Skip to main content

The Physical Action Theory of Trying

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Metaphysics of Action
  • 305 Accesses

Abstract

I introduce the idea that an act of trying is identical to some physical action. Identity requires (at least) one-one correspondence: for each token trying act, there would have be one and only one token physical act (of course, namely itself) with which it is identical. There are two obstacles to the physical action theory of trying that are the opposite of one another: first, the availability of too many particular physical action tokens, and second, the lack of any. My discussion of the too-many-tokens problem leads me into a consideration of what I call the ‘mereological strategy’. I argue that that strategy fails but I leave it open whether or not some non-mereological parallel strategy might succeed. Finally, I look at the lack-of-any-physical-tokens problem, sometimes called ‘naked trying’. I sharpen the argument from the premiss that there are naked tryings to the conclusion that the physical identity theory fails. I believe that it is a scientifically established fact that there are such cases (it’s not just a matter about one’s ‘philosophical intuitions’ about such cases) and I examine two attempts to circumvent the naked trying argument and I conclude that they are unsuccessful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 24.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 32.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Jennifer Hornsby (1980) identifies trying as an internal event (‘…[tryings]are always internal events’ (1980s, 45)) and hence places tryings on the inside of the agent. Other volitionists include Hugh McCann (1998), Paul Pietroski (2000), Brian O’Shaughnessy (1980) and Carl Ginet (1990).

  2. 2.

    Olivier Massin’s particularist view of trying is more complicated: the trying is identified with an action done with a certain intention, i.e., Julie’s trying to open the door=her pushing [of] the door with the intention of opening it (Massin 2013, and in private correspondence).

  3. 3.

    These issues are covered in Gozanno, Simone and Christopher Hill, editors, 2012.

  4. 4.

    Throughout the book, I call a theory of act individuation austere if it finds the multiplicity in the descriptions, so that ‘his improving of the inhabitants’ lives’, ‘his stopping of the flood’, ‘his closing of the sluice’, ‘his turning of the valve’, and ‘his bending of his finger’ are all descriptions of a single action. A theory of act individuation is prolific if it finds the multiplicity in the actions themselves rather than in the descriptions. There are degrees of prolificacy: the most prolific theory holds that the above list names five distinct actions. A less prolific theory might hold that the list names less than five but more than one action.

  5. 5.

    Why the same result does not follow for substances, or for certain events and actions, is a long story, assumed to be true but not to be told here at any length. Briefly, two strategies are these: properties are (1) either time-indexed or world-indexed when ascribed for instance to a substance, (2) or ascribed not to the whole substance but to one of its temporal parts.

  6. 6.

    Peter Simons, Parts: A Study in Ontology, OUP, 2000, who disagrees.

  7. 7.

    Simon Evnine (2016) ‘The times at which they are performed, therefore, cannot in general be essential to the identity of actions.’

  8. 8.

    William James describes the cases of the patients of Dr. Landry and Professor Strümpell. See William James (1950), 490–492.

  9. 9.

    See for example some of the literature, and quotations, in the note below this one.

  10. 10.

    Here are several recent major discussions of effort or exertion in which it is simply assumed that trying or attempting always also occurs and that it is not to be identified with exertion or effort:

    1. 1.

      ‘Exertion is accompanied by a sensation of strain and labour, a feeling that intensifies the harder a person tries’, ‘even if capacity is completely extinguished so that efferent activity is not possible (e.g., in paralysis), then no effort is felt even when intentionally trying to move’, ‘When people are trying to solve problems together, effort experiences can be the basis for unintended plagiarism’ (Jesse Preston and Daniel Wegner (2008), quotes from 570, 571, 578 respectively).

    2. 2.

      Similarly in a second patient…futile attempts to abduct or extend the fingers were described as follows: ‘My fingers felt normal but I could not move them. I knew what I was trying to do…but I could not feel any effort in it at all’, ‘To determine whether sensations of effort could arise when the limbs were not only paralysed but also insentient four patients with spinal transections were interviewed. These patients were aware of sensations of effort when first attempting to move their paralysed limbs…when specifically asked to try and move their limbs, patients said that the feeling of effort or heaviness remained’, ‘…during the stage of complete paralysis of upper motor neuron type patients were aware of their failed attempts to move. But they did not feel the sense of effort…’ ‘Two patients, who suddenly became hemiplegic, without sensory symptoms, noted that attempts to move when movement first returned were accompanied by distinct sensations of effort or heaviness’ (S. C. Gandevia 1982, quotes from 154, 155, 157).

    3. 3.

      ‘Subjects with experimental paralysis of one limb experience strong sensations of effort when they attempt to move that limb…The same hypothesis would account for permanence of sensations of effort in all cases of distal paralysis, where corticofugal pathways are not altered’ (M. Jeannerod 1995, 1429).

  11. 11.

    See Sarah Paul (2009) for a good discussion of the options for understanding intention.

  12. 12.

    See for example Thor Grünbaum (2008); Richard Taylor (1973), 82–85, ‘The Paralyzed Man’; Timothy Cleveland (1997), chapter 6; George Wilson (1989), 151–167. Irving Thalberg is excessive in his judgment: ‘Vesey … rebutted several versions of it [that there is naked trying] … Richard Taylor demolished an enticing reconstruction of it…Yet it comes back to haunt us…’ (Thalberg 1983, 137). Indeed, so it does. And here I am, to haunt again.

  13. 13.

    There is a view that even belief has a phenomenology, that there is something it is like to believe that p. See David Pitt (2011).

  14. 14.

    That ubiquity thesis must be something like this, where ‘F’ ranges over physical actions types and ‘x’ ranges over physical action tokens: (TUT) (Nec) (x) (F) (if P does a token action x of type F intentionally→ P tries to F).

  15. 15.

    If he succeeds in F-ing in spite of his subjective certainty that he can’t, it isn’t the case that he has F-ed intentionally. (I defend this view more fully in Chap. 4).

  16. 16.

    Wilson begs the question when he argues for the proper use of ‘performs’ in connection with muscular contractions, which he says ‘are part of the exercise of my normal control over my body’ (p. 164), thereby conflating the idea of things an agent controls with the idea of causes of his control. The expression ‘are part of’ could be taken in either sense.

  17. 17.

    See also Michael Bratman (2006), 5–19.

Bibliography

  • Annas, Julia. 1977. How Basic are Basic Actions? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society LXXVIII: 195–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, Jonathan. 1998. The Act Itself. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael. 2006. What is the Accordion Effect? Journal of Ethics 10 (1): 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckareff, A. 2007. Mental Overpopulation and Mental Action: Protecting Intentions from Mental Birth Control. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (1): 49–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleveland, Timothy. 1997. Trying Without Willing. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, L. 1979. Theory of Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 1996. Criminal Attempts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehring, Douglas. 1997. Causation & Persistence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evnine, Simon. 2011. Constitution and Composition: Three Approaches to Their Relation. ProtoSociology 27: 212–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Making Object and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1970. Doing and Deserving. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gandevia, S.C. 1982. The Perception of Motor Commands or Effort During Muscular Paralysis. Brain 105: 151–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, Carl. 1990. On Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 1970. A Theory of Human Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, Thor. 2008. Trying and the Argument from Total Failure. Philosophia 36 (1): 67–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, Jennifer. 1980. Actions. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Reasons for Trying. Journal of Philosophical Research XX: 525–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1950. Principles of Psychology. Vol. 2. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. 1995. Mental Imagery in the Motor Context. Neuropsychologica 33 (11): 419–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. Philosophical Papers. Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, Lawrence. 1986. Events: A Metaphysical Study. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, Olivier. 2013. L’Explication de l’action. Analyses contemporaines, Recherches sur la philosophie et le langage, no. 30, Vrin, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCann, Hugh. 1975. Trying, Paralysis, and Volition. The Review of Metaphysics 28 (3): 423–442. Reprinted in McCann (1998), 94–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. The Works of Agency. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Shaughnessy, Brian. 1980. The Will. Vol. 1 and 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattaro, Enrico. 2005. A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence. Vol. 1. Dordrect, Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, Sarah. 2009. How We Know What We are Doing. Philosophers’ Imprint 9 (11): 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, Paul. 2000. Causing Actions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, David. 2011. Introspection, Phenomenality. And the Availability of Intentional Content. In Cognitive Phenomenology, ed. Tim Bayne and Michelle Montague, 141–173. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, Jesse, and Daniel Wegner. 2008. Elbow Grease: When Action Feels Like Work. In Oxford Handbook of Human Action, ed. E. Morsella, John Bargh, and Peter Gollwitzer, 569–586. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Peter. 2000. Parts: A Study in Ontology. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Richard. 1973. Action and Purpose. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thalberg, Irving. 1983. Misconceptions of Mind and Freedom. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, George. 1989. The Intentionality of Human Action. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Notebooks 1914–16. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ruben, DH. (2018). The Physical Action Theory of Trying. In: The Metaphysics of Action. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-90347-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics