Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 20))

  • 636 Accesses

Abstract

Although philosophy of mind is a hot topic in contemporary philosophy, Ancient theories of the mind are not usually taken into consideration. In this Introduction we briefly focus on some of the reasons why the Ancient conceptions of the mind tend not to be considered seriously any more. We try to account for why it is still reasonable to study some theories that apparently have been overcome by contemporary science of the mind. Although one can grant that Ancient theories of the mind may not be a starting point for a contemporary philosopher of mind, we suggest that the approaches of the Ancient philosophers still provide insights to those who are interested in investigating the mind-body problem. Ancient discussions of the mind, we hold, should not be taken as archeological pieces that can be easily neglected. Even though we recognize that some ingredients of Ancient theories in fact are ‘archeological’ (especially those elements related to physiological aspects), we hold that their philosophical analysis, inasmuch as it can contribute to clarifying problems that have not been resolved yet, can be dealt with seriously. Finally, this Introduction also describes briefly the contents of this book.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Crane and Patterson (eds.) (2000, p. 3, note 8).

  2. 2.

    Those authored by Langton, Stone , and Patterson (all of them included in Crane and Patterson (eds.) (2000)).

  3. 3.

    Crane and Patterson (eds.) (2000, p. 2).

  4. 4.

    Lowe (2008, p. 149, note 8).

  5. 5.

    Lowe (2013, p. 230).

  6. 6.

    In addition to the just mentioned works by Lowe, see also Cartwright (1989) and Fine (1994).

  7. 7.

    Crane and Patterson (eds.) (2000) do not seem to endorse this view, as they appear to take seriously Ancient theories as a reasonable historical antecedent of contemporary theories.

  8. 8.

    For discussion see Annas (1992, p. 54).

  9. 9.

    Pl. Phd. 105c9-d4; Arist. de An. 402a6–7.

  10. 10.

    This is understood as a ‘nutritive and reproductive capacity of the soul’: ἡ αὐτὴ δύναμις τῆς ψυχῆς θρεπτικὴ καὶ γεννητική (de An. 416a19).

  11. 11.

    He supplies several arguments for the claim that the soul continues to live after the physical death (Phd. 69e-84b, 102a-107b; Phdr. 245c-e, 246a; R. 608c5-612a7; Lg. 893b-895a). To be sure, Plato acknowledges the existence of the mortal kinds of the soul (the spirited and appetitive kinds) in the Timaeus (see 69c-70a; cf. also 61c, 65a, 70d-71a, 72d), but the important point for us is Plato’s claim that the soul can continue to exist after the individual’s death. This possibility is reserved just to its rational part.

  12. 12.

    This is a more or less usual (and probably wrong) way of rendering the difficult Greek expressions αὐτὸ τὸ αὐτό, αὐτὸ ταὐτό (Alc. I 130b1, d4). This interpretation surely assumes that in the analogy with the crafts the αὐτὸ τὸ αὐτό is the self, the soul, or the person. However, as observed by Gill (2006, p.347), the English term ‘self’ is ‘a rather peculiar usage, representing the conversion of a reflexive suffix (as in ‘himself’) into a noun’. But the Greek αὐτὸ τὸ αὐτό doesn’t mean a fundamentally reflexive relationship, but ‘what is the core or essential feature of the itself’ (349). Pradeau (2000, p. 210) proposes ‘ce soi-meme lui-meme’ as a reasonable rendering of αὐτὸ τὸ αὐτό, although he warns us that his translation renders a ‘redondance pronominale assez inhabituelle’. In the nineteenth century, especially due to the authority of Schleiermacher, the authenticity of this dialogue has been questioned. Some contemporary scholars also forcefully challenge the authenticity of Alcibiades I, notably Smith (2004) and, more recently, Renaud and Tarrant (2015), who tend to support the inauthenticity (pp. 38, 46). However, they declare that their purpose is ‘to explore the hypothesis that the dialogue may be interpreted along the same lines as any other dialogue of Plato’ (p. 5). Some other interpreters tend to take Alc. I to be authentic (Annas (1983, pp. 114–115), cited by Gill (2006, p. 344). See also Pradeau (2000, pp. 20–29); Denyer (2001, pp. 14–26). Gerson (2003, p.14, note 1) prefers not to take a strong position on the authenticity — both of the Theages and the Alc. I —, although he tends to accept their authenticity).

  13. 13.

    As observed by Long (2005, p.174), philosophy of mind is a relatively recent discipline ‘indelibly coloured by Descartes and the sharp distinction he introduced between the physical and the mental. Inasmuch as Plato discusses such concepts as belief, desire, pleasure, action, and emotion, he can be brought into contact with what we call philosophy of mind. But the mind/body distinction, in the way it has preoccupied modern philosophy, has only partial bearing on the Platonic dualism of body and psyche’. In spite of the differences between Plato and Descartes, both philosophers share the view that the soul has a nature such that it will continue to live after death (i.e. independently of the body). But, of course, there are important differences between them as well: in its most technical use, soul appears to be distinguished from mind by Descartes, the former being able to animate the body, and the latter being responsible for intuiting, thinking, and imagining. Descartes usually employs the expression l’esprit and mens when making reference to mind as something different from the body. By contrast, l’âme and anima designate the mind in its union with the body. On the difficulties concerning the word ‘mind’ to understand Plato’s psyche cf. Griswold (1996, pp. 2–3). Besides, in Modern philosophy (maybe due to Descartes’ influence) the starting-point of inquiry is the mind’s consciousness of itself. For a full discussion of these distinctions see Broadie (2001).

  14. 14.

    See Bossi (2015, pp. 45–46).

  15. 15.

    Fronterotta (2015, p. 111).

  16. 16.

    Candiotto (2015a, b, pp. 82–89).

  17. 17.

    Fattal (2013, pp. 17ff.).

  18. 18.

    See Beakley and Ludlow (eds.) (2006, p.3): ‘the doctrine that there are two different types of substance, physical substance, which is the object of the natural science, and mental substance, which is the stuff of which our conscious states are comprised’; Watson (1999, p. 244): ‘the view that reality consists of two disparate parts’. In other words, we use the term ‘dualism’ to connote the number of kinds of substances that there are (see Crane (2001, p. 36)).

  19. 19.

    By way of example, see Plt. 309d-e (a ‘courageous soul’ takes part in what is just); Sph. 228a-b (‘perversion of the soul’ is dissension and sickness).

  20. 20.

    The Cartesian dualism is well attested in the Meditations on First Philosophy II (AT VII 20–21); cf. Notae 6–7 (AT VIII 343–344), where Descartes 1904 puts emphasis upon the fact that ‘the human composite’ is, due to its own nature, destructible, whereas mind is indestructible and immortal. See also Letter to Elisabeth, Primitive Notions (May 21 and June 28, 1643; AT III 665; AT III 691–92). Descartes seems to have assumed that the brain is ‘the seat of our mental life’, since there is a pervasive system of correlations between mental events and brain processes (see Meditations on First Philosophy VI: ‘I take note that the mind is immediately affected not by all parts of the body (mentem non ab omnibus corporis partibus immediate affici), but only by the brain’; AT VII 86; transl. Kemp Smith). See also Discourse on Method Part 5, and Kim (1998, p. 46).

  21. 21.

    See Shields (1988); Nussbaum-Putnam (1992), and more recently Johansen (2012, pp. 5–8, 227–228).

  22. 22.

    Putnam (1997, pp. xiii–xiv, 279, 302 et passim). Surely, one might provide reasons to show that Putnam’s functionalism is not ‘substantially the same’ as Aristotle’s view that ‘all things are defined or determined (ὡρισμένα) by their function (τῷ ἔργῳ)’ (Aristotle, Mete. 390a10).

  23. 23.

    Shields (1988, p. 1).

  24. 24.

    As argued by James (2000, pp. 112–113), Descartes , as a young student at the Jesuit College of La Flèche, must have received a thorough training in Aquinas ’ philosophy and the debates surrounding it. But later he took the opinions of scholastics to be mistaken and relatively easy to refute (Letter to Mersenne, November 11, 1640 = AT III 231–232, quoted by James (2000, p. 113, note 7).

  25. 25.

    Charles (2008).

  26. 26.

    Lowe (2013, pp. 197–198).

  27. 27.

    Strongly challenged by Kahn more than two decades ago; see Kahn (1996, pp. 243–247).

  28. 28.

    Themistius, Paraphrase of Posterior Analytics (ed. Wallies) 1.2–12 (quoted by Todd (1996, p.3), and by Ierodiakonou (2002, p.164)).

  29. 29.

    We are very grateful to Gabriela Rossi for her critical reading of this introduction.

Bibliography

  • Annas, J. (1983). An introduction to Plato’s republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (1992). Hellenistic philosophy of mind. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beakley, B., & Ludlow, P. (Eds.). (2006). The philosophy of mind. Classical problems/ contemporary issues (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossi, B. (2015). Una lettura irreverente. In Candiotto (Ed.)., 2015 ‘Monismo’ e ‘dualismo’ (pp. 45–57).

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadie, S. (2001). Soul and body in Plato and Descartes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (new series), 101, 295–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Candiotto, L. (Ed.). (2015a). Senza dualismo. Nuovi percorsi nella filosofia di Platone. Milano: Mimesis Edizione.

    Google Scholar 

  • Candiotto, L. (2015b). Platone e la metafisica delle relazioni. In Candiotto (Ed.), 2015, 73–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles, D. (2008). Aristotle’s psychological theory. In J. J. Cleary, G. M. Gurtler, & S. J. Leiden (Eds.), Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy 24 (pp. 1–29).

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind. An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T., & Patterson, S. (Eds.). (2000). History of the mind-body problem. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denyer, N. (2001). Plato: Alcibiades (Cambridge Greek and Latin classics). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1904). Oeuvres de Descartes (ed. Charles Adams & Paul Tannery). Paris: Léopold Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fattal, M. (2013). Le Banquet de Platon: une philosophie de la relation? In M. Fattal (Ed.), Platon et Plotin. Relation, logos, intuition. Paris: L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality: The second philosophical perspectives lecture. Philosophical Perspectives, 8 (Logic and Language), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fronterotta, F. (2015). Il dualismo platonico e lo statuto del mondo sensibile. In Candiotto (Ed.), 2015, 111–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, L. (2003). Knowing persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, C. (2006). The structured self in Hellenistic and roman thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griswold, C. L., Jr. (1996). Self-knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ierodiakonou, K. (2002). Psellos’ Paraphrasis on Aristotle’s De interpretatione. In K. Ierodiakonou (Ed.), Byzantine philosophy and its ancient sources (pp. 157–181). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, S. (2000). The emergence of the Cartesian mind. In T. Crane & S. Patterson (Eds.), The history of the mind-body problem (pp. 111–130). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansen, T. K. (2012). The powers of Aristotle’s soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, C. (1996). Plato and the Socratic dialogue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Philosophy of mind. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Long, A. A. (2005). Platonic souls as persons. In R. Salles (Ed.), Metaphysics, soul and ethics. Themes from the work of Richard Sorabji (pp. 173–191). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008). Personal agency. The metaphysics of mind and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2012). A neo-Aristotelian substance ontology: Neither relational nor constituent. In T. E. Tahko (Ed.), Contemporary Aristotelian metaphysics (pp. 229–248). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2013). Neo-Aristotelian metaphysics: A brief exposition and defense. In E. Feser (Ed.), Aristotle on method and metaphysics (pp. 196–205). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C., & Putnam, H. (1992). Changing Aristotle’s mind. In M. C. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 27–56). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeau, J.-F. (2000). Platon, Alcibiade (présentation par J.-F. Pradeau. Traduction inédite par Chantal Marboeuf et J.-F. Pradeau). Paris: Flammarion (2e édition corrigée).

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1997). Mind, Language and Reality (Philosophical Papers, volume 2). New York: Cambridge University Press. (reprinted; 1st ed. 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  • Renaud, F., & Tarrant, H. (2015). The platonic ‘Alcibiades I’. The dialogue and its ancient reception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shields, C. (1988). Soul and body in Aristotle. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 6, 103–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. D. (2004). Did Plato write the Alcibiades I? Apeiron, 37, 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, R. B. (1996). Themistius on Aristotle on the soul (translated by Robert B. Todd). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, R. A. (1999). Dualism. In R. Audi (Ed.), The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (2nd ed., pp. 244–245). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcelo D. Boeri .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Boeri, M.D., Kanayama, Y.Y. (2018). General Introduction. In: Boeri, M.D., Kanayama, Y.Y., Mittelmann, J. (eds) Soul and Mind in Greek Thought. Psychological Issues in Plato and Aristotle. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-78547-9_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics