Skip to main content

Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the Evolutionary Objection: Rethinking the Relevance of Empirical Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

Abstract

Neo-Aristotelian metaethical naturalism is a modern attempt at naturalizing ethics using ideas from Aristotle’s teleological metaphysics. Proponents of this view argue that moral virtue in human beings is an instance of natural goodness, a kind of goodness supposedly also found in the realm of non-human living things. Many critics question whether neo-Aristotelian naturalism is tenable in light of modern evolutionary biology. Two influential lines of objection have appealed to an evolutionary understanding of human nature and natural teleology to argue against this view. In this paper, I offer a reconstruction of these two seemingly different lines of objection as raising instances of the same dilemma, giving neo-Aristotelians a choice between contradicting our considered moral judgment and abandoning metaethical naturalism. I argue that resolving the dilemma requires showing a particular kind of continuity between the norms of moral virtue and norms that are necessary for understanding non-human living things. I also argue that in order to show such a continuity, neo-Aristotelians need to revise the relationship they adopt with empirical science and acknowledge that the latter is relevant to assessing their central commitments regarding living things. Finally, I argue that to move this debate forward, both neo-Aristotelians and their critics should pay attention to recent work on the concept of organism in evolutionary and developmental biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    She says, for instance, that if humans are understood as creatures with an immortal soul or as persons or rational agents, it will not be clear that they are a natural kind of thing.

  2. 2.

    The empirical research cited by these authors includes Frank (1985), Thornhill and Palmer (2000), Hrdy (1999), Hirshleifer and Rasmusen (1989), and Wilson and Dugatkin (1997).

  3. 3.

    Note that on the neo-Aristotelian conception of practical reason, rationality and morality are not at odds but on the same footing. Practical reason involves not just self-interested considerations but moral considerations as well.

  4. 4.

    Note that if the critics were moral skeptics, Lott’s argument which starts from the assumption that there are in fact virtuous people would not convince them.

  5. 5.

    See Lott (2012a, 420) for a rejection of a “two-stage” reading of neo-Aristotelian naturalism.

  6. 6.

    It’s important to note that although there is a logical continuity between the human and non-human case in that they are life -forms and have a natural history , there is also an important difference resulting from the fact that the human life -form is inter alia characterized by practical reason. Because practical reason has practical authority, it also belongs to the human life -form that its bearers characteristically have a sound grasp on practical reason. Thus, there is an important sense in which knowledge of the human life -form has to “come from the inside”. As Hacker-Wright (2013) puts it, human natural goodness depends on our “rational self-interpretation” (92). This difference between humans and non-humans raises an important question about whether the noted logical continuity is enough to meet what I have called the continuity requirement. As Lott (2014) articulates the issue, neo-Aristotelians need to show that their account of practical reason relies on the specifically human life -form and not on some more abstract category like “person” or “rational agent”. In order to do this, neo-Aristotelians have to explain in what way other aspects of the human life -form relate to practical reason and play a constitutive role. This is a question that needs to be addressed before the neo-Aristotelian project can fully succeed, but it doesn’t directly relate to the evolutionary challenge and I must leave it aside here. See Hacker-Wright (2013) for an attempt to address this question.

  7. 7.

    Note, for instance, that it’s not at all obvious that the violent fights of elephant seals are detrimental to their flourishing in the sense of living the characteristic life of their life -form.

  8. 8.

    Fitzpatrick gives the impression that the problem with defining welfare in terms of gene replication is that it would be “a radical departure from intuitive notions of organismic welfare or well-being” (Fitzpatrick, 68). But it’s important to clarify that it is not our intuitions regarding the flourishing of animals like elephant seals that keep us from defining flourishing in genetic terms. The reason has to do with the continuity requirement.

  9. 9.

    Regardless of whether or not these accounts are taken to offer a reduction of the concept of function , the conditions they specify for function ascription are reductive in the sense that they can be understood without making any reference to the concept of function .

  10. 10.

    Note that Fitzpatrick denies that his account of function is a standard etiological theory (Fitzpatrick, 229–46).

  11. 11.

    Another biologically inclined critic, Odenbaugh (2017) seems to makes the same assumption when he claims that the etiological account of function is “the only good theory we have of normative natural functions”. In fact, he goes as far as claiming that because the neo-Aristotelian account of function is not reducible to our best scientific accounts of functions it is not a naturalistic theory, but a form of vitalism.

  12. 12.

    Note that an organism ’s flourishing is given in a system of natural-historical judgments that express the characteristic features that “play a part” in the life of that kind of organism .

  13. 13.

    Another way to explain away the evaluations of natural goodness, particularly in the case of sentient animals, would be to allow that they have a welfare, but only one that is entirely rooted in their desires and their ability to feel pleasure and pain. Note that this concept of welfare doesn’t depend on an organism ’s life -form, but is rather based on the individual’s own psychology. So it is different from the neo-Aristotelian concept of flourishing and thus is not suitable for naturalizing moral virtue.

  14. 14.

    See Thompson’s (2004) vivid discussion of how empirical observations guide us in acquiring knowledge of a novel type of jellyfish.

  15. 15.

    See Klein (2005) for an account of the shifting ontology of chemistry in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.

  16. 16.

    See Daniel Nicholson’s remarks on the disappearance of the organism in evolutionary theory (Nicholson 2014, 1–2).

  17. 17.

    Hacker-Wright made similar remarks about the concept of gene in personal communication.

  18. 18.

    When we make a judgment like “cats have four legs” we aren’t primarily concerned with identifying what makes cats living but are simply trying to understand the kind of thing in front of us.

  19. 19.

    See, e.g., how Laubichler and Wagner (2000) argue that taking the concept of organism to be ontologically prior to its functional structures can solve certain problems of mathematical models in biology with character identification.

References

  • Andreou, C. 2006. Getting On in a Varied World. Social Theory and Practice 32 (1): 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. The Extended Phenotype: The Long Reach of the Gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1937. Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W.J. 2000. Teleology and the Norms of Nature. New York: Garland Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. 2001. Natural Goodness . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R.H. 1985. Choosing the Right Pond: Human Behavior and the Quest for Status. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. 2009. What is Natural About Foot’s Ethical Naturalism? Ratio 22 (3): 308–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Human Nature, Virtue, and Rationality. In Aristotelian Ethics in Contemporary Perspective, ed. Julia Peters, 83–96. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirshleifer, D., and E. Rasmusen. 1989. Cooperation in a Repeated Prisoners’ Dilemma with Ostracism. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 12 (1): 87–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hrdy, S.B. 1999. Mother Nature: A History of Mothers, Infants, and Natural Selection. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. 2010. Assessing the Prospects for a Return of Organisms in Evolutionary Biology. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 32 (2/3): 341–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. 1995. Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarckian Dimension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., and L.A. Vickers. 2003. Pop Socio-biology Reborn: The Evolutionary Psychology of Rape and Violence. In In Mendel’s Mirror: Philosophical Reflections on Biology, ed. Philip Kitcher, 333–355. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U. 2005. Shifting Ontologies, Changing Classifications: Plant Materials from 1700 to 1830. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36 (2): 261–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M.D., and G.P. Wagner. 2000. Organism and Character Decomposition: Steps Towards an Integrative Theory of Biology. Philosophy of Science 67: 289–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E.A. 2001. Science Gone Astray: Evolution and Rape. Michigan Law Review 99 (6): 1536–1559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott, M. 2012a. Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function, and Moral Goodness. Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3): 353–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Moral Virtue as Knowledge of Human Form. Social Theory and Practice 38 (3): 407–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Why Be a Good Human Being? Natural Goodness, Reason, and the Authority of Human Nature. Philosophia 42 (3): 761–777.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, M. 1983. Naive Theories of Motion. In Mental Models, ed. Dedre Gentner and Albert L. Stevens, 299–324. Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, E. 2009. Life and Action. Analysis 69 (3): 557–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.G. 1989. In Defense of Proper Functions. Philosophy of Science 56: 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monod, J. 1971. Chance and Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology, trans. A. Wainhouse. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. 1991. Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defense. Philosophy of Science 58 (2): 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J., and L.B. Resnick. 1989. Comparing Historical and Intuitive Explanations of Motion: Does Naive Physics Have a Structure. In Proceedings of the 11th Annual Conference Cognitive Science Society, Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D.J. 2014. The Return of the Organism as a Fundamental Explanatory Concept in Biology. Philosophy Compass 9 (5): 347–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. 2017. Nothing in Ethics Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution? Natural Goodness, Normativity, and Naturalism. Synthese 194 (4): 1031–1055.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. 2000. The Ontogeny of Information. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., P.E. Griffiths, and R.D. Gray (eds.). 2001. Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and G.B. Müller (eds.). 2010. Evolution, the Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., and P. Kitcher. 1988. The Return of the Gene. The Journal of Philosophy 85 (7): 339–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. 2004. Apprehending Human Form. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 54: 47–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill, R., and C.T. Palmer. 2000. A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C.B. (ed.). 2003. Evolution, Gender, and Rape. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D.M. 2015. Organisms, Agency, and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2003. Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Phenotypic Accommodation: Adaptive Innovation Due to Developmental Plasticity. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mole Dev Evo), 304B (6): 610–618.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D.S., and L.A. Dugatkin. 1997. Group Selection and Assortative Interactions. The American Naturalist 149 (2): 336–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodcock, S. 2006. Philippa Foot’s Virtue Ethics Has an Achilles Heel. Dialogue 45 (3): 445–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. 1973. Functions. Philosophical Review 82 (2): 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful to Sergio Tenenbaum, Denis Walsh, Philip Clark, and John Hacker-Wright for extensive comments on earlier drafts of this article. I would like to also thank Andrew Sepielli and audiences at The Ethics of NatureThe Nature of Ethics conference at the University of Manchester, the 2015 meeting of the Canadian Philosophical Association in Ottawa, the 2nd annual roundtable in philosophy of science at the University of Toronto, and the 2016 meeting of the Pacific APA in San Francisco for their helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Parisa Moosavi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Moosavi, P. (2018). Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the Evolutionary Objection: Rethinking the Relevance of Empirical Science. In: Hacker-Wright, J. (eds) Philippa Foot on Goodness and Virtue. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-91256-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics