Skip to main content

Spotlight on Mathematics: Dislocations of Kant and Husserl

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Kant, Shelley and the Visionary Critique of Metaphysics
  • 197 Accesses

Abstract

Having “taxonomized” various positions related to the visionary critique of metaphysics in previous chapters, in this chapter I initiate a second level of the project, which I exemplify in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics with respect to the philosophical programs of Kant and Husserl. In each case, a particular feature of Kant’s or Husserl’s philosophy is “dislocated” and emphasized at the expense of others, much as I showed in Chap. 3 how practical rationality is dislocated and emphasized at the expense of theoretical rationality in the philosophies of Kant and Peirce. This chapter serves as an extended exercise in illustrating how visionary critique can be “lifted” to a second level through selective emphasis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Though, for Kant, not the only bedrock: the status of intuition and understanding are equiprimordial for his enterprise.

  2. 2.

    Hilbert’s philosophical orientation, and even more so that of his close collaborator Bernays, were inspired by to some extent by the neo-Friesian-Kantianism of Nelson, but that is not my concern here. See Mancosu (1998, 170–175). Mancosu concludes that Hilbert and Bernays should not be seen as “standing in the Kantian tradition” (Mancosu 1998, 175).

  3. 3.

    One thinks, before, of the esoteric philosophy of Plato , of Spinoza’s geometrization , and of Leibniz’s mathesis universalis , to name but three earlier instances.

  4. 4.

    Because Eley’s work is not available in translation , I have quoted from it more amply than has elsewhere been my practice in this work.

  5. 5.

    I have consistently translated ‘Sinn’ as ‘sense’ and ‘Bedeutung’ as ‘significance’. I have translated ‘bedeuten’ as ‘to stand for’ rather than ‘to signify’ in order to avoid any confusion with semiotic accounts.

  6. 6.

    In the same way that Frege’s emphasis on judgeability leads to his distinction between sense and significance, we might see Longuenesse’s reading of Kant in terms of the capacity to judge as proto-Husserlian. Arguably, too, it is just this power which found its most overt (but not its most sophisticated or penetrating) exemplification in the power of the productive imagination in the A edition of the Critique.

  7. 7.

    Marion refers to the treatment he gives at Marion (1998, 21–9), which is “taken up and slightly amplified” in Marion (2000, 123).

  8. 8.

    Marion refers to Church (1932).

  9. 9.

    I have used Marion’s expression for the rule.

  10. 10.

    The problem is especially in Marion’s interpretation of Wittgenstein’s later position as operational. What is potentially most interesting about Marion’s interpretation emerges in its conjunction with issues concerning the interpretation of second-order quantifiers; see Marion (1998, 48ff.). Here Marion, building on work of Hintikka and others, makes inroads into what I view as a very prospective approach to Wittgenstein’s philosophical relevance. In particular, it provides a fruitful external context for Wittgenstein’s debates with Ramsey.

Bibliography

  • Bassler, O. Bradley. “Mark van Atten’s On Brouwer,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47:4 (2006), 581–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bassler, O. Bradley. The Long Shadow of the Parafinite: Three Scenes from the Prehistory of a Concept (Boston: Docent, 2015).

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. “A Set of Postulates for the Foundation of Logic,” Annals of Mathematics 33 (1932) 346–66 and 34 (1932) 839–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coffa, J. Alberto. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station, ed. Linda Wessels (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eley, Lothar. Metakritik der Formalen Logik: Sinnliche Gewissheit als Horizont der Aussagenlogik und Elementaren Präikatenlogik (Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff, 1969).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic, revised and edited by Ludwig Landgrebe, trans. James S. Churchill and Karl Ameriks (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans. Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Longuenesse, Béatrice. Kant and the Capacity to Judge: Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Charles T. Wolfe (Princeton: Princeton, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, Paolo. From Brouwer to Hilbert: The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s (New York: Oxford, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Mathieu. “Operations and Numbers in the Tractatus,” Wittgenstein Studien 2 (2000), 105–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Mathieu. “Wittgenstein and Brouwer,” Synthese 131:1–2 (2003), 103–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Mathieu. Wittgenstein, Finitism, and the Foundations of Mathematics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayberry, J. P. The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets (Cambridge: Cambridge, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkoetter, Timothy. “Are Kantian analytic judgments about objects?”, in Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants, ed. V. Rohden (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2008) 191–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkoetter, Timothy. “Truth criteria and the very project of a transcendental logic”, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 91:2 (2009), 1–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Atten, Mark. On Brouwer (Wadsworth, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics Cambridge, 1939, ed. Cora Diamond (Ithaca: Cornell, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Grammar, ed. Rush Rhees, trans. Anthony Kenny (Berkeley: California, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bassler, O.B. (2018). Spotlight on Mathematics: Dislocations of Kant and Husserl. In: Kant, Shelley and the Visionary Critique of Metaphysics. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77291-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics