Skip to main content

Science and Democracy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Scientists, Democracy and Society

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 16))

  • 375 Accesses

Abstract

We have seen why the moral responsibility of science is inevitable. However, society taken as a whole collaborates with science: scientists and ordinary citizens are members of a single community of inquiry, whose aim is the truth. After examining the features of a ‘perfectionist’ democracy, I will clarify why it does not represent a utopian ideal by examining the role and characteristics of both experts and public opinion. We will appreciate how science and society are both fragmented and subject to variable alliances. Finally, we will see the differences between this and other conceptions of the relationship between science and democracy. In this context, the essential role of the concept of truth will be confirmed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is perhaps worth noting that in moral philosophy perfectionism is not usually associated with pragmatism. The European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy has devoted an entire issue on the subject, cf. Laugier and Donatelli (2010). Here, as I have just pointed out, the contrast is between proceduralist democracy, where citizens’ preferences and desires are given, and a certain kind of perfectionist democracy in which all citizens evaluate their preferences and desires in view of the scientific mentality.

  2. 2.

    It is perhaps worth adding to this that Talisse harshly criticises the kind of democracy defended by Dewey, contrasting it to his Peircean conception of democracy. However, at least implicitly, Talisse also accepts Dewey’s position, unlike Peirce, when he maintains that moral discourse falls within the logic of inquiry. And this is the point that interests me here.

  3. 3.

    See, for example, Jansen (2008) for an overview of studies on Lippmann, whose philosophical position was certainly more sophisticated than it may seem here.

  4. 4.

    For example, he writes: “the experts will remain human beings. They will enjoy power, and their temptation will be to appoint themselves censors, and so absorb the real function of decision. Unless their function is correctly defined they will tend to pass on the facts they think appropriate, and to pass down the decisions they approve. […] The only institutional safeguard is to separate as absolutely as it is possible to do so the staff which executes from the staff which investigates.” Lippmann (1922: 206). And also: “the power of the expert depends upon separating himself from those who make the decisions, upon not caring, in his expert self, what decision is made” (ibid.: 204).

  5. 5.

    The correspondence between Einstein and Velikovsky is available at www.varchive.org/org/einstein/

  6. 6.

    It should be noted, however, that this argument was used by Carl Sagan when, addressing the general public, he denied any credibility to Velikovsky’s theory. Cf. Sagan (1979, Chap. 7).

  7. 7.

    See Goldman (2006: 21), where the reader will find the enunciation of all five methods.

  8. 8.

    As we have read since the preface: “the philosophy stated in this book connects the growth of democracy with the development of the experimental method in the sciences”, cf. Dewey (1916: 3).

  9. 9.

    This is the essay The Public and its Problems, which I will refer to in the next section.

  10. 10.

    This is a ballet based on the music of Romualdo Marenco, which was first performed at the Teatro della Scala in Milan at the end of the nineteenth century. The idea of the ballet was to represent the triumph of science and technology over obscurantism and prejudices. Ignorance was attacked and beat in retreat, until the final stage, where the triumphal music marked the victory of science.

  11. 11.

    As Russell (1954: 211) writes: “Every increase of skill demands, if it is to produce an increase and not a diminution of human happiness, a correlative increase of wisdom. There has been during the last hundred and fifty years an unprecedented increase of skill, and there is no sign that the pace of this increase is slackening. But there has not been even the slightest increase of wisdom”.

  12. 12.

    On these issues, see also the ideas of Michael Oakeshott, an author who has been curiously ignored by the literature on the philosophy of expertise, perhaps because the field he was primarily interested in was political philosophy, not philosophy of science. On Oakeshott, see in particular Oakeshott (1991).

  13. 13.

    For regulatory science, see also Jasanoff (1990), where she shows how the limits of peer review systems are particularly apparent in this very case.

  14. 14.

    See Funtowicz and Ravetz (1993: 744): “To characterize an issue involving risk and the environment, in what we call ‘post-normal science’, we can think of it as one where facts are uncertain, values in dispute, stakes high and decisions urgent. In such a case, the term ‘problem’, with its connotations of an exercise where a defined methodology is likely to lead to a clear solution, is less appropriate. We would be misled if we retained the image of a process where true scientific facts simply determine the correct policy conclusions”. When moving into fields where there is uncertainty and values, every reference to the truth ceases to exist.

  15. 15.

    In reality, Barnes and Bloor assume without any argument that the introduction of social categories is necessary to explain the theoretical choice between possible alternatives coherent with empirical evidence. Both Slezak (1991) and Laudan (1984a) point out that the presence of social factors must be independently proven. In general, the attempt to derive from the underdetermination the thesis of the irrelevance of epistemic factors is like biting off more than can be chewed. On this, see Laudan (1984a, b). For a detailed analysis, refer to Barrotta (1998).

  16. 16.

    The supporters of Wave Two have, with good reason, protested that in this way Collins and Evans have lumped together very different authors under the same label (see, for example, Jasanoff 2003). However, we must consider that the way in which Collins and Evans characterise Wave Two serves their theses, which mainly concern Wave Three. I find nothing rhetorically wrong in this strategy. Furthermore, Collins and Evans explicitly admit that in this way they introduced a remarkable historical simplification: “Our historical version of the Second Wave was painted with a broad brush and we acknowledge its deficiencies” (Collins and Evans 2002: 449).

  17. 17.

    See, for example, Fisher (2009, Chap. 5). Fisher raises many interesting problems when he examines the position of Collins and Evans. For example, he looks at the crucial problem of the connection between scientific and technological progress and social progress. It is certainly not the job of the scientific expert to decide what kind of technology humankind needs. However, we must consider that Collins and Evans’s position intentionally does not address this kind of issue (Cf. Collins and Evans 2017: 74–6). The accusation of going back to the thesis of Wave One is one that is frequently launched by the critics of Collins and Evans. See also Jasanoff (2003) and Wynne (2003).

  18. 18.

    As Hachoen writes (2000: 486): “When the cold-war coalition and the welfare state faced difficulties, Popper remained quiet. […] Hayek managed to corrupt his socialism”.

  19. 19.

    Popper (1994: 121): “One may say that the problem [concerning the moral responsibility of the scientist] has lately become more general, due to the fact that lately all science, and indeed all learning, has tended to become potentially applicable. Formerly, the pure scientist or the pure scholar had only one responsibility beyond those which everyone else has – that is, the search for truth. […] For all I know, Maxwell had little reason to worry about the possible applications of his equations. And perhaps even Hertz did not worry about Hertzian waves. This happy situation belongs to the past”.

  20. 20.

    This affirmation is found almost everywhere in The Open Society. For example, he writes: “I suggest […] to replace the utilitarian maxim ‘Aim at the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number’, or briefly, ‘Maximize happiness’, by the formula ‘The least amount of avoidable suffering for all’, or briefly, ‘Minimize suffering’. […] We should realize that from the moral point of view suffering and happiness must not be treated as symmetrical; that is to say, the promotion of happiness is in any case much less urgent than the rendering of help to those who suffer, and the attempt to prevent suffering” Popper (1966, vol. 1: 235). Among commentators, Bryan Magee (1973) particularly highlighted the analogy between the asymmetry on which the principle of falsification is based and the one on which negative utilitarianism is based.

  21. 21.

    Feyerabend devotes many pages of Against Method to Galileo, see Feyerabend (1975).

  22. 22.

    See Feyerabend (1975: 49–50): “Voodoo […] is a case in point. Nobody knows it, everybody uses it as a paradigm of backwardness and confusion. And yet Voodoo has a firm though still not sufficiently understood material basis, and a study of its manifestations can be used to enrich, and perhaps even to revise, our knowledge of physiology”. In Feyerabend (1978: 91–6), Feyerabend does not hesitate to defend astrology as well.

  23. 23.

    This is clearly an exaggeration by Feyerabend. On this, see Selinger (2011, Chap. 5).

  24. 24.

    The issue raised is linked to a tension within the same philosophy of science as Feyerabend’s. Two theories are mutually incommensurable when they do not share any observational statements. If this is the case, the two theories cannot even be defined as rival, and therefore it is not comprehensible how their existence allows mutual criticism. On the other hand, if two theories are rival then criticism is definitely possible, but this requires that they are commensurable. This problem has been raised continually by Feyerabend’s critics. More recently it was also raised by John Preston (1997: 111).

References

  • Barnes, B. (1982). T.S. Kuhn and social science. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., & Shapin, S. (Eds.). (1979). Natural order. Historical studies of scientific culture. Beverly Hills/London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrotta, P. (1998). La dialettica scientifica. Per un nuovo razionalismo critico. Turin: UTET-libreria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1983). Wittgenstein. A social theory of knowledge. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M., et al. (2011). Acting in an uncertain world. An essay on technical democracy (G. Burchell, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. (2010). Tacit and explicit knowledge. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2002). The third wave of science studies: Studies of expertise and experience. Reprinted in Selinger, E. & Crease R. P. (Eds.). (2006). The philosophy of expertise (pp. 39–110). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2017). Why democracies need science. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Commager, H. S. (1950). The American mind. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Grazia, A. (1978). The Velikovsky affair (1st ed., 1966). London: Sphere.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education. In Dewey (1969–91). The collected works (J. A. Boydstone Ed.). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. (The middle works, Vol. 9).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1927). The public and its problems. In Dewey (1969–1991). The collected works. (The later works, Vol. 2, pp. 235–372).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellenberger, L. (1986). A lesson from Velikowsky. http://abob.libs.uga.edu/bobk/vlesson.html

  • Epstein, S. (1996). Impure science. AIDS, activism, and the politics of knowledge. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1978). Science in a free society. London: NBL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, F. (2009). Democracy and expertise. Reorienting policy inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, F. (1992). The end of history and the last man. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2000). The governance of science: Ideology and the future of the open society. Philadelphia: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funtowicz, S. O., & Ravetz, J. (1992). Three types of risk assessment and the emergence of post-normal science. In S. Krimsky & D. Golding (Eds.), Social theory of risk (pp. 251–273). London: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funtowicz, S. O., & Ravetz, J. (1993). Science for post-normal age. Futures, 25(7), 739–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelwick, R. (1977). The way of discovery. An introduction to the thought of Michael Polanyi. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. J. (2006). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Reprinted in Selinger E. & Crease R. P. (Eds.). (2006). The philosophy of expertise (pp. 14–38). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacohen, M. H. (2000). Karl Popper. The formative years, 1902–1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, S. C. (2008). Walter Lippmann, Straw Man of communication research. In D. D. Park & J. Pooley (Eds.), History of media and communication research. Contested Memories (pp. 71–112). New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (1990). The fifth branch: Science advisers as policymakers. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2003). Breaking the waves in science studies: Comments on H.M. Collins and Robert Evans. Social Studies of Science, 33(3), 389–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2005). Design on nature. Science and democracy in Europe and the United States. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juergens, R. E. (1978). Minds in Chaos. In de Grazia (Ed.). (1978). The Velikovsky affair (1st ed., 1966, pp. 20–55). London: Sphere.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge, N. (Ed.). (2005). Scientific values and civic virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2005). Un monde pluriel mais commun. Entretiens avec F. Ewald. La Tour d’Aigues: Édition de l’Aube.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984a). The pseudo-science of science? In J. E. Brown (Ed.), Scientific rationality: The sociological turn (pp. 41–73). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984b). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laugier, S., & Donatelli, P. (Eds.). (2010). Perfectionism and pragmatism. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, 2, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippmann, W. (1922). Public opinion. Mineola: Dover, 2004

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippmann, W. (1925). The phantom public. New Brunswick: Transaction Publisher, 1993

    Google Scholar 

  • Magee, B. (1973). Karl Popper. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1991), Rational conduct. In Rationalism in politics and other essays (pp. 99–131). New and expanded edition (1st ed., 1961). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt. How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from Tobacco smoke to global warming. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1877). The fixation of belief. In Peirce (1931–1935). Collected papers (C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. (Vol. V, pp. 223–247).

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1946). Science, faith, and society. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1962a). Personal knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1962b). The republic of science: Its political and economic theory. Minerva, 38(2000), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, M. (1963). Science and religion: Separate dimensions or common ground? Philosophy Today, 7, 4–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1956). Three views concerning human knowledge. In Conjectures and refutations (1969, pp. 130–160). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1966). The open society and its enemies (5th ed.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1994), The moral responsibility of the scientist. In The myth of the framework. In defence of science and rationality (pp. 121–129). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, J. (1997). Feyerabend. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1954). Human society in ethics and politics. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagan, C. (1979). Broca’s brain: Reflections on the romance of science. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartori, G. (1957). Democrazia e definizioni. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selinger, E. (2011). Expertise. Philosophical reflections. New York/London: Automatic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S., & Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shearmur, J. (1996). The political thought of Karl Popper. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. (1991). Bloor’s bluff: Behaviourism and the strong programme. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 5(3), 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talisse, R. (2007). A pragmatist philosophy of democracy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velikovsky, I. (1950). Worlds in collision. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, B. (2003). Seasick on the third wave? Subverting the egemony of propositionalism: Responses to Collins and Evans (2002). Social Studies of Science, 33(3), 401–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Barrotta, P. (2018). Science and Democracy. In: Scientists, Democracy and Society. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 16. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74938-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics