scholar
  6. MacFarlane, B. (2009). Researching with integrity: The ethics of academic inquiry. New York/London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  7. Peters, R. S. (1967). What is an educational process? In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The concept of education. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  8. Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  9. Pring, R. (2001). The virtues and vices of an educational researcher. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 35(3), 407–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Richards, I. A. (Ed.). (1966). Plato’s republic. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Stenhouse, L. (1975). An introduction to curriculum research and development. London: Heinemann.Google Scholar
  12. Sutherland, W. J., Spiegelhalter, D., & Burgman, M. A. (2013). Twenty tips for interpreting scientific claims. Nature, 503, 335–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Tight, M. (2017). Higher education journals: Their characteristics and contribution. Higher Education Research and Development. Downloaded as a pre-publication e-print at http://www.research.lancs.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/higher-education-journals(e174a909-2219-4b70-a3ea-103e3dde7e7b)/export.html 30th November 2017
  14. Times Higher Education. (2017, November 16). Too many higher education journals – Here are the best ones. pp. 9–10.Google Scholar
  15. Ware, M., & Mabe, M. (2012). An overview of scientific and scholarly journal publishing. The Hague, The Netherlands: International Association of Scientific, Technical and Medical Publishers.Google Scholar
  16. White, J. P. (1973). Towards a compulsory curriculum. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  17. White, J. P. (2007). What schools are for and why? (IMPACT Paper No 14). Oxford, UK: Wiley/Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain.Google Scholar
  18. White, J. P. (2008). Aims as policy in primary education. Research Survey 1/1. In R. Alexander (Ed.), The primary review. Cambridge, UK: University of Cambridge.Google Scholar
  19. Whitty, G. (2006). Education(al) research and education policy making: Is conflict inevitable? British Educational Research Journal, 32(2), 159–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of East AngliaNorwichUK
  2. 2.St Edmund’s CollegeCambridgeUK
  3. 3.Homerton CollegeCambridgeUK

Personalised recommendations