Skip to main content

Phenomenology Imported with EASE

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover The Structure of Interdisciplinary Science

Part of the book series: New Directions in the Philosophy of Science ((NDPS))

  • 377 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, the method developed above is applied in a case study of an interdisciplinary approach. The case in question is a study which is part of an ongoing research project, EASE, in which philosophical phenomenology is integrated with more traditional approaches to schizophrenia research. A number of problems with this specific act of integration are pointed out. Indeed, there are a lot of good things to say about the EASE-project. The basic idea is certainly a good one, and it has the potential to significantly improve how we understand and handle schizophrenia. Nevertheless, approach-based analysis reveals considerable epistemic problems related to the specific approach in focus.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We need to distinguish clearly between the EASE project and the distinct constitutive approaches as presented in individual publications. To repeat myself: An approach-based analysis of interdisciplinary activities requires focus on one interdisciplinary approach (at a time). As discussed in several places above, in approach-based analysis specific research projects (or programmes, perhaps) are considered to be bundles of closely related approaches. A discipline, on the other hand, is considered to be a bundle (of bundles) of approaches. For convenience and clarity, I will use ‘NP2014’ to refer to the approach in focus in this case study and ‘EASE’ to refer the bundle, of which NP2014 is a constitutive element.

  2. 2.

    With the important caveat that I am not a trained psychiatrist. Consequently, I do not possess the competences to carry out any kind of psychiatric diagnostics with or without the EASE-methods involved.

  3. 3.

    Short for ‘Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders’ (published the American Psychiatric Association) and ‘The International Classification of Diseases’ (published by WHO).

  4. 4.

    In Hvidtfeldt (2011), I analysed differences between how anxiety patients and psychiatrists described what it is to suffer from anxiety. Interestingly, in the patients’ descriptions expressions such ‘being afraid’, ‘feeling scared’, ‘to panic, or ‘feeling terrified’ were absolutely central, but these played only a very minor role in descriptions of anxiety by the psychiatrists.

  5. 5.

    Another interesting finding of (Hvidtfeldt 2011) was that anxiety patients in some cases seemed to develop the official symptoms of anxiety only after being presented with the suspicion that anxiety might be the explanation for some indeterminable somatic complaint (such as more or less chronic bellyache) for which they had consulted their GP. Importantly, the symptoms of anxiety are perfectly healthy reactions in threatening situations. Indeed, it does not seem completely irrational to be more than a little alarmed by being diagnosed with a mental disorder.

  6. 6.

    For interesting philosophical discussions of delusions and double bookkeeping, see Bortolotti 2010a, b; Murphy 2012.

  7. 7.

    It would not be unreasonable to describe EASE as mainly proceeding in the polymath mode with all the associated risks discussed in Chap. 3. Even though it is an interesting topic, I shall refrain from providing anecdotal evidence for this claim, since it is not central to the goal of this case study.

  8. 8.

    All items are discussed in some detail and exemplified in (Parnas et al. 2005, pp. 240–256), to which I refer the interested reader.

  9. 9.

    Recall Hacking’s notion of “interactive kinds” briefly mentioned above.

  10. 10.

    Apart from his opinion about the utility of phenomenology in studies of genesis, it is interesting that Jaspers appear to express a strong disdain for interdisciplinarity in this quote. The danger of “cerebral mythologies” can best be understood along the lines of “the seductive allure of neuroscience” discussed in Chap. 3 (Weisberg et al. 2008). Certainly, Jaspers did not endorse a strong medical model.

  11. 11.

    This is likely to be the case even if we ignore the significant problems of false positives and false negatives which plague psychiatric diagnostics (Cohen 1994, p. 998 f.).

  12. 12.

    Josef Parnas has published extensively on various problems of contemporary psychiatry, for instance those related to operationalisation (Parnas and Bovet 2014).

  13. 13.

    In the technical sense of a dynamical system which is highly sensitive to initial conditions. See Kellert 2009 for an interesting discussion of chaos theory and interdisciplinarity.

  14. 14.

    In a less friendly tone, Kieran Healy criticises reliance on the sophisticated judgment of people in possession of esoteric expertise. He claims that a “weak methodological core invites connoisseurs”, and that “[…] connoisseurship thrives best in settings where judgment is needed but measurement is hard” (Healy 2017).

  15. 15.

    This is most apparent in live interview sessions and video recordings. For examples in print, see Parnas et al. (2005).

  16. 16.

    That is, “Ideas Implying Nonphysical Causality” (Parnas et al. 2005, p. 255). Examples could be the belief that hoping for something to happen will affect whether it happens or not, or that the weather is somehow affected by one’s mood.

  17. 17.

    Certainly, it would not take a talented evolutionary psychologist very long to come up with a list of advantages related to an optimum level of self-disturbance. For instance, it might be easier to maintain a high spirit if one’s somewhat disturbed view of the world would facilitate the “re-interpretation” of facts to fit one’s preferences better.

  18. 18.

    Which the authors of NP2014 are well aware of, of course, and make use of in other contexts (Parnas et al. 2011, p. 201).

  19. 19.

    The importance of this point is not diminished by (EASE) studies suggesting high interrater reliability such as presented in (Møller et al. 2011; Nordgaard and Parnas 2012). High interrater reliability may suggest, but does not demonstrate neutrality (i.e. immunity towards bias). Further, unfortunately, the mentioned interrater reliability studies are not terribly convincing. Though the raters compared were blinded to diagnostic and clinical information in the studies, they did not rate on the basis of independent interviews. Actually, they were either both present during the interview or re-rated on the basis of videotaped interviews. Since a central reason for doing semi-structured interviews is the possibility of addressing interesting issues in detail, it is hardly surprising if a second rater notices the same interesting topics that the interviewer finds worth pursuing in more detail.

  20. 20.

    In spite of these hypothesised smaller effect sizes, one might still get significant results, of course, but that might require substantially larger samples.

  21. 21.

    “Prodromal” is used to capture a phase in which symptoms of an illness are experienced before the full-blown syndrome has developed. The concept implies that the development of the full-blown illness is inevitable (Phillips et al. 2005). In the case of schizophrenia, it is often negative symptoms that appear in the prodromal phase. This is in part a consequence of the requirement of at least one positive symptom for being diagnosed with schizophrenia.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. 1980. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. Edited by American Psychiatric Association. 3rd ed. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. 4th ed. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. 4th ed. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. Edited by American Psychiatric Association. 5th ed. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, Nancy C. 2007. DSM and the Death of Phenomenology in America: An Example of Unintended Consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33 (1): 108–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, German E. 1992. Phenomenology, Psychopathology and Jaspers: A Conceptual History. History of Psychiatry 3 (11): 303–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, Lisa. 2010a. Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs, International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Double Bookkeeping in Delusions: Explaining the Gap between Saying and Doing. In New Waves in the Philosophy of Action, ed. K. Frankish, A. Buckareff, and J. Aguilar. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Jacob. 1994. The Earth is Round (P < .05). American Psychologist 49 (12): 997–1003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everitt, Brian S. 1987. Statistics in Psychiatry. Statistical Science 2 (2): 107–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fulford, K.W.M., et al. 2006. Oxford Textbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Steven N. 2016. Aligning Statistical and Scientific Reasoning. Science 352 (6290): 1180–1181. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aaf5406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1998. Mad Travelers: Reflections on the Reality of Transient Mental Illnesses. Charlottesville, VA: University Press of Virginia.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, Kieran. 2017. Fuck Nuance. Sociological Theory 35 (2): 118–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hvidtfeldt, Rolf. 2011. Conceptual Plasticity—A Sober Constructivist Account of Categorization + Consequences. Master thesis, Philosophy, University of Copenhagen.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Sådan får man et diagnosebarn. VERA—tidsskrift for pædagoger 74: 54–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, Karl. 1912. Die phänomenologische Forschungsrichtung in der Psychopathologie. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie ix: 391–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. General Psychopathology. Translated by J. Hoenig and M. Hamilton. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1968. The Phenomenological Approach in Psychopathology. The British Journal of Psychiatry 114 (516): 1313–1323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, Stephen H. 2009. Borrowed Knowledge: Chaos Theory and the Challange of Learning Across Desciplines. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Patricia. 1992. Freud’s Dream: A Complete Interdisciplinary Science of Mind. Cambridge, MA; London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Freud’s Interdisciplinary Fiasco. In The Prehistory of Cognitive Science, ed. Andrew Brook, 230–249. Basingstoke, UK; New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvale, Steinar, and Svend Brinkmann. 2009. Interviews—Learning the Craft of Qualitative Research Interviewing. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Likert, Rensis. 1932. A Technique for the Measurement of Attitudes. Archives of Psychology 140: 1–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medin, Douglas L., et al. 1997. Categorization and Reasoning among Tree Experts: Do All Roads Lead to Rome? Cognitive Psychology 32: 49–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller, Paul, et al. 2011. Examination of Anomalous Self-experience in First-Episode Psychosis: Interrater Reliability. Psychopathology 44: 386–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møller, Paul, and R. Husby. 2000. The Initial Prodrome in Schizophrenia: Searching for Naturalistic Core Dimensions of Experience and Behavior. Schizophrenia Bulletin 26: 217–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Dominic. 2006. Psychiatry in the Scientific Image. UK: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Folk Epistemology of Delusions Dominic Murphy. Neuroethics 5: 19–22. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9125-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordgaard, Julie, and Josef Parnas. 2012. A Semi Structured, Phenomenologically-Oriented Psychiatric Interview: Descriptive Congruence in Assessing Anomalous Subjective Experience and Mental Status. Clinical Neuropsychiatry 9 (3): 123–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Self-disorders and the Schizophrenia Spectrum: A Study of 100 First Hospital Admissions. Schizophrenia Bulletin 40 (6): 1300–1307. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbt239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, Josef. 2000. The Self and Intentionality in the Pre-Psychotic Stages of Schizophrenia. A Phenomenological Study. In Exploring the Self, ed. Dan Zahavi, 115–147. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, Josef, et al. 1998. Self-experience in the Prodromal Phases of Schizophrenia. Neurology, Psychiatry and Brain Research 6: 97–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. EASE: Examination of Anomalous Self-experience. Psychopathology 38: 236–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Self-experience in the Early Phases of Schizophrenia: 5-Year Follow-Up of the Copenhagen Prodromal Study. World Psychiatry 10: 200–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Rediscovering Psychopathology: The Epistemology and Phenomenology of the Psychiatric Object. Schizophrenia Bulletin 39 (2): 270–277. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbs153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, Josef, and Dan Zahavi. 2002. The Role of Phenomenology in Psychiatric Diagnosis and Classification. In Psychiatric Diagnosis and Classification, ed. Mario Maj, Wolfgang Gaebel, Juan Jose López-Ibor, and Norman Sartorius. Chichester, UK: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, Josef, and Pierre Bovet. 2014. Psychiatry Made Easy: Operation(al)ism and Some of Its Consequences. In Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry III: The Nature and Sources of Historical Change, ed. Kenneth S. Kendler and Josef Parnas. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, Lisa J., et al. 2005. Prepsychotic Phase of Schizophrenia and Related Disorders: Recent Progress and Future Opportunities. The British Journal of Psychiatry 187 (48): 33–44. https://doi.org/10.1192/bjp.187.48.s33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raballo, Andrea, and Josef Parnas. 2011. The Silent Side of the Spectrum: Schizotypy and the Schizotaxic Self. Schizophrenia Bulletin 37 (5): 1017–1026. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbq008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saha, Sukanta, et al. 2007. A Systematic Review of Mortality in Schizophrenia: Is the Differential Mortality Gap Worsening Over Time? Archives of General Psychiatry 64 (10): 1123–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, Louis A. 2013. Jaspers, Phenomenology, and the ‘Ontological Difference’. In One Century of Karl Jaspers’ General Psychopathology, ed. Giovanni Stanghellini and Thomas Fuchs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Delusion and Double Book-Keeping. In Karl Jaspers’ Philosophy and Psychopathology, ed. Thomas Fuchs, Thiemo Breyer, and Christoph Mundt, 125–148. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, Louis A., and Josef Parnas. 2003. Schizophrenia, Consciousness, and the Self. Schizophrenia Bulletin 29 (3): 427–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, Joseph P., et al. 2011. False-Positive Psychology: Undisclosed Flexibility in Data Collection and Analysis Allows Presenting Anything as Significant. Psychological Science 22: 1359–1366. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797611417632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonsohn, Uri, et al. 2014. P-Curve: A Key to the File-Drawer. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 143 (2): 534–547. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0033242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, David W. 2013. Phenomenology. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Ed.), ed. Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/phenomenology/.

  • Tandon, Rajiv, et al. 2013. Definition and Description of Schizophrenia in the DSM-5. Schizophrenia Research 150 (1): 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, L., et al. 1981. DSM-Ill Training Guide for Use with the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagrostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. 3rd ed. New York: Brunner/Mazel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, Deena Skolnick, et al. 2008. The Seductive Allure of Neuroscience Explanations. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 20 (3): 470–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organization. 1992. The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioral Disorders. Geneva: World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2005. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating First Person Perspective. Cambrigde, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hvidtfeldt, R. (2018). Phenomenology Imported with EASE. In: The Structure of Interdisciplinary Science. New Directions in the Philosophy of Science. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-90872-4_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics