Skip to main content

Disciplines and Approaches

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover The Structure of Interdisciplinary Science

Part of the book series: New Directions in the Philosophy of Science ((NDPS))

  • 418 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, the most common ways of distinguishing between branches of science are criticised for focusing too narrowly on a few dimensions of a highly complex phenomenon. Some usually neglected aspects are pointed out, which are required for a more adequate account of disciplinarity. The complexity of disciplines, however, renders an adequate concept hereof more or less useless as the foundation for analyses of specific cases of interdisciplinarity. “Discipline” and related concepts are compared to the alternative “approach”, which, it is argued, will serve us better as the basic unit of analyses of scientific crossbreeding. The thought that disciplines should be considered as bundles (of bundles) of approaches is discussed and some consequences are drawn.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For instance, in terms of topics of interest, central aspects of methodology, paradigmatic examples of good practice, as well as theoretical background assumptions (Fauconnier and Turner 2002; Lakoff 1987; Margolis and Laurence 1999; Murphy 2002).

  2. 2.

    Just think of how Kant considered arithmetic to be the synthetic a priori truths of time, while he considered geometry to be the synthetic a priori truths of space [4:283].

  3. 3.

    —which is “a constant source of both delight and achievement among mathematicians” (Hacking 2014, p. 9).

  4. 4.

    As explicitly stated in the quotation above, Darden and Maul do indeed include problems in their characteristic of fields, as well.

  5. 5.

    According to www.oxforddictionaries.com, an approach is “a way of dealing with a situation or problem”. In the present context, of course, focus is on representational approaches, and the situation or problem is how to scientifically represent some phenomena. You can decide to adopt an entirely different approach or to slightly alter your present approach. Pretty straightforward, in my opinion.

  6. 6.

    There are some difficulties related to applying the exact same approach to different targets, though. These issues will be addressed in Chap. 7.

  7. 7.

    Indeed, grasping the concept “skill” may require some sort of meta-skill. In the words of Collins and Evans: “[S]kills [are] notoriously hard to explain—as qualitative sociologists know to their cost” (2002, p. 258).

References

  • Aldrich, John H. 2014. Interdisciplinarity. New York: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Barry. 1974. Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Interests and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, William, ed. 1986. Integrating Scientific Disciplines. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, David. 1976. Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, Donald T. 1969. Ethnocentrism of Disciplines and the Fish-Scale Model of Omniscience. In Interdisciplinary Relationships in the Social Sciences, ed. Muzafer Sherif and Carolyn W. Sherif. Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carp, Joshua. 2012. The Secret Lives of Experiments: Methods Reporting in the fMRI Literature. NeuroImage 63: 289–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry M. 1985. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, Harry M., and Robert Evans. 2002. The Third Wave of Science Studies: Studies of Expertise and Experience. Social Studies of Science 32 (2): 235–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, Lindley, and Nancy Maull. 1977. Interfield Theories. Philosophy of Science 44 (1): 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • EC. 2014. Guidance for Evaluators of Horizon 2020 Proposals. [pdf]. EC. Last modified 26 September 2014. Accessed 8 Januray. http://ec.europa.eu/research/participants/data/ref/h2020/grants_manual/pse/h2020-evaluation-faq_en.pdf.

  • Fauconnier, Gilles, and Mark Turner. 2002. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. New York; Great Britain: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison, Peter. 2008. Ten Problems in History and Philosophy of Science. Isis 99 (1): 111–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, Gerd, Zeno Swijtink, Theodore Porter, Lorraine Daston, John Beatty, and Lorenz Kruger. 1989. The Empire of Chance: How Probability Changed Science and Everyday Life (Ideas in Context). Vol. 12. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 2014. Why is There Philosophy of Mathematics at All? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, David L. 1982. Exemplars and Scientific Change. In Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, Stephen H. 2009. Borrowed Knowledge: Chaos Theory and the Challange of Learning Across Desciplines. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Patricia. 1992. Freud’s Dream: A Complete Interdisciplinary Science of Mind. Cambridge, MA; London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Freud’s Interdisciplinary Fiasco. In The Prehistory of Cognitive Science, ed. Andrew Brook, 230–249. Basingstoke, UK; New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, Joseph J., ed. 1979a. Interdisciplinarity and Higher Education. Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979b. Science and Discipline: Some Historical and Critical Reflections. In Interdisciplinarity and Higher Education, ed. Joseph J. Kockelmans. Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science: Foundations of the Unity of Science V. 2, No. 2. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Foundations of the Unity of Science, V. 2, No. 2. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, Imre. 1970. Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 91–196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, Imre, and Alan Musgrave. 1970. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind. Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, Eric, and Stephen Laurence. 1999. Concepts: Core Readings. Cambridge, MA; London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Gregory L. 2002. The Big Book of Concepts. Cambridge, MA; London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nissani, Moti. 1997. Ten Cheers for Interdisciplinarity: The Case for Interdisciplinary Knowledge and Research. Social Science Journal 34 (2): 201–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, Dudley. 1974. Galileo: A Philosophical Study. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Reason and the Search for Knowledge: Investigations in the Philosophy of Science, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherif, Muzafer. 1979. Crossdisciplinary Coordination in the Social Sciences. In Interdisciplinarity and Higher Education, ed. Joseph J. Kockelmans. Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen. 1972. Human Understanding. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Stephen. 2000. What are Disciplines? And How is Interdisciplinarity Different? In Practising Interdisciplinarity, ed. Peter Weingart and Nico Stehr. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hvidtfeldt, R. (2018). Disciplines and Approaches. In: The Structure of Interdisciplinary Science. New Directions in the Philosophy of Science. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-90872-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics