Skip to main content

Towards a Better Understanding of Mathematical Understanding

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Truth, Existence and Explanation

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 334))

Abstract

Please check if the identified section head levels are okay.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For example, Steiner (1978) and Kitcher (1989); I will return to these accounts.

  2. 2.

    Though perhaps not the issue of beauty, which shares with understanding both an elusive quality and a psychological connotation.

  3. 3.

    For example, mathematical beauty deserves its own investigation; see Rota 1997 and Netz 2005 for some such work.

  4. 4.

    Though, as I have said, not a theory with necessary and sufficient conditions.

  5. 5.

    I do not specifically address how structure relates to understanding the different aspects of mathematics because I think that understanding definitions vs. theorems vs. axiom systems, etc., can only be addressed in terms of abilities – though I do not argue for this here.

  6. 6.

    That is, understanding of any sort is hard to explain; mathematical understanding presents special challenges given its technical nature and abstract subject matter.

  7. 7.

    Frege 1884, introduction.

  8. 8.

    This is not always an explicit assumption, but it leads to a dismissive attitude one finds in Frege and some of his defenders.

  9. 9.

    Avigad 2008 focuses on abilities: those behind understanding mathematical proofs.

  10. 10.

    Though there is some recent philosophy of mathematics literature on the topic. In particular, see Avigad 2008 and 2010.

  11. 11.

    This is a paper on the philosophy of mathematics education (rather than mathematics education); nevertheless, I should note that its intended audience still seems different from that of mainstream philosophy of mathematics.

  12. 12.

    Later in the article he helps himself to a wider use of “knowledge”, as in “know-how” or “knowledge of”; however, this is a problem that I will not address.

  13. 13.

    Assuming this is what Gettier examples show. Porteous agrees that these examples challenge the traditional account, but maintains that for mathematics justified true belief is close enough.

  14. 14.

    For a detailed look at some specific relationships between explanation and understanding, see Tappenden 2005. This is an interesting, useful paper; but like Kitcher, Steiner and Friedman, Tappenden focuses on theories or frameworks that promote understanding. Though more sketchy, my project here has a broader (even broader!) aim.

  15. 15.

    Like Kitcher (1989) and unlike Steiner (1978), as we’ll see.

  16. 16.

    The volume Mancosu et al. (2005) shows that there is some progress and interest; nevertheless, most of its articles are programmatic in nature.

  17. 17.

    For recent work on the concept of grounding in mathematics, start with Šebestik 2016.

  18. 18.

    This is a limitation, not a criticism. Steiner is explicit about the narrowness of his project: “We have not analyzed mathematical explanation, but explanation by proof; there are other kinds of mathematical explanation.” (147, emphasis in original)

  19. 19.

    For example, Hafner and Mancosu 2005 “maintain that mathematical explanations are heterogeneous” (222) – so no single theory – and that the topic is even “treacherous.” (241)

  20. 20.

    Avigad 2010 also recommends a “bottom up” approach in order to – at least first – better articulate the data that a theory of understanding would explain. (See conclusion.) I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing me to Avigad’s work on this topic; although his work resonates a great deal with my views I unfortunately discovered it too late to follow his recommendation!

  21. 21.

    The standard literature begins with Benacerraf (1965); see Hellman (1989), Resnik (1997) and Shapiro (1997) for more developed philosophies.

  22. 22.

    I say “just” because one can adopt the structuralist perspective and still think mathematical objects exist. That is, one can retain the view that arithmetic is about the numbers 3, 4, 5, etc., while maintaining that important arithmetic results typically concern the natural number structure rather than individual numbers. The perspective is thus agnostic on philosophical issues about the priority or independence of structures from mathematical objects and systems.

  23. 23.

    The idea that it is relations and relation-types that “matter” more to mathematics is a core view of mathematical structuralism. For example, according to Shapiro, “The theme of mathematical structuralism is that what matters to a mathematical theory is not the internal nature of its objects, such as its numbers, functions, sets, or points, but how those objects relate to each other.” (Shapiro undated, opening sentence.) Despite this core, the general idea of “structure” is quite hard to pin down; in addition it is ambiguous. With regard to physical objects, it can be used to refer to a particular, as in “The bank is in that big brick structure down the road,” though it can also mean a type, as in “The A-frame structure is visually striking”. When it comes to explaining what a mathematical structure is, the notion of abstraction is often used. For example, Shapiro explains that a mathematical system is a “collection of objects together with certain relations on those objects…. A structure is the abstract form of a system, which ignores or abstracts away from any features of the objects that do not bear on the relations. So, the natural number structure is the form common to all of the natural number systems.” (Shapiro undated, section 1.) The idea is that by bracketing, or removing from consideration, certain features of two mathematical systems their underlying common form, or structure, can be unveiled. This process of ignoring some features to get at a common, usually more abstract, underlying property or form is roughly what “abstraction” means. However, the notorious problems of what philosophers mean by an abstract structure (or any kind of universal), the activity of abstraction or, especially perhaps, the relation between the two are well beyond the purview of this paper.

  24. 24.

    See for example Maclaurin 1742, Introduction.

  25. 25.

    See again Maclaurin 1742, Book I, Chapter I, especially opening paragraph.

  26. 26.

    Thurston is another mathematician who emphasizes the art and beauty of mathematics, and who explores what we mean by mathematical understanding. See his 1994 and 2010.

  27. 27.

    I hope to provide more argument for this elsewhere. Here I am just addressing how or why images carry epistemic weight in mathematics, not arguing that they can do so.

  28. 28.

    Tappenden (2005) also appeals to visualization in connection with mathematical understanding, but, as mentioned above, his focus is on whole theories. For him, a theory that lends itself to visualization tends to be more understandable and fruitful. (150) He also notes that visualizability counts in favor of the “naturalness” of a theory or framework. (180) Here I focus on a neighboring but different question of how and why visual images function as tools for understanding, which Tappenden brackets (155) to pursue his other goals.

  29. 29.

    This is not to say I accept such diagrams as full proofs or as better than proofs. My point is merely that visual information can assist understanding; my question is why and how.

  30. 30.

    There are of course some issues. One is to explain how a single diagram can support a general theorem. Another is to connect the geometric and the symbolic expressions of the theorem – to explain how the spatial object supports the numerical equation, x2 + y2 = z2. For this latter in particular I think the structuralist lens is important; I focus on another example to make my point more obvious.

  31. 31.

    See for example, Brown (2008), Mancosu et al. (2005), and Nelsen (1993).

  32. 32.

    The “object” in question can be seen as the set of natural numbers and its “characterizing property” as induction. (There is of course literature debating whether inductive proofs can explain. For example, Lange 2009 and responses.)

  33. 33.

    For example, if adding a new “column”, one must add it next to the previously “tallest” column and one must make it exactly one block higher. One cannot add that taller column to the middle or the other end of the staircase. If iterating via “layers” one must put a block on top of each existing step, and then add one to the “floor” next to the lowest end or new stack of two. These rules can easily be taught to a child.

  34. 34.

    Again, such pictures are in my view neither genuine proofs nor better than traditional proofs, except insofar as they are more widely accessible. They do not supplant the equation or its traditional proof. But they are tools that promote understanding, and as such they function like partial justifications. Further, this function explains their normativity (why we are correct to believe the theorem on the basis of the picture), and their epistemic contributions (why they lead to understanding rather than mere belief).

  35. 35.

    Contrary to the views of Nelsen, Brown and others.

  36. 36.

    I believe other examples can be analyzed similarly to explain why such pictures carry justifying weight. For example, a similar analyses can be given regarding the standard spatial representation of 1 + 3 + 5 … + 2n-1 = n2, or that of the Zeno series (though these further examples are beyond the scope of this paper). As with the case here analyzed, I would argue that the normative status of the diagram depends on shared structural features: that key properties of the picture match key elements of the relevant equations. The shared structure is what explains why they increase our understanding as well as why we take them to reveal the facts (rather than taking them to be mere causes of beliefs that perhaps happen to be true).

  37. 37.

    I am grateful to an anonymous referee for some constructive feedback on a written draft of this paper, though I fear I have sidestepped rather than answered the hard questions. I am also indebted to participants at two conferences, for the opportunity to try out some of these ideas: the Logic Colloquium 2015 (joint meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic and the Conference of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science), at the University of Helsinki, and FilMat 2016 (second international conference of the Italian network for the philosophy of mathematics), at the University of Chieti-Pescara. Finally, thanks go to the editors of this volume for all of their hard work.

References

  • Avigad, J. 2008. Understanding proofs. In The philosophy of mathematical practice, ed. Mancosu, 317–353. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Understanding, formal verification, and the philosophy of mathematics. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research XXVII (1): 165–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. 1965. What numbers could not be. Philosophical Review 74: 47–73 Reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam eds., 1983, pp. 272–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P., and H. Putnam. 1983. Philosophy of mathematics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, B. 1810/1996. Contributions to a better-grounded presentation of mathematics. In From Kant to Hilbert, a Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, ed. William Ewald, vol. 1, 174–224. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J.R. 2008. Philosophy of mathematics: A contemporary introduction to the world of proofs and pictures. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ewald, W., ed. 1996. From Kant to Hilbert, a source book in the foundations of mathematics (volumes I and II). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. 2012. And so on…: reasoning with infinite diagrams. Synthese 186: 371–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1884. The foundations of arithmetic. Trans. J.L. Austin. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1974. Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy 71: 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giaquinto, M. 2007. Visual thinking in mathematics: An epistemological study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz, E., and H. Breger, eds. 2000. The growth of mathematical knowledge. Kluwer: Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hafner, J., and P. Mancosu. 2005. The varieties of mathematical explanation. In Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics, ed. P. Mancosu et al., 215–250. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G.H. A mathematician’s apology (London 1941). References to the electronic version. http://www.math.ualberta.ca/mss/.

  • Haylock, D., and A. Cockburn. 2008. Understanding mathematics for young children. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. 1989. Mathematics without numbers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1989. Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Scientific explanation, ed. P. Kitcher and W.C. Salmon, 410–505. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., and W. Salmon, eds. 1989. Scientific explanation. University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. 2009. Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory. Analysis 69: 203–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, C. 1742. A Treatise of fluxions. Excerpted In: From Kant to Hilbert, a source book in the foundations of mathematics (volumes I and II), ed. W. Ewald (1996), 95–122. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. 2000. On mathematical explanation. In The growth of mathematical knowledge, ed. E. Grosholz and H. Breger, 103–119. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. ed. 2008. The philosophy of mathematical practice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Explanation in mathematics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 edn., ed. Edward N. Zalta). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/mathematics-explanation/.

  • Mancosu, P., K. Jorgensen, and S. Pedersen, eds. 2005. Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michener, E.R. 1978, August. Understanding mathematics. A.I. Memo – 488, LOGO Memo – 50, MIT Artificial Intelligence Lab document.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelsen, R.B. 1993. Proofs without words. Washington, DC: The Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Netz, R. 2005. The aesthetics of mathematics: a study. In Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics, ed. P. Mancosu, K.F. Jørgensen, and S.A. Pedersen, 251–293. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H. 1900. Intuition and logic in mathematics. In: From Kant to Hilbert, a source book in the foundations of mathematics (volumes I and II), ed. W. Ewald (1996), 1012–1020. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1908. Science and method, authorized translation by G. B. Halsted in The foundations of science. Washington, DC: The University Press of America, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porteous, K. 2008. Understanding mathematics. Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal, 23. http://socialsciences.exeter.ac.uk/education/research/centres/stem/publications/pmej/pome23/index.htm.

  • Resnik, M. 1997. Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rota, G. 1997. The phenomenology of mathematical beauty. Synthese 111: 171–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Šebestik, Jan. Bolzano’s logic. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 edn., ed. Edward N. Zalta). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/bolzano-logic/.

  • Shapiro, S. 1997. Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. undated. Mathematical structuralism. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. http://www.iep.utm.edu/.

  • Steiner, M. 1978. Mathematical explanation. Philosophical Studies 34: 135–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. 2005. Proof style and understanding in mathematics I: Visualization, unification and axiom choice. In Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics (Synthese library, volume 327), ed. P. Mancosu, K.F. Jørgensen, and S.A. Pedersen, 147–214. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, W. 1994. On proof and progress in mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 30 (2): 161–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. short essay in article. 2010. Mathematics meets fashion: Thurston’s concepts inspire designer. AMS News Releases, April 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1972. On certainty. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Janet Folina .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Folina, J. (2018). Towards a Better Understanding of Mathematical Understanding. In: Piazza, M., Pulcini, G. (eds) Truth, Existence and Explanation. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 334. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93342-9_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics