Skip to main content

From Mirror to Lamp

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Theatre of Imagining
  • 382 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter analyzes the redefinition and reappraisal of imagination that took place in the late eighteenth century and early nineteenth, initiated by Immanuel Kant and developed by, for example, Samuel Taylor Coleridge. Imagination was redefined as a productive or creative force with several functions and sub-functions, allowing for a new, affirmative appraisal that takes imagination from the metaphor of the reflecting mirror to that of the lamp exuding a divine light from and onto the imaginer. Kallenbach here traces how imagination becomes re-evaluated as a superior faculty that is both a precondition for knowledge and the agent for aesthetic judgment. Imagination gradually becomes synonymous with ideality and the rare gift of the genius.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Thus Hume writes that “in the imagination the perception is faint and languid, and cannot without difficulty be preserv’d by the mind steddy and uniform for any considerable time.” A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects (Kitchener, Ontario, Canada: Batoche Books, 1999), 13.

  2. 2.

    With inspiration from Plotinus, this had largely been confined to “marginalized hermetic cults” celebrating the magical, divine powers of imagination; see Kearney, 155.

  3. 3.

    The periodization of both Idealism and Romanticism is debatable. The starting point will here be Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781). While Percy Bysshe Shelley’s Defence of Poetry (1821) often marks the end of Romanticism, the idealist aesthetics, as will be evident in the following chapters, still stood strong towards the end of the 1870s.

  4. 4.

    Jean-Luc Nancy, The Ground of the Image trans. Jeff Fort, Perspectives in Continental Philosophy (New York: Fordham University Press, 2005), 80.

  5. 5.

    Abrams uses these “antithetic metaphors of mind” to illustrate the radical shift in the conception of the human consciousness that occurred in the late eighteenth century, with its consequences for aesthetic thought as well. In The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition (London, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1971), Preface.

  6. 6.

    George S. Rousseau, “Science and the Discovery of Imagination in Enlightened England,” in Nervous Acts (Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004), 91.

  7. 7.

    Abrams, Preface.

  8. 8.

    Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason [Kritik der reinen Vernunft], trans. Marcus Weigelt (London: Penguin, 2007), |B103, |A78.

  9. 9.

    Sometimes also called Phantasie, Vorstellung or Perceptionsvermögen.

  10. 10.

    Brann characterizes the different approaches as “more psychological in the earlier and altogether logical or ‘transcendental’ in the later edition”; see The World of the Imagination: Sum and Substance (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991), 89. Kant retracted many of his claims of the powers of imagination in the second edition. Martin Heidegger ’s 1927 study Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics [Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik], trans. Richard Taft, 5th ed. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997), provides an interpretation of this.

  11. 11.

    See Mark Johnson, The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 148.

  12. 12.

    Ibid.

  13. 13.

    See, e.g., James Engell, The Creative Imagination (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), 130. Johnson argues that Kant’s notion of reproductive imagination “is only representing the standard empiricist view of imagination as a power to form unified images, and to recall in memory past images, so as to constitute a unified and coherent experience.” 149.

  14. 14.

    Kant, |A97. See also Johnson, 149.

  15. 15.

    Kant, |B104, |A79.

  16. 16.

    Ibid., |B151.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., e.g., |A97.

  18. 18.

    There has been some discussion as to whether the reproductive imagination is in fact transcendental or not. See, e.g., Johnson.

  19. 19.

    Kant, |A123.

  20. 20.

    Johnson, 151.

  21. 21.

    “The concept of a dog designates a rule according to which my imagination can generally register the figure of a four-footed animal, without being restricted to any particular figure supplied by experience or to any possible image which I can present in concreto.” Kant, |B181, |A41. For a to-the-point account, see Johnson, 152ff.

  22. 22.

    Kant, |A123.

  23. 23.

    Ibid., |A124.

  24. 24.

    Ibid.

  25. 25.

    Engell, 133.

  26. 26.

    Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement [Kritik der Urteilskraft], trans. James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), §I, 35.

  27. 27.

    Ibid., §9, 48.

  28. 28.

    Ibid.

  29. 29.

    “[I]t can be nothing else than the state of the mind involved in the free play of imagination and understanding (so far as these are in mutual accord, as is requisite for cognition in general),” in ibid., §9, 49.

  30. 30.

    Ibid., §17, 66.

  31. 31.

    Kearney, 172.

  32. 32.

    Ibid., 173.

  33. 33.

    Kant, Judgement, General remark on the first section of the analytic, 71, my bold emphasis.

  34. 34.

    Which for Kant primarily applies to the sublime in nature rather than art.

  35. 35.

    Mary Warnock, Imagination (London: Faber and Faber, 1976), 56.

  36. 36.

    Ibid., 63.

  37. 37.

    Kant, Judgement, §44, 135.

  38. 38.

    Ibid.

  39. 39.

    Ibid., §45, 135f.

  40. 40.

    Ibid., §45, 135.

  41. 41.

    Ibid., §46, 136.

  42. 42.

    Genius is the innate mental aptitude (ingenium) through which nature gives the rule to art” (ibid.) and stands in complete opposition to “the spirit of imitation,” ibid., §47, 137.

  43. 43.

    Ibid., §47, 138.

  44. 44.

    Ibid., §49, 142.

  45. 45.

    Ibid., §49, 145.

  46. 46.

    Ibid., §49, 143.

  47. 47.

    Ibid.

  48. 48.

    Ibid., §50.

  49. 49.

    Engell, 135.

  50. 50.

    Iser, The Fictive and the Imaginary, 186.

  51. 51.

    Engell characterizes Coleridge as “as once a culminating and original figure,” noting that “[t]he range and profundity of his idea of the imagination make it a natural climatic point.” Engell, 366 and 329.

  52. 52.

    In “Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View,” in Anthropology, History, and Education, ed. Günter Zöller and Robert B. Louden, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), §28, 278, Kant writes: “The power of imagination […] is either inventive (productive) or merely recollective (reproductive). But the productive power of imagination is nevertheless not exactly creative, for it is not capable of producing a sense representation that was never given to our faculty of sense; one can always furnish evidence of the material of its ideas.”

  53. 53.

    Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Biographia Literaria or Biographical Sketches of My Literary Life and Opinions, ed. Kathleen Coburn, vol. I-II, The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge Vol. 7, Bollingen Series (London, Princeton, NJ: Routledge, Princeton University Press, 1983), Vol. I, Chapter 13, 304f.

  54. 54.

    See, e.g., Jonathan Wordsworth’s discussion, “‘The Infinite I Am’: Coleridge and the Ascent of Being,” ed. Richard Gravil, Lucy Newlyn, and Nicholas Roe, Coleridge’s Imagination (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cambridge Books Online., 1985, online publication 2009), https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511659324.

  55. 55.

    Kant makes a similar distinction in his Antropologie: “The power of imagination, in so far as it also produces images involuntarily, is called fantasy.” Kant, “Antropology,” 278.

  56. 56.

    Coleridge, Biographia, I–II, Vol. I, Chapter 4, 82. For a detailed discussion of the contemporary developments of the etymology of imagination, see Editors’ Introduction, ibid., xcvii ff.

  57. 57.

    Ibid., Vol. I, Chapter 7, 125.

  58. 58.

    See, e.g., Engell, 344.

  59. 59.

    Iser, The Fictive and the Imaginary, 188.

  60. 60.

    Warnock, 97.

  61. 61.

    Engell, 335.

  62. 62.

    Ibid.

  63. 63.

    Coleridge, Biographia, I–II, Vol. I, Chapter 9, 156.

  64. 64.

    Ibid., Vol. II, Chapter 14, 15–16.

  65. 65.

    Kant, “Antropology,” 279.

  66. 66.

    Coleridge, Biographia, I–II, Vol. I, Chapter 7, 124.

  67. 67.

    Engell, 347.

  68. 68.

    Coleridge, Biographia, I–II, Vol. I, Chapter 12, 255.

  69. 69.

    Ibid., I, Chapter 10, 168.

  70. 70.

    This ability also serves to contrast it from Fancy, which has only the ability to combine.

  71. 71.

    Coleridge, Biographia, I–II, Introduction, lxxxv.

  72. 72.

    The substance of the brain was thought to resemble fibers.

  73. 73.

    See Clarke, Dewhurst and Aminoff, 74ff.

  74. 74.

    Rousseau, 88.

  75. 75.

    Richard C. Sha, “Toward a Physiology of the Romantic Imagination,” Configurations 17, no. 3 (2009): 15.

  76. 76.

    Introduced by Franz Joseph Gall (1758–1828).

  77. 77.

    Termed the “Organ of Poetry” by Gall; see George Combe, A System of Phrenology, 3rd ed. (Edinburgh: John Anderson, 1830), 325.

  78. 78.

    Ibid., 513.

  79. 79.

    Ibid., 514.

  80. 80.

    Ibid., 325.

  81. 81.

    Combe also cites Prospero’s concluding speech in Shakespeare ’s The Tempest as “a beautiful specimen” of the style of writing that this faculty produces; ibid., 326.

  82. 82.

    Ibid., 335.

  83. 83.

    Therefore, a well-developed Ideality was essential for the tragic actor: “It is necessary to a player of tragedy. The tone or note of voice suitable to Ideality is elevated and majestic, and hence it is essential to enable the actor to feel and express the greatness of the personages whom he represents.” Ibid., 330.

  84. 84.

    Ibid., 328.

  85. 85.

    Richard C. Sha, “Imagination,” in A Handbook of Romanticism Studies (John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, 2012), 14. See further Robert Darnton, Mesmerism and the End of the Enlightenment in France (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1968).

  86. 86.

    Sha, “Imagination,” 32.

  87. 87.

    Ibid., 10. See also Rousseau: “The fact that Enlightenment physiologists centered their attention on the diseased rather than healthy imagination is of tremendous consequence for the development of European poetry; for it was not until culture scientifically defined the very same madness it wished to condemn that poets turned to the writing of ‘mad verse’ for catharsis and relief.” In Rousseau, 92.

  88. 88.

    Percy Bysshe Shelley, “Shelley’s Defence of Poetry,” in Peacock’s Four Ages of Poetry; Shelley’s Defence of Poetry; Browning’s Essay on Shelley, ed. H. F. B. Brett-Smith, The Percy Reprints; No. 3 ([Philadelphia]: Folcroft, 1977), 23.

  89. 89.

    Ibid., 31.

References

  • Abrams, M. H. The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition. London, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1971. 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brann, Eva T. H. The World of the Imagination: Sum and Substance. Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Edwin, Kenneth Dewhurst, and Michael Jeffrey Aminoff. An Illustrated History of Brain Function: Imaging the Brain from Antiquity to the Present. Norman Neurosciences Series. 2nd ed. San Francisco: Norman Publ., 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. Biographia Literaria or Biographical Sketches of My Literary Life and Opinions. The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge Vol. 7, Bollingen Series. Edited by Kathleen Coburn Vol. I–II, London, Princeton, NJ: Routledge, Princeton University Press, 1983. 1817.

    Google Scholar 

  • Combe, George. A System of Phrenology. 3rd ed. Edinburgh: John Anderson, 1830. 1825.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darnton, Robert. Mesmerism and the End of the Enlightenment in France. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engell, James. The Creative Imagination. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics [Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik]. Translated by Richard Taft. 5th ed. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997. 1927.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects. Kitchener, Ontario, Canada: Batoche Books, 1999. 1739–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iser, Wolfgang. The Fictive and the Imaginary: Charting Literary Anthropology [Das Fiktive und das Imaginäre. Perspektiven literatischer Antrophologie]. Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993. 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Mark. The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990. 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. “Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View.” Translated by Robert B. Louden. In Anthropology, History, and Education, edited by Günter Zöller and Robert B. Louden. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Critique of Judgement [Kritik der Urteilskraft]. Translated by James Creed Meredith. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. 1790.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Critique of Pure Reason [Kritik der reinen Vernunft]. Translated by Marcus Weigelt. London: Penguin, 2007. 1781, 1787.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney, Richard. The Wake of Imagination: Toward a Postmodern Culture. London: Routledge, 1998. 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, Jean-Luc. The Ground of the Image. Translated by Jeff Fort. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. New York: Fordham University Press, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, George S. “Science and the Discovery of Imagination in Enlightened England.” In Nervous Acts, 86–112. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sha, Richard C. “Imagination.” In A Handbook of Romanticism Studies, 17–35: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. “Toward a Physiology of the Romantic Imagination.” Configurations 17, no. 3 (2009): 197–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, Percy Bysshe. “Shelley’s Defence of Poetry.” In Peacock’s Four Ages of Poetry; Shelley’s Defence of Poetry; Browning’s Essay on Shelley, edited by H. F. B. Brett-Smith. The Percy Reprints; No. 3, 21–59. [Philadelphia]: Folcroft, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, Mary. Imagination. London: Faber and Faber, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willis, Thomas. De Anima Brutorum Quæ Hominis Vitalis Ac Sensitiva Est, Exercitationes Duæ. Londini: Gulielm Wells, 1672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wordsworth, Jonathan. “‘The Infinite I Am’: Coleridge and the Ascent of Being.” In Coleridge’s Imagination, edited by Richard Gravil, Lucy Newlyn and Nicholas Roe Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cambridge Books Online, 1985, online publication 2009. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511659324.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kallenbach, U. (2018). From Mirror to Lamp. In: The Theatre of Imagining. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-76303-3_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics