Skip to main content

Another Dissimilarity between Moral Virtue and Skills: An Interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics II 4

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 607 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 20))

Abstract

In Nicomachean Ethics II 4 Aristotle famously raises a puzzle concerning moral habituation, and he seems to dissolve it by recourse to the analogy between moral virtue and skills. A new interpretation of the chapter is offered on the basis of an important evaluative dissimilarity then noted by Aristotle, one almost universally disregarded by interpreters of the chapter. I elucidate the nature of the dissimilarity in question and argue for its paramount importance for understanding Aristotle’s conception of moral agency. I also show that it is the particularly intricate and puzzling character of the chapter that has prevented scholars from noticing such a dissimilarity and from integrating it to the interpretation of the chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For Annas ’ skill-based account of virtue , see Annas (2011).

  2. 2.

    And perhaps also from simply recognising the dissimilarity itself. A good example is Tom Angier ’s recent book, where he does not even consider Nicomachean Ethics II 4 as containing an argument against the ‘evaluative’ assimilation of moral virtue to skills (see Angier (2010, pp. 41–49)). Some interpreters have even attributed to Aristotle some sort of consequentialist assimilation of virtuous agency to skills concerning the way they contribute to the value of their typical products. The most prominent example is Sauvé Meyer (2011, p. 47 and p. 162). Her view serves as an example of the sort of consequentialist view I have mentioned.

  3. 3.

    I will be using Bywater 1894 edition of the Ethica Nicomachea. All translations are my own, unless otherwise indicated.

  4. 4.

    This is for instance the interpretation of Grant (1885), Joachim (1951) and Taylor (2006) (see their commentaries ad loc.).

  5. 5.

    Stewart (1892, p. 182). Italics are mine.

  6. 6.

    Cf. τὸ κατὰ τὴν ἐν αὑτῷ γραμματικήν (1105a25), τά κατὰ τὰς ἀρετὰς γινόμενα (1105a28–9).

  7. 7.

    John Burnet , for instance, suggests that the prepositions ὑπό and κατά ‘correspond to the distinction between ποιεῖν and πράττειν, ἔργον and πρᾶξις’ respectively (Burnet (1900, p. 87)). The same interpretation is advanced by Gauthier and Jolif (1970, p. 130).

  8. 8.

    The phrase with ὑπό is not necessarily Aristotle’s stock phrase to refer to artifacts . Whereas he sometimes uses this phrase (e.g. EN 1175a24), he also uses the phrase with κατά in other places (e.g. Ph. 193a32).

  9. 9.

    Broadie and Rowe (2002, p. 300). Italics are my own. For similar interpretations, see also Tricot (1959, p. 98), Annas (1993, p. 68), and more recently Jimenez (2016, p. 16).

  10. 10.

    Broadie and Rowe (2002, translation ad loc.).

  11. 11.

    Or ‘have their goodness in themselves’ (Ross) or ‘ont leur valeur en elles-mêmes’ (Tricot). In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle tends to use τὸ εὖ and τὸ ἀγαθόν interchangeably (e.g. EN 1097b27).

  12. 12.

    In fact, there are reasons to think with Arthur Adkins that the traditional conception of ἀρετή reinforced this natural suggestion. Adkins argues that such a conception, ‘from Homer onwards, always commended the correct reaction, or the production of the correct result, in a given situation, regardless of the manner in which the result was produced or the intentions of the agent’, adding that ‘the explicit linking of εὐδαιμονία and ἀρετή merely emphasised this’ (1963, p. 332). Adkins himself suggests that the first in the history of philosophy to remove this ‘chief impediment’ was in fact Aristotle (p. 334), by insisting that any action performed from ἀρετή must satisfy certain conditions internal to the agent. I think Adkins was right.

  13. 13.

    The clearest interpretation along these lines is Alexander Grant ’s (1885, commentary ad loc.). His view is that T2 helps to solve the aporia about habituation by somehow reinforcing the analogical argument initially offered by Aristotle to dissolve it. For the point of this analogical argument was to show that if we have reason to suppose that mere getting F-things done is not proof of the possession of skill , then we have reason to suppose that it is no proof of the possession of moral virtue either. If Aristotle’s second argument now in T2 consists in arguing that, whereas an artifact can be judged as being good by its intrinsic properties, mere doing of ‘just things’ or ‘moderate things’ cannot be so judged, it follows that it is even more evident that in the case of moral virtues the mere doings of these things do not imply the possession of a just or moderate character by the agent: for how could they have such implication if, strictly speaking, these ‘things’ are not even moderate or just? I find Grant ’s interpretation unconvincing. Aristotle evidently thinks that merely getting just things done is no proof of the possession of justice, not because it cannot be characterised as ‘moderate’, ‘just’, etc., but rather because, although it can be so characterised, there are (as he claims in T3) further conditions internal to the agent performing these actions that need to be fulfilled in order for the agent to count as just or moderate.

  14. 14.

    See for instance Hutchinson (1986, pp. 90–91); Irwin (1999, p. 195); Taylor (2006, p. 83). These scholars ssuppose that in order for something to count as having ‘artistic merit’ you needed the knowledge condition. Hence, on this interpretation, you need the knowledge condition in order for something to count as a just or moderate deed too. It is now supposed that Aristotle’s point in T2 is merely to point out that in order for these deeds to count as done justly or moderately and thus to imply the possession of character you need further inward conditions besides the knowledge condition. This contributes to the initial analogical argument simply because the distinction between the knowledge condition and such further inward conditions (acting from rational choice and full possession of character) is perfectly adequate to account for the distinction between ‘the just, etc. deed’ and ‘the just, etc. deed done justly’. The just deed is done with the relevant knowledge , and is the one involved in habituation; the just deed done justly requires further inward conditions and it is the one arising from virtuous character. It should be clear by now that I reject this reading. The knowledge condition is not needed in order for something to count as a just or moderate deed or outcome. Moreover, this reading flagrantly ignores the significance of the evaluative disanalogy, and also misinterprets the initial distinction between (i) artifacts and (ii) bringing them about in a skillful way that is the basis of the analogy – what can now be the basis of this distinction, if the knowledge condition applies equally to both?

  15. 15.

    See also Rh. 1374a9–17 and EN 1136a1–4.

  16. 16.

    Cf. EN 1113b26–7, 1114a12–16.

Bibliography

Ancient Texts

  • Annas, J. (1993). The Morality of Happiness. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1894). In I. Bywater (Ed.), Aristotelis Ethica Nicomachea. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Modern Texts

  • Adkins, A. (1963). Merit and responsibility: A study in Greek values. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angier, T. (2010). Technê in Aristotle’s ethics: Crafting the moral life. London: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, S., & Rowe, C. (2002). Aristotle: Nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnet, J. (1900). The ethics of Aristotle. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, R. A., & Jolif, J. Y. (1970). L’ Éthique à Nicomaque. Introduction, traduction et commentaire, vol. 1. Louvain and Paris: Publications Universitaires.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant, A. (1885). The Ethics of Aristotle, 4th Edn, 2 Vols. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, D. S. (1986). The virtues of Aristotle. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. (1999). Aristotle: Nicomachean ethics (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jimenez, M. (2016). Aristotle on becoming virtuous by doing virtuous actions. Phronesis, 61, 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joachim, H. H. (1951). Aristotle: The Nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauvé-Meyer, S. (2011). Aristotle on moral responsibility: Character and cause. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. A. (1892). Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. C. W. (2006). Aristotle: Nicomachean ethics books II-IV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tricot, J. (1959). Éthique a Nicomaque. Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier Echeñique .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Echeñique, J. (2018). Another Dissimilarity between Moral Virtue and Skills: An Interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics II 4. In: Boeri, M.D., Kanayama, Y.Y., Mittelmann, J. (eds) Soul and Mind in Greek Thought. Psychological Issues in Plato and Aristotle. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-78547-9_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics