Skip to main content

Categories

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Introduction to Formal Philosophy

Part of the book series: Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy ((SUTP))

  • 123k Accesses

Abstract

Mathematical categories provide an abstract and general framework for logic and mathematics. As such, they could be used by philosophers in all the basic fields of the discipline: semantics, epistemology and ontology. In this paper, we present the basic definitions and notions and suggest some of the ways categories are starting to infiltrate formal philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We should emphasize that this is but one definition and that there are others (equivalent, of course). It very much depends on the background one wants to assume to start with and the goals one has in mind when using categories. If we were to assume that all mathematical entities have to be sets, we would give a slightly different definition. On the other hand, if we were to assume a purely formal set up, a fully specified formal framework, we would give a different definition still. For alternative definitions, see for instance [2, 19, 24].

  2. 2.

    Notice that the latter concept can be defined directly in terms of arrows with no reference to the concept of product. Thus a category can have a terminal object without having all products.

  3. 3.

    The preceding remark concerning the possibility of defining the concept of terminal object directly applies mutatis mutandis to the concept of initial object.

  4. 4.

    This is shocking only if someone sticks firmly to the axiom of extensionality. From a categorical point of view, the axiom of extensionality is not the adequate criterion of identity for abstract sets.

  5. 5.

    Since this object is also defined up to a unique isomorphism, we immediately introduce the standard notation.

  6. 6.

    As far as I know, Bill Lawvere was the first to propose this general definition. For more on its properties, see [18].

  7. 7.

    Notice that we do not have to take the closure of X since in the case of topological spaces, the operations define a coHeyting algebra, i.e. the algebra of closed sets.

  8. 8.

    There are obvious foundational issues arising at this point, but we will simply brush them under the carpet and ignore them altogether.

  9. 9.

    Notice that the functors go from the opposite category C op. This is related to theoretical aspects of category theory that we cannot explain in such a short paper.

References

  1. Adámek, J., & Trnková, V. (1990). Automata and algebras in categories (Mathematics and its applications (East European series), Vol. 37). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  2. (***)Awodey, S. (2007). Category theory (Oxford logic guides, Vol. 49). Oxford: Clarendon Press. [A nice introduction to category theory.].

    Google Scholar 

  3. Awodey, S., & Kishida, K. (2008). Topology and modality: The topological interpretation of first-order modal logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1(Special Issue 02), 146–166.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Borceux, F. (1994). Handbook of categorical algebra. 1 (Encyclopedia of mathematics and its applications, Vol. 50). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Crane, L. (2009). Relational spacetime, model categories and quantum gravity. International Journal of Modern Physics A, 24(15), 2753–2775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Döring, A., & Isham, C. J. (2008). A topos foundation for theories of physics. I. Formal languages for physics. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 49(5), 25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Döring, A., & Isham, C. J. (2008). A topos foundation for theories of physics. II. Daseinisation and the liberation of quantum theory. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 49(5), 26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Döring, A., & Isham, C. J. (2008). A topos foundation for theories of physics. III. The representation of physical quantities with arrows . Journal of Mathematical Physics, 49(5), 777–825

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Döring, A., & Isham, C. J. (2008). A topos foundation for theories of physics: IV. Categories of systems. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 49(5), 826–884.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Eilenberg, S., & Mac Lane, S. (1945). A general theory of natural equivalences. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 58, 231–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Geuvers, H., Niqui, M., Spitters, B., & Wiedijk, F. (2007). Constructive analysis, types and exact real numbers. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 17(1), 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Ghilardi, S., & Zawadowski, M. (2002). Sheaves, games, and model completions: A categorical approach to nonclassical propositional logics (Trends in logic – studia logica library, Vol. 14). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Johnson, M., & Rosebrugh, R. (2010). Ontology engineering, universal algebra, and category theory. In R. Poli, M. Healy, & A. Kameas (Eds.), Theory and applications of ontology: Computer applications (pp. 565–576). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  14. Johnstone, P. T. (2002). Sketches of an elephant: A topos theory compendium. Volume 2 (Oxford logic guides, Vol. 44). Oxford: The Clarendon Press Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Krömer, R. (2007). Tool and object. A history and philosophy of category theory (Volume 32 of science networks. Historical studies). Basel: Birkhäuser Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Landry, E., & Marquis, J.-P. (2005). Categories in context: Historical, foundational and philosophical. Philosophia Mathematica (3), 13(1), 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. La Palme Reyes, M., Macnamara, J., Reyes, G. E., Zolfaghari, H. (1999). Models for non-Boolean negations in natural languages based on aspect analysis. In D. M. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (Vol. 13, pp. 241–260). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  18. (***)Lawvere, F. W., & Rosebrugh, R. (2003). Sets for mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [A gentle introduction to category theory. A nice place to start for philosophers.].

    Google Scholar 

  19. (***)Mac Lane, S. (1998). Categories for the working mathematician (Graduate texts in mathematics, 2nd ed., Vol. 5). New York: Springer. [The standard reference in the field. However, it does presuppose familiarity with various mathematical theories.]

    Google Scholar 

  20. (***)Mac Lane, S., & Moerdijk, I. (1994). Sheaves in geometry and logic. A first introduction to topos theory (Universitext). New York: Springer. [A reference on sheaves and toposes. Not an introductory book.].

    Google Scholar 

  21. Makkai, M., & Reyes, G. E. (1995). Completeness results for intuitionistic and modal logic in a categorical setting. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 72(1), 25–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Marquis, J. -P. (2006). What is category theory? In G. Sica (Ed.), What is category theory? (pp. 221–255). Monza: Polimetrica.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Marquis, J. -P. (2009). From a geometrical point of view: A study of the history and philosophy of category theory (Logic, epistemology, and the unity of science, 1st ed., Vol. 14). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  24. McLarty, C. (1995). Elementary categories, elementary toposes (Oxford logic guides, Vol. 21). Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Moerdijk, I. (1998). Sets, topoi and intuitionism. Philosophia Mathematica (3), 6(2), 169–177. Perspectives on intuitionism.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Mormann, T. (1995). Trope sheaves. A topological ontology of tropes. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 3, 129–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Mormann, T. (1997). Topological aspects of combinatorial possibility. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 5, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Mormann, T. (1999). Neither mereology nor Whiteheadian account of space yet convicted. Analysis (Oxford), 59(3), 174–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Smith, B. (1998). The basic tools of formal ontology. In N. Guarino (Ed.), Formal ontology in information systems (pp. 19–28). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Worththington, J. (2012). A bialgebraic approach to automata and formal language theory. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 163(7), 745–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean-Pierre Marquis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Marquis, JP. (2018). Categories. In: Hansson, S., Hendricks, V. (eds) Introduction to Formal Philosophy. Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77434-3_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics