Advertisement

The Parafinite and Self-Positioning

  • O. Bradley Bassler
Chapter

Abstract

In this chapter, I begin with the prehistory of the Kantian parafinite or indefinitely large in the thought of Galileo and Leibniz before continuing the discussion of self-positioning in Kant’s First Critique in Chap.  1. Next I extend the Kantian notion of self-positioning to what I call second-order self-positioning in Kant’s Second Critique and then compare the demands of theoretical and practical rationality in Kant’s late Opus Postumum so far as self-positioning is concerned. The chapter ends with a discussion of symbolism in Kant and Blumenberg, here understood as what I call higher-order self-positioning.

Bibliography

  1. Adams, Robert Merrihew. Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
  2. Bassler, O. Bradley. Diagnosing Contemporary Philosophy with the Matrix Movies (Palgrave Macmillan, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bassler, O. Bradley. “Leibniz on the Indefinite as Infinite,” The Review of Metaphysics 51 (1998): 849–874.Google Scholar
  4. Bassler, O. Bradley. The Long Shadow of the Parafinite: Three Scenes from the Prehistory of a Concept (Boston: Docent, 2015).Google Scholar
  5. Blumenberg, Hans. The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, trans. Robert Wallace (Cambridge: MIT, 1985).Google Scholar
  6. Blumenberg, Hans. Shipwreck with Spectator: Paradigms for a Metaphor of Existence, trans. Stephen Rendall (Cambridge: MIT, 1997).Google Scholar
  7. Blumenberg, Hans. Paradigmen zu einer Metaphorologie, 2nd ed. (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1999).Google Scholar
  8. Blumenberg, Hans. Paradigms for a Metaphorology, trans. Robert Savage (Ithaca: Cornell, 2010).Google Scholar
  9. Brient, Elizabeth. “Blumenberg Reading Cusanus: Metaphor and Modernity,” in Erinnerung an das Humane: Beiträge zur phänomenologischen Anthropologie Hans Blumenbergs, ed. Michael Moxter (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2011).Google Scholar
  10. Budick, Sanford. Kant and Milton (Cambridge: Harvard, 2010).Google Scholar
  11. Dietrich, A. J. Kants Begriff des Ganzen in seiner Raum-Zeitlehre und das Verhältnis zu Leibniz (Halle: Niemeyer, 1916, repr. Hildesheim, Olms, 1997).Google Scholar
  12. Förster, Eckhart. Kant’s Final Synthesis (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
  13. Galilei, Galileo. Opere di Galileo Galilei (Florence: Edizione Nazionale, 1890–1910).Google Scholar
  14. Galilei, Galileo. Two New Sciences, Including Centers of Gravity and Force of Percussion, and new translation with introduction and notes by Stillman Drake (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974).Google Scholar
  15. Husserl, Edmund. Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans. Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1978).Google Scholar
  16. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987).Google Scholar
  17. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002).Google Scholar
  18. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996).Google Scholar
  19. Kolakowski, Leszek. Metaphysical Horror (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988).Google Scholar
  20. Kolakowski, Leszek. “The philosophical role of the Reformation,” trans. Michael Montgomery, in Triquarterly 22 (Fall 1971), A Leszek Kolakowski Reader, 118–38.Google Scholar
  21. Lasswitz, Kurd. Geschichte der Atomistik vom Millelalter bis Newton, 2 vols. (repr. Hildesheim: Olms, 1984).Google Scholar
  22. Leibniz, G. W. Philosophical Papers, trans. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989).Google Scholar
  23. Wang, Hao. Reflections on Kurt Gödel (Cambridge: MIT, 1987).Google Scholar
  24. Wasserman, Earl R. Shelley: A Critical Reading (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins, 1971).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • O. Bradley Bassler
    • 1
  1. 1.University of GeorgiaAthensUSA

Personalised recommendations