Skip to main content

Reasons Primitivism and Epistemic Expressivism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 382 Accesses

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

Abstract

I discuss Michael Smith’s recent case against the idea that the concept of a normative reason is unanalysable. Smith argues that, as a matter of conceptual fact, some fact, p, can only be a reason to believe that q, given that p provides evidence for the truth of q, and that this is best explained by the concept of a reason for belief being analysable in evidential terms. Given, then, that the concept of a reason is not a “ragbag,” reasons primitivism fails quite generally. I propose that reasons primitivists can make sense of this evidential constraint on reasons for belief if they adopt a suitable expressivist account of reasons judgements. I conclude by briefly considering a metaphysical version of Smith’s argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This formulation is inspired by that offered in Kauppinen (2015).

  2. 2.

    The one-star formulation of reasons primitivism allows for the possibility of giving a metaphysically reductive account of normative properties and facts in terms of natural properties and facts (see, e.g., Schroeder 2007). None of the formulations given above imply the claim that all other normative (or evaluative) concepts, properties and facts would be analysable in terms of reasons.

  3. 3.

    Worries in the same spirit are aired in passing also in Kearns and Star (2009). For other recent criticisms of reasons primitivism or developments of alternatives to it, see Broome (2013, chap. 4); Finlay (2014, chap. 3); Howard (2019); McHugh and Way (2016); Thomson (2008, chaps. 8–9); Väyrynen (2011).

  4. 4.

    For criticism, see Cuneo and Kyriacou (forthcoming); for Heathwood’s response, see his chapter in this volume.

  5. 5.

    For discussion, see Heathwood (2009) and Cuneo and Kyriacou (forthcoming).

  6. 6.

    This kind of line is taken, for example, in Dreier (1992, 21), and Olson (2014), with regard to the issue of explaining why the supervenience of the normative on the natural (or the descriptive) would be a conceptual truth.

  7. 7.

    Perhaps there is yet another place to look. We could perhaps suggest that while the concept of a reason is to be taken as primitive, the evidential constraint is built into the concept of a belief in that it is true, as a matter of conceptual fact, that we ought to believe in accordance with our evidence, and thus only take something, p, to be a reason to believe something, q, if p is evidence, or makes it more likely, that q (on normativity of belief, see, e.g., McHugh and Whiting 2014).

  8. 8.

    I mean to understand “(broadly) desire-like” broadly enough in order to encompass desire-plus-belief states, and higher-order states of being in some such complex states, such that behave in broadly desire-like ways (see Schroeder 2013; Toppinen 2013; Ridge 2014).

  9. 9.

    See, e.g., Blackburn (1993); Gibbard (2003, chap. 5); Hare (1952, chap. 10).

  10. 10.

    See Gibbard (1990, chap. 3, 2003, chap. 11, 2012, chap. 8).

  11. 11.

    Nishi Shah’s (2003) criticism of Gibbard seems to be partly based on this point.

  12. 12.

    This seems to be how Shah (2003) suggests Gibbard could respond to this particular worry.

  13. 13.

    See also Kyriacou (2012).

  14. 14.

    Just to mention one fairly big issue, expressivists would need to have something to offer in relation to Frege-Geach style worries. Perhaps they should go hybrid/relational (cf. Schroeder 2013; Toppinen 2013; Ridge 2014). Now, this is rough, and extremely preliminary, but perhaps to think that p is a reason to believe that q is, roughly, to (a) have inferential dispositions to raise one’s credences on certain sorts of grounds (or to have certain ways of forming beliefs), and (b) to believe that raising one’s credence in q on the grounds of believing that p would fit the bill (amount to forming a belief in this way). To believe that there’s no reason to believe that q could then be a matter of having these inferential dispositions (ways of forming beliefs) and of believing that such dispositions don’t manifest in raising one’s credence in q (that a belief that q cannot be formed in these ways). For more sophisticated expressivist treatments of judgements concerning epistemic justification or knowledge, see Chrisman (2007), Field (2009), Kappel (2010), Kyriacou (2012) and Ridge (2007). For discussion of how expressivists should understand reasons for action thought, see Ridge (2014, chap. 4) and Sinclair (2016).

  15. 15.

    For the idea that the minimal rationality constraints on interpretation can be understood naturalistically or descriptively, see, e.g., Glüer and Wikforss (2009). For discussion of deviant causal chains, see, e.g., Mele (2003) (which defends a causalist account of action) and Wedgwood (2006).

  16. 16.

    This selection of options has been inspired in part by McHugh (2013, 2015).

  17. 17.

    For defences of “pragmatic” reasons for belief, see, e.g. Howard (2019), Leary (2017) and Reisner (2008).

  18. 18.

    The talk of explaining meaning in terms of states of mind is not very precise. If expressivism is advanced as a metasemantic thesis (see, e.g., Chrisman 2016 and Ridge 2014), it is perhaps possible to have a unified account of reasons-talk and thought at some level despite the fact that the explanation for why this unified account works the way it does would be somewhat disunified.

References

  • Blackburn, Simon. 1993. Moral Realism. In Essays in Quasi-Realism, ed. Simon Blackburn, 111–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, John. 2013. Rationality Through Reasoning. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, Matthew. 2007. From Epistemic Contextualism to Epistemic Expressivism. Philosophical Studies 135 (2): 225–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The Meaning of “Ought”: Beyond Descriptivism and Expressivism in Metaethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, Terence, and Christos Kyriacou. forthcoming. Defending the Moral/Epistemic Parity. In Metaepistemology, ed. Conor McHugh, Jonathan Way, and Daniel Whiting. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, James. 1992. The Supervenience Argument Against Moral Realism. Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (3): 13–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Metaethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1): 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, Hartry. 2009. Epistemology Without Metaphysics. Philosophical Studies 143 (2): 249–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, Stephen. 2014. Confusion of Tongues: A Theory of Normative Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Meaning and Normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, Kathrin, and Åsa Wikforss. 2009. Against Content Normativity. Mind 118 (469): 31–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R.M. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, Chris. 2009. Moral and Epistemic Open-Question Arguments. Philosophical Books 50 (2): 83–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Christopher. 2019. The Fundamentality of Fit. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 14, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kappel, Klemens. 2010. Expressivism About Knowledge and the Value of Knowledge. Acta Analytica 25 (2): 175–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, Antti. 2015. Favoring. Philosophical Studies 172 (7): 1953–1971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kearns, Stephen, and Daniel Star. 2009. Reasons as Evidence. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 4, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau, 215–242. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyriacou, Christos. 2012. Habits-Expressivism About Epistemic Justification. Philosophical Papers 41 (2): 209–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leary, Stephanie. 2017. In Defense of Practical Reasons for Belief. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (3): 529–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, Conor. 2013. Normativism and Doxastic Deliberation. Analytic Philosophy 54 (4): 447–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. The Illusion of Exclusivity. European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4): 1117–1136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, Conor, and Jonathan Way. 2016. Fittingness First. Ethics 126 (3): 575–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, Conor, and Daniel Whiting. 2014. The Normativity of Belief. Analysis 74 (4): 698–713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McPherson, Tristram. 2012. Ethical Non-Naturalism and the Metaphysics of Supervenience. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 7, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau, 205–234. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, Alfred R. 2003. Motivation and Agency. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, Jonas. 2014. Moral Error Theory: History, Critique, Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 1993. The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society and Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisner, Andrew. 2008. Weighing Pragmatic and Evidential Reasons for Belief. Philosophical Studies 138 (1): 17–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, Michael. 2007. Epistemology for Ecumenical Expressivists. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 81: 83–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, Thomas M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, Mark. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Tempered Expressivism. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 8, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau, 283–314. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, Nishi. 2003. How Truth Governs Belief. Philosophical Review 112 (4): 447–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, Neil. 2016. Reasons, Inescapability and Persuasion. Philosophical Studies 173 (10): 2823–2844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Michael. 2015. Evaluative Judgements, Judgements about Reasons, and Motivations In Motivational Internalism, edited by Gunnar Björnsson, Caj Strandberg, Ragnar Francén Olinder, John Eriksson, and Frederik Björklund, 27–43. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Parfit’s Mistaken Metaethics. In Does Anything Really Matter? Essays on Parfit and Objectivity, ed. Peter Singer, 99–120. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 2008. Normativity. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toppinen, Teemu. 2013. Believing in Expressivism. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 8, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau, 252–282. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Non-Naturalism Gone Quasi. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 13, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen, Pekka. 2011. A Wrong Turn to Reasons? In New Waves in Metaethics, ed. Michael Brady, 185–207. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, Ralph. 2006. The Normative Force of Reasoning. Noûs 40 (4): 660–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Teemu Toppinen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Toppinen, T. (2018). Reasons Primitivism and Epistemic Expressivism. In: Kyriacou, C., McKenna, R. (eds) Metaepistemology. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93369-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics