Skip to main content

Foundationalism and the Disengaged Knower

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Self and Social Relations
  • 197 Accesses

Abstract

I outline foundationalism and its reliance on an immediately given epistemic content. I develop the foundationalist account as related to a particular picture of the human condition, the moral/cultural motivations for adopting such an account, and I highlight the connection of foundationalism to atomistic conceptions of the individual. I give arguments for, and classic examples of, both rationalist and empiricist forms of immediacy. I end the chapter by highlighting what I take to be incoherent in the notion of an immediately given epistemic content and outline the transcendental form of argument I will use to draw out this incoherency. In giving these transcendental arguments over the following two chapters, I will be putting pressure on the atomist conception of the individual which is so connected with the foundationalist enterprise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Rorty (1991), 21.

  2. 2.

    For more on this see Rorty (2009).

  3. 3.

    Rorty (1991), 22.

  4. 4.

    I think that to call knowledge nothing other than widespread agreement is far too simple. Knowledge and reason are grounded on a widely shared activity, but that activity makes available standards of reason and presents tensions and conflicts which can be used as a basis for argument about better and worse ways to conceive of things.

  5. 5.

    Ibid., 31.

  6. 6.

    Kant (1991).

  7. 7.

    Rorty (1991), 31.

  8. 8.

    Ibid., 31.

  9. 9.

    The objectivist hope of forming the true human community is often born out in the history of philosophy via the many attempts to ground our ethics first of all in a naturalist epistemology. To get a good sense of Bentham’s ‘objectivist’ task, see Bentham (1994), and for his view on empty phrases see Mill (1950), 51–53, where he is quoting from Bentham (2009). This particular line of thought can be traced back to Hume’s empiricist epistemology and the account of ethics which he drew from this. See Hume (1983).

  10. 10.

    Rorty (1991), 22.

  11. 11.

    Taylor (1997a), 3.

  12. 12.

    Ibid., 4.

  13. 13.

    Ibid., 5.

  14. 14.

    Ibid., 7.

  15. 15.

    Ibid., 7.

  16. 16.

    Descartes (1996), 12.

  17. 17.

    Williams (2005), 51.

  18. 18.

    Brandom (1997), 125.

  19. 19.

    Descartes (1996), 16.

  20. 20.

    Ibid., 17.

  21. 21.

    Ibid., 17.

  22. 22.

    Descartes (1931), 38.

  23. 23.

    For a longer discussion on this see Kenny (1968), 40–62.

  24. 24.

    Brandom (1997), 121.

  25. 25.

    Williams (2005), 44.

  26. 26.

    Descartes (1996), 21.

  27. 27.

    Ibid., 24.

  28. 28.

    Ibid., 24.

  29. 29.

    ‘Let whoever can do so deceive me, he will never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as I continue to think I am something; or make it true at some future time that I have never existed, since it is now true that I exist; or bring it about that two and three added together are more or less than five, or anything of this kind in which I see a manifest contradiction’ in Ibid., 25.

  30. 30.

    Ibid., 28.

  31. 31.

    Sensations are not the only things taken to be given in the history of philosophy. Willem A DeVries and Timm Triplett stress this point in their Knowledge, Mind, and the Given, highlighting Spinoza’s axioms in his Ethics, as well as both Platonic Realists and Bertrand Russell who have claimed that universals must be given. See deVries and Triplett (2000), XXI. Spinoza is a particularly conspicuous example, as he lists a selection of axioms at the start of each section of his Ethics, from which in combination he claims to derive the entirety of his system. See Spinoza (1996).

  32. 32.

    Russell (1998), 4.

  33. 33.

    Ibid., 3.

  34. 34.

    Ibid., 3.

  35. 35.

    deVries and Triplett (2000), XXVI.

  36. 36.

    Taylor (1997a), 9

  37. 37.

    Locke and Berkeley discussed in the following paragraph are both members of this tradition. See Book II: Of Ideas in Locke (1997) and Berkeley (1999).

  38. 38.

    deVries and Triplett (2000), XXI.

  39. 39.

    Kenny (2008), 132.

  40. 40.

    Berkeley (1999), 27.

  41. 41.

    Russell (1998), 20–21.

  42. 42.

    Sellars (2000), 21.

  43. 43.

    Ibid., 23.

  44. 44.

    Taylor (1997a), 12.

  45. 45.

    Taylor (1997b).

  46. 46.

    Ibid., 26.

  47. 47.

    Taylor acknowledges that while transcendental arguments traditionally conceived are concerned with experience, they need not all be so concerned. He gives an example from Strawson’s ‘Individuals’, and also some of Wittgenstein’s work in the Philosophical Investigations. I take my account of Wittgenstein in Chap. 5 to be a transcendental reading. See Taylor (1976). See also Strawson (2003).

  48. 48.

    Taylor (1997a), 29.

  49. 49.

    Ibid., 12.

Bibliography

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 1994. The Principle of Utility. In Ethics, ed. Peter Singer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, George. 1999. Principles of Human Knowledge, Three Dialogues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1997. Study Guide by Robert Brandom. In Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, ed. Robert Brandom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Spinoza, Benedict. 1996. Ethics. Trans. Edwin Curley. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1931. Reply to Second Objections. In The Philosophical Works of Descartes. Vol. II. Trans. Elizabeth S. Haldane and G.R.T. Ross. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. In Meditations on First Philosophy, ed. John Cottingham, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • deVries, Willem A., and Timm Triplett. 2000. Knowledge, Mind and the Given. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1983. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1991. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. H.J. Paton. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, Anthony. 1968. Descartes: A Study of His Philosophy. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. The Rise of Modern Philosophy. Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1997. In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Roger Woolhouse. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1950. In Mill on Bentham and Coleridge, ed. F.R. Leavis. London: Chatto & Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1991. Solidarity or Objectivity? In Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, vol. I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. 2nd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1998. The Problems of Philosophy. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 2000. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. In Knowledge, Mind, and the Given, ed. Willem A. deVries and Timm Triplett. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter. 2003. Individuals. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1976. The Opening Arguments of the Phenomenology. In Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Alasdair MacIntyre. Garden City: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997a. Overcoming Epistemology. In Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997b. The Validity of Transcendental Arguments. In Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 2005. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. 2nd ed. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Whittingham, M. (2018). Foundationalism and the Disengaged Knower. In: The Self and Social Relations. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77246-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics