Skip to main content

Human Rights as Political Imaginary

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human Rights as Political Imaginary
  • 588 Accesses

Abstract

Drawing on an emerging iconoclastic human rights historiography, pioneered by the historian Samuel Moyn, López traces the origins of human rights not to a mythical postwar consensus at the UN, but to a concatenation of social and political dynamics in the 1970s. This historical vantage point opens up avenues for developing thicker conceptions of human rights by drawing attention to the concrete historical and social relational contexts in which human rights emerged, and which subsequently enabled them to be disseminated. Drawing on the work of Jeffrey Alexander, Bob Jessop, and Margaret Somers, the notion of political imaginary is developed, and defined as assemblages of social representations, social technologies, modes of agency and subjectivity, and particular organizational forms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the notion of legal and rights consciousness, see Scheingold (2004, xvii–xvlii). For an overview of the emergence and subsequent development of legal consciousness in sociolegal studies, see Silbey (2005). For examples of substantive empirical explorations of legal consciousness, see Ewick and Silbey (1998), Engel and Munger (2003), and Sarat and Kearns (2009). For a critique of the legal consciousness research programme, see Valverde (2003a, b).

  2. 2.

    One of the iconic drafters of the UDHR , René Cassin , noted, in its effort to achieve consensus, the committee tasked with drafting the document sidestepped “metaphysical controversies […] on the origins of human rights” (cited in Slaughter 2009, 47).

  3. 3.

    Amongst the critics of human rights’ thinness, some argue, as I will show in the next chapter, for the need to develop a more combative conception, as Blau and Moncada do when they insist on the need to go beyond “the liberal vision” (2005). Others claim that the apparent austerity of human rights as a moral language is belied by an unspoken political project (liberalism) whose hegemony allows it to remain unmarked qua political project (Brown 2004).

  4. 4.

    Charles Beitz (2011), a political philosopher, whose work I discuss in more detail in Chap. 4, develops a thoughtful critique of contemporary attempts to ground human right’s normativity. He opts instead for grasping the normative valence of human rights by framing them as the product of an emergent practice that provides agents with reasons for action, specifically with the goal of protecting “important individual interests against predictable threats and to deter societies from developing certain features that might cause their government to pursue policies that threaten international order” (2011, 131).

  5. 5.

    This of course does not entail denying the social and causal efficacy or the “epistemological privilege” of particular “ideational regimes” (Somers and Block 2005). Rather it draws attention to fact that even though a moral order might originate “in an explicit doctrine or theory […] the process through which it penetrates and takes hold of a social imaginary is slow and complex” (Gaonkar 2002, 11).

  6. 6.

    For a fascinating attempt to show the possibility of universalizing local human rights cultures, see Gregg (2011). Interesting as this account is, it is a prospective one that does not explain the contemporary global currency of human rights, but posits how such a vision might plausibly be extended.

  7. 7.

    This of course is also a dilemma faced by political anthropologists, “So we are left with either a philosophically rich but phenomenologically thin set of explanations for social life on the one hand, or on the other, a set of general ideas of real importance that are nevertheless kept frustratingly incipient – social theory that dare not speak its name” (Goodale 2009, 7).

  8. 8.

    Not surprisingly the analysis of human rights intercultural dialogue is the bailiwick of cultural anthropologists (An-Na’im 2010; Eberhard 2001).

  9. 9.

    For Habermas , “the legitimacy of the rule of law depends, rather, on the institutionalization of those procedural norms, through which the private individual is recognized, not just as a bearer of fundamental rights but also as a potential contributor to those discursive processes through which the idea of the common good gains legal sanction” (Johnson 2001, 45). Concretely, the procedural norms that Habermas has in mind are those that “guarantee the discursive mode by means of which generation and application of legislative programs are to proceed within the parameters of rational debate. This implies the institutionalization of legal procedures that guarantee an approximate fulfillment of the demanding preconditions of communication required for fair negotiations and free debates. These idealizing preconditions demand the complete inclusion of all parties that might be affected, their equality, free and easy interaction, no restrictions of topic and topical contributions, the possibility of revising the outcomes, etc. In this context the legal procedures serve to uphold within an empirically existing community of communication the spatial, temporal, and substantive constraints on choices that are operative within a presumed ideal one” (Habermas 1992, 449). For a range of responses to Habermas’ critical theory , see Meehan (2013).

  10. 10.

    Alexander ’s is not a jejune vision of civil society. From the start he concedes that justice is a possibility that is “devilishly difficult to obtain” because of the contradictions of institutionalization but most fundamentally “because meaning is relational and relative” and “the civility of the self always articulates itself in language about the incivility of the other” (2006, 50).

  11. 11.

    For the purposes of theoretically locating the strong programme, Alexander and his collaborators divide sociological analyses of culture into two camps: the sociology of culture and cultural sociology. The latter is reserved for the strong programme, while the former is used to refer to all those approaches, the majority in sociology according to Alexander and Smith , that understand culture as an effect of social structure, thus depriving culture of any real autonomy. Social structure refers to the social processes whereby individuals are differentially distributed in social space leading to identity, interest and group formation, in different spheres and at different scales (e.g., gender, class, nation). Social structure is also conjoined with material factors (Alexander and Smith 2003, 11). A cultural sociology , in contrast to a sociology of culture, should be able to identify cultural determinants that function as an “independent variable” identifying “inputs every bit as vital as more material or instrumental forces” (Alexander and Smith 2003, 12). Although this first step is heuristically very useful in opening up a conceptual space for the autonomy of culture, collapsing the totality of the sociology of culture, cultural studies, and Foucauldian analyses under the rubric the sociology of culture cuts the strong programme off from many explanatory elements and mechanisms that could potentially enrich its analysis.

  12. 12.

    I am not discounting the important explanatory power of these elements; I believe they alone do not suffice.

  13. 13.

    In practical conceptual terms, this is accomplished by opposing affect and meaning, which Alexander and Smith see as being generated by the deep structures of culture, with purely instrumental, coerced, or reflexive action. Moreover since culture is transversal to social phenomena, even the most interest-laden action or the most technocratic and rational of bureaucracies are not devoid of the horizon of meaning and affect that culture enables (Alexander and Smith 2003, 12). Thus it is possible to distil the cultural structure that provides any social phenomenon with meaning by “bracketing-out” social relations that are non-symbolic (Alexander and Smith 2003, 14).

  14. 14.

    Somers is referring to the structural or normative autonomy of social institutions. Mention of the relational materialism of science studies is particularly apropos because as Alexander and Smith note, the designation of “strong” is taken from the strong programme in science and technology studies, which they understand to mean the “radical uncoupling of cognitive content from natural determination”. Translated into the cultural sphere this requires, they contend, an uncoupling of social structure and cultural structure (2003, 13). I am not convinced that this is a felicitous translation. A more pertinent uncoupling of meaning and its indetermination by the intransitive domain of reality is to be found in the work of Roy Bhaskar (Bhaskar 1978; see López and Potter 2001).

  15. 15.

    In this respect, Alexander is critical of Gramsci’s conception of hegemony, Althusser ’s notion of interpellation, and Foucault ’s conflation of power and knowledge. He argues that these authors assume an automaticity that obscures the contingency of performance, going as far as claiming that they “assume powerful scripts, great actors, compliant audiences, corrupted or brainwashed journalists, and bought-off critics. With a wave of the hand, texts become automatically transformed into successful action. Whether it is law, school books, movies, political campaigns or wars, background representations are assumed to speak, and to speak persuasively” (Alexander 2011, 88). This is, to my mind, an overstatement. After all, Gramsci’s theory of hegemony represents an attempt not only to explain the failure of the performance of a socialist script but also to theorize the conditions under which the performance of hegemonic worldviews might equally backfire (Gramsci 1971). Similarly, Foucault ’s conceptualization of knowledge in the context of fields of dispersion (1972), or in terms of micro-politics (1995), frames social performances as contingent and subject to failure. Finally, with respect to Althusser, the problem is perhaps not due to his conception of interpellation, but to his functionalist understanding of the role of ideology in social reproduction (Hirst 1976). All the same, it is worth remembering that Althusser was keen to displace accounts of the social in terms of expressive totalities, and his theoretical work was oriented towards tooling thought to grasp the complexity of the social (López 2003, 115–37). What is more, Judith Butler, an author whose conception of performativity Alexander cites favourably (2011, 217–18), persuasively claims that Althusser ’s conception of interpellation remains central for contemporary theories of subject formation and “continues to survive its critique” (Butler 1995, 6).

  16. 16.

    The classic source of performance theory outside of dramaturgical studies is of course cultural anthropology, namely, the work of Victor Turner (1985, 1986; see Gonquergood 1989) and James Clifford (1988), the linguistic theory of John Austin (1962; see Hall 1999), and the work of the philosopher Judith Butler (1988), all of which are acknowledged by Alexander (2011). For overviews of performance theory across the humanities and the social sciences, see Bauman and Briggs (1990), Carlson (2013), and Schechner (2004).

  17. 17.

    Of course the notion of a “successful performance” is difficult to disentangle in the context of human rights. While a human rights performance might resonate as morally meaningful to an audience, this in itself does not guarantee that the resources and capacity will be available to remediate the situation. Indeed as Moyn argues, if worldly success were required to maintain the vitality of human rights, then “their worth will ultimately be open to doubt, sooner or later” (2015, 180). That this has yet to be the case indicates that performance in this second and fuller sense, namely, as change inducing, has not been heretofore necessary for the “successful” performance of human rights. Said differently, “Why does all the energy and effort going into human rights activism produce such decidedly meager results? How could the rhetoric of human rights be so globally pervasive while the politics of human rights is so utterly weak” (Cmiel 2004, 118)?

  18. 18.

    Of course, it is remarkable only in the context of the claims made regarding human rights’ purported long historical pedigree (Ishay 2004; Lauren 1998; Hunt 2007; cf. Moyn 2010, 2014b).

  19. 19.

    This section, as well as my general sociological framing of human rights, draws generously on Moyn ’s pioneering work (2010, 2012, 2014b, 2015) to which I am greatly indebted.

  20. 20.

    For accounts that stress the long roots of human rights, see Lauren (1998) and Ishay (2004) and Cmiel (2004) for a critical overview. The impact of the eighteenth-century revolutions is dealt with by Hunt (2007), while Glendon (2002) is an excellent exemplar of the visionary genre, and Borgwardt (2007) explores the intersection of human rights and American internationalism. The roots of human rights in the abolitionist movement are detailed in Blackburn (2013), while anti-colonialism is dealt with by Burke (2011). Anderson (2003) addresses the criss-crossing of anti-racism and human rights.

  21. 21.

    As Mark Mazower notes, “soon the protagonists of these accounts turn into visionaries and heroes – inspiration for our drabber and less strenuous times: Eleanor Roosevelt , Raphael Lemkin, René Cassin , and other leading figures in the emergence of the UN and especially of its human rights regime are now routinely invoked as reminders of what individual commitment and activism can accomplish” (2009, 6; cf. Bradley 2012, 330). See, especially, Glendon (2002) and Lauren (1998).

  22. 22.

    Lauren , for instance, cites Eleanor Roosevelt , the chair of the Human Rights Committee that drafted the UDHR, who claimed, “At a time when there are so many issues on which we find it difficult to reach a common basis of agreement, it is a significant fact that …[so many] states have found such large measure of agreement in the complex field of human rights” (cited in Lauren 1998, 280).

  23. 23.

    In horticulture a variety typically occurs in nature and is true to type. A cultivar is a “cultivated variety”, the product of human selection and cultivation; it is not necessarily true to type, that is, offspring can differ from parents.

  24. 24.

    I develop this point more fully in my analysis of the development of human rights in Europe in Chap. 6.

  25. 25.

    Probst does not argue that the Holocaust was never mentioned or that it played no role at all, but that it was far from central. This was to change in the 1990s after the fall of the Berlin Wall (2003, 55). Consequently the Holocaust as a founding act of the EU is “only plausible from an ex-post perspective” (Probst 2003, 54).

  26. 26.

    Marco Duranti draws attention to “French right-wing intellectuals such as Alexandre Marc , who had called on Hitler to lead the youth of Europe towards the construction of ‘new order’ in 1933, and Louis Salleron , who had been instrumental in formulating Vichy corporatist policies […] In the Congress’ political committee, Hélène de Suzannet , one of the most outspoken advocates of amnesty for imprisoned collaborators in France tabled a motion in favour of the right of individuals to petition such a court [a European human rights court], and Reginald Thomas Paget , one of the foremost champions of the rights of accused German war criminals and a seminal figure in the ‘Holocaust denial’” (Duranti 2012, 161). Duranti argues that “the heretofore overlooked involvement of such figures in the ‘human rights revolution’ suggests that the birth of international human rights law cannot be read so directly out of the Jewish genocide and the [French] republican tradition as commonly supposed” (2012, 161).

  27. 27.

    Christian democracy ’s extraordinary success in shepherding postwar Europe away from authoritarian nationalism and positioning itself as a bulwark against the communist threat through its commitment to market liberalism and parliamentary democracy in part explains its surprising postwar hegemony (Kaiser 2007). However, it is worth remembering that even as recently as the interwar period, Catholics and Christian Democrats were deeply suspicious of parliamentary government, mass democracy, and the market economy (Kaiser 2007, 35), hence their support for more conservative, at times authoritarian, social, and political arrangements. Moyn locates the origin of a personalist-inspired Christian human rights in 1937 and argues that the conception of human dignity and rights underwriting Christian human rights was characterized by its rejection of authoritarianism. However, this disavowal of illiberalism was not only compatible with the conservative moral governance that would flourish in the postwar, such governance was in fact the telos of Christian Human Rights (Moyn 2015, 15; see Duranti 2016).

  28. 28.

    Another notable post-colonial elite committed to Christian human rights is Mark Romulo , the Philippines delegate to the United Nations, who made important contributions to the General Assembly debate on the UDHR (Moyn 2015, 92). Moyn also draws attention to the work of Jacques Maritain , the French Catholic philosopher, whose trajectory towards human rights through personalism is a complex one, as it was for the Catholic Church (2015, 73–89). It required breaking with antecedent authoritarian positions and renouncing critical dismissals of formal rights that had echoed those made by Mounier (2015, 86). Following this, he was to become the “main publicist of Christian personalism” in the UN and beyond, giving it a broader resonance (Moyn 2010, 64).

  29. 29.

    Borgwardt (2007) argues that this being so, the rhetorical shift introduced by the incorporation of the term human rights proved nonetheless to be consequential.

  30. 30.

    Borgwardt notes that when Norman Rockwell , the American illustrator, set out to represent the Four Freedoms that subsequently reappeared in the Atlantic Charter, which “went on to become some of the most enduring icons of the war years form many Americans on the home front”, the internationalist hue of the freedoms was replaced with an exclusively domestic home front palate (2007, 47).

  31. 31.

    Moyn draws attention to the novelty of the right to change religions in Article 18 of the UDHR . This was motivated by the perception that missionary activities might be under threat and pushed several Muslim states to abstain in the General Assembly (Moyn 2015, 152).

  32. 32.

    Origin may not be destiny, but origin can in some case produce structural selectivity. In this context, it is worth mentioning Moyn ’s discussion of recent headscarf jurisprudence in the EU. Whereas many commentators critical of the jurisprudence suggest that decisions supporting headscarf bans arise from excessive secularism and Islamophobia, Moyn reflecting on religious freedom’s original anti-communist rationale draws different conclusions. He writes, the “doctrinal basis on which the cases ultimately rest had nothing originally to do with religion in general or Islam in particular. Instead its source lies in Cold War anxiety that secularist communism would topple Christian democracy . If so, the secularism of the European Court’s headscarf jurisprudence is a recent artifact, primarily following from the collapse of European Christianity in recent memory. Even more ironically […] the European Court headscarf cases actually owe part of their doctrinal rationale and perhaps their exclusionary associations not to the secularist associations of religious freedom but to the legacy of religious struggles against communism once feared as secularism incarnate. The Muslim has taken the place of the communist in European imagination – and above all in the history of the religious liberty norm” (2015, 145).

  33. 33.

    It is however worth noting that less sanguine readings of the conjugation of social security and postwar internationalism can be made, see, for instance, Neocleous (2008), as well as significant shortcomings of the Nuremberg trials, see, for instance, Sellars (2002) and Zolo (2009).

  34. 34.

    As historian, political, and legal scholar Mary L. Dudziak shows in her finely researched monograph Cold War Civil Rights, leveraging a critique of American racism via the UDHR was blocked to African Americans. This is because “to criticize the nation before an international audience and to air the nation’s dirty laundry overseas was to reinforce the negative impact of American racism on the nation’s standing as a world leader. It was seen, therefore, as a great breach of loyalty. As a result, just as the House Committee on Un-American Activities and the government’s loyalty security programme silenced progressive voices within the United States, through passport restrictions and international negotiations the long arm of US government red-baiting silenced critics of US racism overseas” (2011, 12). Dudziak ’s work compelling shows how an understanding of the national civil rights reforms necessitates putting them in an international context. Insofar, as the US sought to position itself as a world leader in the Cold War, accusations of racism and racial violence tarnished its image, affecting its foreign relations strategies. One could think here about the US state’s concerns to prevent newly independent countries in the global south from falling into the Soviet sphere of influence. Consequently, argues Dudziak , “[t]he Cold War created a constraining environment for domestic politics. It also gave rise to new opportunities for those who could exploit Cold War anxieties, while yet remaining within the bounds of acceptable ‘Americanism’” (2011, 15). Ironically, the attempt to introduce a human rights logic to the civil rights struggles, under the banner of anti-imperialism and colonialism, undertaken by more radical figures such as Malcolm X in the late 1960s (Dudziak 2011, 224–25), occurred at a conjuncture when the Vietnam War would replace civil rights as the issue defining US prestige abroad, after which civil rights would become peripheral to US foreign affairs (Dudziak 2011, 248). Moreover, as explored in Chap. 6, it was precisely the link between human rights and anti-colonialism that made lawyers allergic to human rights.

  35. 35.

    Parenthetically, Keys notes Amnesty International in the US “was saddled, too, with a name that for most Americans immediately conjured up the deeply polarizing issue of amnesty for Vietnam War draft resisters. In the early 1970s AI USA staff feared its mail was being sabotaged by postal workers who misconstrued the amnesty in its title” (2014, 89).

  36. 36.

    The following paragraphs draw extensively from Keys’ analysis (2014, 103–213).

  37. 37.

    Scoop , as he was known, assembled a group of political operators such as Richard Perle , Douglas Feith , Elliott Abrams , Donald Rumsfeld , and Paul Wolfowitz who would become key players in the rise of neoconservatism (Keys 2014, 103; Boot 2004; Vaïsse 2010).

  38. 38.

    Term used to describe Soviet Jews who were “refused” permission to emigrate to Israel; see Peretz (2017).

  39. 39.

    This, of course, chimed with the retreat from grand utopian projects of social transformation and the minimalist and moralized politics that had provided fertile ground for the emergence of contemporary human rights, as discussed above.

  40. 40.

    A strategic site of intervention, as Keys documents, was the foreign aid authorization bill. While liberals denounced foreign aid for supporting oppressive regimes, conservatives lambasted its ballooning cost and status as overly generous hand-out. This meant that bipartisan support could be secured for efforts to reduce aid to undemocratic regimes. In addition, because this was a bill that came around every year, the bill became a magnet for all manner of amendments (Keys 2014, 139).

  41. 41.

    As Keys (2014, 264–66) and others have argued, most notably Snyder (2011), more consequential for transnational human rights organizing would be the impact of the Helsinki Final Act , signed during the presidency of Gerald Ford . Sarah B. Snyder argues that “the Helsinki process was one factor that shaped Gorbachev’s thinking about human rights, self-determination and nonviolence, all of which contributed to the demise of communism in Eastern Europe and the collapse of the Soviet Union” (2011, 217).

  42. 42.

    It is interesting to note that “Ronald Reagan, William Haig and William Casey, and other high officials read and praised Claire Sterling ’s book The Terror Network , only to later discover to their embarrassment that it was based essentially on CIA disinformation ‘blown back’” (Zulaika and Douglass 1996, 14). Nonetheless, “[i]n general, during the 1980s, counterterrorism became a surrogate for earlier efforts to fight Communist subversion abroad, whereas at home it became ‘the talisman’ the FBI needed to conduct investigations of those in opposition to the Reagan administration’s policies in Central America’” (Zulaika and Douglass 1996, 15).

  43. 43.

    Robert L. Bernstein created Helsinki Watch in 1978, with Orville Schell Jr., an elite New York lawyer, and Aryeh Neier who was finishing his tenure as the director of the American Civil Liberties Union. Bernstein , chairman and CEO of Random House, had become concerned with the situation of dissident writers during a visit to the Soviet Union (Neier 2012, 205). Funded first by the Ford and subsequently by the MacArthur Foundations, Helsinki Watch focused its attention on the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe. The election of Ronald Reagan , who first attempted to dismiss human rights and then co-opt them for anti-communism, forced the organization to widen its mandate: “The Leaders of Helsinki Watch were concerned that in such circumstances, an American organization that denounced abuses of human rights by the Soviet Unions and the states it controlled, but did not also deal with abuses of human rights regimes aligned with Washington would lose credibility. It would be seen simply as a mouthpiece for an administration that had made clear its intention to use accounts of human rights abuse as a stick to belabor its enemies while serving as an apologist for severe abuses by its friends” (Neier 2012, 206–7). This eventuated in the America’s Watch Committee (Neier 2012, 207).

    Neier argues that the competitive advantage that Helsinki Watch , and then Human Rights Watch , had over Amnesty International in the 1980s in the US was due to the latter’s initial narrow focus on prisoners of conscience (Neier 2012, 204). Freedom Watch , which would also become a key player in the field of human rights, “emphasized to its donors that it had no ties to Amnesty and privately criticized its rival for focusing on the effects rather than the causes of repression and for ‘emphasiz[ing] the most aberrational acts of violence by the government’” (Keys 2014, 213). Helsinki Watch , on the other hand, expanded its mandates to new areas such as the violations of the laws of war, was more streamlined and could react more quickly to changing conditions as a result of its non-reliance on membership funding, and was openly engaged in the practice of trying to steer US foreign policy in the direction of human rights promotion (Neier 2012, 202–5). This said, as Keys careful analysis shows, Amnesty International had more of an impact on US foreign policy than it first appears (2014, 206–12).

  44. 44.

    Overall the authors conclude, “we find that human rights do play a role in the decision of who receives US bilateral foreign assistance, and how much aid they are allotted. But other national security interests play a more prominent role. Countries perceived to be of vital importance to US national security, as measured by the presence of military personnel, along with Latin America, receive aid regardless of their human rights records” (Apodaca and Stohl 1999, 196). This is telling, as Latin America was a key focus of human rights activism during the Carter and Reagan administrations.

  45. 45.

    This self-evidence as I will show in the next chapter is the product of the human rights political imaginary. Consequently its conditions of possibility need to be investigated rather than taken at face value.

  46. 46.

    Consequently, although to my mind, Borgwardt may not show how human rights were internationalized, she nonetheless convincingly shows how the values of the New Deal were. She accomplishes this by outlining the semiotic, political, cultural, and economic relational matrix that overdetermined their internationalization. Consequently her historical account by no means constitutes a thin account.

  47. 47.

    My approach to sociological explanation does not prioritize theory over empirical work. In fact, as noted in the book’s introduction, the political imaginary framework was developed in the context of my empirical historical research on the emergence of the human right to food (López 2015), from which the discussion that follows draws.

  48. 48.

    Of course, this corresponds to Althusser ’s definition of ideology. Admittedly it has shortfalls as a theory of ideology; nonetheless it has been very productive as a theory of subjectivation (Butler 1995; López 2003, 133–37). What is more, Althusser ’s inability to develop a tenable distinction between ideology and science does not mean that the concept of ideology should be abolished; for a powerful defence of the pertinence of ideology as an analytical category in the context of the cultural turn, see Purvis and Hunt (1993).

  49. 49.

    The field of dispersion is of course of Foucauldian provenance, from his work on the archaeology of knowledge (1972).

  50. 50.

    I address my own standpoint on objectivity in sociological practice in the next chapter.

Bibliography

  • Afshari, Reza. 2007. “On Historiography of Human Rights Reflections on Paul Gordon Lauren’s The Evolution of International Human Rights: Visions Seen.” Human Rights Quarterly 29 (1):1–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ake, Claude. 1987. “The African Context of Human Rights.” Africa Today 34 (1/2):5–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey C. 2003. The Meanings of Social Life: A Cultural Sociology. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey C. 2006. The Civil Sphere. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey C. 2011. Performance and Power. Cambridge and Malden, MA: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey C., and Pjillip Smith. 2003. “The Strong Program in Cultural Sociology: Elements of a Structural Hermeneutics.” In The Meanings of Social Life: A Cultural Sociology, edited by Jeffrey C. Alexander, 11–26. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, Louis. 1971. Lenin and Philosophy, Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Carol Elaine. 2003. Eyes off the Prize: The United Nations and the African American Struggle for Human Rights, 1944–1955. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anleu, Sharyn Roach. 1999. “Sociologists Confront Human Rights: The Problem of Universalism.” Journal of Sociology 35 (2):198–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi Ahmed, ed. 2010. Human Rights in Cross-Cultural Perspectives: A Quest for Consensus. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apodaca, Clair, and Michael Stohl. 1999. “United States Human Rights Policy and Foreign Assistance.” International Studies Quarterly 43 (1):185–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armaline, William T., Davita S. Glasberg, and Bandana Purkayastha. 2015. The Human Rights Enterprise: Political Sociology, State Power, and Social Movements. Cambridge and Malden, MA: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, John. 1962. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Richard, and Charles L. Briggs. 1990. “Poetics and Performance as Critical Perspectives on Language and Social Life.” Annual Review of Anthropology 19:59–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baxi, Upendra. 1998. “Voices of Suffering and the Future of Human Rights.” Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems 8:125–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles R. 2011. The Idea of Human Rights. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel A. 2000. East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengtsson, Jan Olof. 2006. The Worldview of Personalism: Origins and Early Development. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. 1978. A Realist Theory of Science, Brighton. Brighton: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Robin. 2013. The American Crucible: Slavery, Emancipation and Human Rights. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau, Judith R., and Alberto Moncada. 2005. Human Rights: Beyond the Liberal Vision. Lanham, MD and New York: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boot, Max. 2004. “Neocons.” Foreign Policy 140:20–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borgwardt, Elizabeth. 2007. A New Deal for the World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, Pierre. 1992. “The Paris Workshop”. In An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology, edited by Pierre Bourdieu and Loïc JD Wacquant, 218–260. Chicago: University of Chicago press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Mark Philip. 2012. “Approaching the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.” In The Human Rights Revolution: An International History, edited by Akara Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 327–344. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricmont, Jean. 2006. Humanitarian Imperialism: Using Human Rights to Sell War. New York: NYU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Wendy. 2004. “‘ The Most We Can Hope For...’: Human Rights and the Politics of Fatalism.” The South Atlantic Quarterly 103 (2):451–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Roland. 2011. Decolonization and the Evolution of International Human Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1988. “Performative Acts and Gender Constitution: An Essay in Phenomenology and Feminist Theory.” Theatre Journal 40 (4):519–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1995. “Conscience Doth Make Subjects of Us All.” Yale French Studies 88:6–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2011. Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of Sex. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carleton, David, and Michael Stohl. 1985. “The Foreign Policy of Human Rights: Rhetoric and Reality from Jimmy Carter to Ronald Reagan.” Human Rights Quarterly, 205–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, Marvin. 2013. Performance: A Critical Introduction. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castoriadis, Cornelius. 1998. The Imaginary Institution of Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford, James. 1988. The Predicament of Culture: Twentieth-Century Ethnography, Literature and Art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cmiel, Kenneth. 2004. “The Recent History of Human Rights.” The American Historical Review 109 (1):117–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobbah, Josiah A.M. 1987. “African Values and the Human Rights Debate: An African Perspective.” Human Rights Quarterly 9 (3):309–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. Daniel. 2012. “The Holocaust and the ‘Human Rights Revolution’: A Reassessment.” In The Human Rights Revolution: An International History, edited by Akara Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 53–72. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa Santos, Boaventure. 2008. “Human Rights as an Emancipatory Script: Cultural and Political Conditions.” In Another Knowledge Is Possible, edited by Boaventura De Sousa Santos, 3–40. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLanda, Manuel. 2002. Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. London: Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1994. Difference and Repetition. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diner, Dan. 1997. “On Guilt Discourse and Other Narratives: Epistemological Observations Regarding the Holocaust.” History and Memory 9 (1/2):301–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diner, Dan. 2003. “Restitution and Memory: The Holocaust in European Political Cultures.” New German Critique 90:36–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diner, Hasia. 2010. We Remember with Reverence and Love: American Jews and the Myth of Silence After the Holocaust, 1945–1962. New York: NYU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, Jack. 1984. “Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights.” Human Rights Quarterly 6:400–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douzinas, Costas. 2007. Human Rights and Empire: The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubiel, Helmut. 2003. “The Remembrance of the Holocaust as a Catalyst for a Transnational Ethic?” New German Critique 90:59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dudziak, Mary L. 2011. Cold War Civil Rights: Race and the Image of American Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duranti, Marco. 2012. “The Holocaust, the Legacy of 1789 and the Birth of International Human Rights Law: Revisiting the Foundation Myth.” Journal of Genocide Research 14 (2):159–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duranti, Marco. 2016. The Conservative Human Rights Revolution: European Identity, Transnational Politics, and the Origins of the European Convention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberhard, Christoph. 2001. “Towards an Intercultural Legal Theory: The Dialogical Challenge.” Social & Legal Studies 10 (2):171–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckel, Jan, and Samuel Moyn, ed. 2014. The Breakthrough: Human Rights in the 1970s. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emirbayer, Mustafa. 2004. “The Alexander School of Cultural Sociology.” Thesis Eleven 79 (1):5–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, David M., and Frank W. Munger. 2003. Rights of Inclusion: Law and Identity in the Life Stories of Americans with Disabilities. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ewick, Patricia, and Susan S. Silbey. 1998. The Common Place of Law: Stories from Everyday Life. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough, Norman. 2003. Analysing Discourse: Textual Analysis for Social Research. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough, Norman, Bob Jessop, and Andrew Sayer. 2002. “Critical Realism and Semiosis.” Alethia 5 (1):2–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fassin, Didier. 2012. Humanitarian Reason: A Moral History of the Present. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1972. The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1995. Discipline and Punish. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, Michael. 1994. “The Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights.” Human Rights Quarterly 16:491–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaonkar, Dilip Parameshwar. 2002. “Toward New Imaginaries: An Introduction.” Public Culture 14 (1):1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glendon, Mary Ann. 2002. A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonquergood, Dwight. 1989. “Poetics, Play, Process, and Power: The Performative Turn in Anthropology.” Text and Performance Quarterly 9 (1):82–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, Mark. 2009. Surrendering to Utopia: An Anthropology of Human Rights. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections Form the Prison Notebooks. Edited and Translated by Q.Hoare & GN Smith. New York: International Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregg, Benjamin. 2011. Human Rights as Social Construction. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. “Further Reflections on the Public Sphere.” In Habermas and the Public Sphere, edited by Craig J. Calhoun, 421–461. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2012. “The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights.” Metaphilosophy 41 (4):464–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, Kita. 1999. “Performativity.” Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 9 (1/2):184–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, Paul. 1976. “Althusser and the Theory of Ideology.” Economy and Society 4 (5):385–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopgood, Stephen. 2006. Keepers of the Flame. Understanding Amnesty International. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, Lynn Avery. 2007. Inventing Human Rights: A History. New York and London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hynes, Patricia, Michele Lamb, Damien Short, and Matthew Waites. 2012. “The Sociology of Human Rights: Editorial Foreword.” Sociology 46 (5):787–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ignatieff, Michael. 2001. Human Rights as Politics and Human Rights as Idolatry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishay, Micheline R. 2004. The History of Human Rights. Berkeley and London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jessop, Bob. 2004. “Critical Semiotic Analysis and Cultural Political Economy.” Critical Discourse Studies 1 (2):159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jessop, Bob. 2010. “Cultural Political Economy and Critical Policy Studies.” Critical Policy Studies 3 (3–4):336–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jessop, Bob. 2013. “Recovered Imaginaries, Imagined Recoveries: A Cultural Political Economy of Crisis Construals and Crisis Management in the North Atlantic Financial Crisis.” In Before and Beyond the Global Economics Crisis: Economics, Politics and Settlement, edited by Mats Brenner, 234–254. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jessop, Bob, and Stijn Oosterlynck. 2008. “Cultural Political Economy: On Making the Cultural Turn Without Falling into Soft Economic Sociology.” Geoforum 39 (3):1155–1169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jessop, Bob, and Ngai-Ling Sum. 2006. “Towards a Cultural International Political Economy: Poststructuralism and the Italian School.” In International Political Economy and Poststructural Politics, 157–176. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Pauline. 2001. “Distorted Communications Feminism’s Dispute with Habermas.” Philosophy & Social Criticism 27 (1):39–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, Wolfram. 2007. Christian Democracy and the Origins of European Union. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kausikan, Bilahari. 1993. “Asia’s Different Standard.” Foreign Policy 92:24–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keck, Margaret E., and Kathryn Sikkink. 1998. Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, David. 2005. The Dark Sides of Virtue: Reassessing International Humanitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kersbergen, Kees van, and Bertjan Verbeek. 1994. “The Politics of Subsidiarity in the European Union.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 32 (2):215–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keys, Barbara J. 2012. “Anti-Torture Politics: Amnesty International, the Greek Junta, and the Origins of the Human Rights Boom in the United States.” In The Human Rights Revolution: An International History, edited by Akara Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 201–222. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keys, Barbara J. 2014. Reclaiming American Virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kurasawa, Fuyuki. 2007. The Work of Global Justice: Human Rights as Practices. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, Jacques. 1977. Ecrits: A Selection. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laclau, Ernesto, and Chantal Mouffe. 1985. Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers Through Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauren, Paul Gordon. 1998. The Evolution of International Human Rights: Visions Seen. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Daniel, and Natan Sznaider. 2010. Human Rights and Memory. Philadelphia: Penn State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • López, José Julián. 2003. Society and Its Metaphors: Language, Social Theory and Social Structure. London: Continuum Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • López, José Julián. 2009. “Par-Delà L’éthique: Vers Une Sociologie Des Pratiques Éthiques Contemporaines.” Cahiers de Recherche Sociologique 48:27–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López, José Julián. 2015. “The Human Right to Food as Political Imaginary.” Journal of Historical Sociology 30 (2): 239–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López, José Julián. 2016. “Disembedding the Embedded/Disembedded Opposition.” In Markets, Communities and Nostalgai, edited by Christian Karner and Bernhard Weicht, 223–247. London and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • López, José, and Garry Potter, eds. 2001. After Postmodernism: An Introduction to Critical Realism. London: Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, Niklas. 1995. Social Systems. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madsen, Mikael Rask. 2011a. “Reflexivity and the Construction of the International Object: The Case of Human Rights.” International Political Sociology 5 (3):259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mauzy, Diane K. 1997. “The Human Rights and ‘Asian Values’ Debate in Southeast Asia: Trying to Clarify the Key Issues.” The Pacific Review 10 (2):210–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazower, Mark. 2004. “The Strange Triumph of Human Rights, 1933–1950.” The Historical Journal 47 (2):379–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazower, Mark. 2009. No Enchanted Palace: The End of Empire and the Ideological Origins of the United Nations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meehan, Johanna. 2013. Feminists Read Habermas (RLE Feminist Theory): Gendering the Subject of Discourse. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merry, Sally Engle. 2006. “Transnational Human Rights and Local Activism: Mapping the Middle.” American Anthropologist 108 (1):38–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meunier, E-Martin. 2007. Le Pari Personnaliste: Modernité et Catholicisme Au XXe Siècle: Essai. Montreal: Les Editions Fides.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, John W., John Boli, George M. Thomas, and Francisco O. Ramirez. 1997. “World Society and the Nation-State.” American Journal of Sociology 103 (1):144–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moon, Claire. 2012. “What One Sees and How One Files Seeing: Human Rights Reporting, Representation and Action.” Sociology 46 (5):876–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Lydia. 2013. Human Rights and Social Theory. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morsink, Johannes. 1999. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting, and Intent. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2010. The Last Utopia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2012. “Imperialism, Self-Determination, and the Rise of Human Rights.” In The Human Rights Revolution: An International History, edited by Akara Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 159–178. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2014b. Human Rights and the Uses of History. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2015. Christian Human Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mutua, Makau W. 2001. “Savages, Victims, and Saviors: The Metaphor of Human Rights.” Harvard International Law Journal 42 (1):201–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash, Kate. 2009. The Cultural Politics of Human Rights. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neier, Aryeh. 2012. The International Human Rights Movement: A History. Princeton, NJ and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Paul J., and Ellen Dorsey. 2008. New Rights Advocacy: Changing Strategies of Development and Human Rights NGOs. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neocleous, Mark. 2003. Imagining the State. Maidenhead and Philadelphia: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neocleous, Mark. 2008. Critique of Security. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, James W. 1987. Making Sense of Human Rights: Philosophical Reflections on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Berkeley and London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Normand, Roger, and Sarah Zaidi. 2008. Human Rights at the UN: The Political History of Universal Justice. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novick, Peter. 2000. The Holocaust in American Life. Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oxford University Press. 2003. Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, Andy. 2008. “The Development of Holocaust Consciousness in Contemporary Britain, 1979–2001.” Holocaust Studies 14 (2):71–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peck, James. 2011. Ideal Illusions: How the US Government Co-opted Human Rights. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peretz, Pauline. 2017. Let My People Go: The Transnational Politics of Soviet Jewish Emigration During the Cold War. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Porat, Dan A. 2004. “From the Scandal to the Holocaust in Israeli Education.” Journal of Contemporary History 39 (4):619–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Postone, Moishe. 1980. “Anti-Semitism and National Socialism: Notes on the German Reaction to ‘Holocaust.’” New German Critique 19:97–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Probst, Lothar. 2003. “Founding Myths in Europe and the Role of the Holocaust.” New German Critique 90:45–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purvis, Trevor, and Alan Hunt. 1993. “Discourse, Ideology, Discourse, Ideology, Discourse, Ideology…” British Journal of Sociology 44 (3): 473–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarat, Austin, and Thomas R. Kearns. 2009. Law in Everyday Life. Book, Edited. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechner, Richard. 2004. Performance Theory. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheingold, Stuart A. 2004. The Politics of Rights: Lawyers, Public Policy, and Political Change. 2nd ed. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Kirsten. 2002. The Rise and Rise of Human Rights. Stroud: Sutton Pub Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapira, Anita. 1998. “The Holocaust: Private Memories, Public Memory.” Jewish Social Studies 4 (2):40–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shestack, Jerome J. 1998. “The Philosophic Foundations of Human Rights.” Human Rights Quarterly 20 (2):201–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silbey, Susan S. 2005. “After Legal Consciousness.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 1:323–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sismondo, Sergio. 2011. An Introduction to Science and Technology Studies. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaughter, Joseph. 2009. Human Rights, Inc: The World Novel, Narrative Form, and International Law. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Sarah B. 2011. Human Rights Activism and the End of the Cold War: A Transnational History of the Helsinki Network. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. 1993. “Citizenship and the Place of the Public Sphere: Law, Community, and Political Culture in the Transition to Democracy.” American Sociological Review 58 (5):587–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. 1994a. “Rights, Relationality, and Membership: Rethinking the Making and Meaning of Citizenship.” Law & Social Inquiry 19 (1):63–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. 1994b. “The Narrative Constitution of Identity: A Relational and Network Approach.” Theory and Society 23 (5):605–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. 1997. “Deconstructing and Reconstructing Class Formation Theory: Narrativity, Relational Analysis and Social Theory.” In Reworking Class, edited by R. John Hall, 73–106. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. 2008. Genealogies of Citizenship. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R., and Fred Block. 2005. “From Poverty to Perversity: Ideas, Markets, and Institutions over 200 Years of Welfare Debate.” American Sociological Review 70 (2):260–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staples, Amy L. S. 2006. The Birth of Development: How the World Bank, Food and Agriculture Organization, and World Health Organization Changed the World, 1945–1965. Kent, OH: Kent State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Arlene. 2014. Reluctant Witnesses: Survivors, Their Children, and the Rise of Holocaust Consciousness. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stohl, Michael, David Carleton, and Steven E. Johnson. 1984. “Human Rights and US Foreign Assistance from Nixon to Carter.” Journal of Peace Research 21 (3):215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sum, Ngai-Ling, and Bob Jessop. 2013. Towards a Cultural Political Economy: Putting Culture in Its Place in Political Economy. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, Cass. 2009. The Second Bill of Rights: FDR’s Unfinished Revolution – And Why We Need It More Than Ever. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 2002. “Modern Social Imaginaries.” Public Culture 14 (1):91–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teeple, Gary. 2005. The Riddle of Human Rights. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Victor. 1985. On the Edge of the Bush: Anthropology as Experience. Tuscon: University of Arizona Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, Victor. 1986. The Anthropology of Performance. New York: PAJ Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaïsse, Justin. 2010. Neoconservatism: The Biography of a Movement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valverde, Mariana. 2003a. “‘Which Side Are You On?’ Uses of the Everyday in Sociolegal Scholarship.” PoLAR: Political and Legal Anthropology Review 26 (1):86–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valverde, Mariana. 2003b. Law’s Dream of a Common Knowledge. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, Malcolm. 1996. “Human Rights and the Universalization of Interests: Towards a Social Constructionist Approach.” Sociology 30 (3):593–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Carl. 2010. The Moral Dimensions of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Richard A. 2009. “Representing Human Rights Violations: Social Contexts and Subjectivities.” In Human Rights: An Anthropological Reader, edited by Mark Goodale, 134–160. Oxford and New York: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodiwiss, Anthony. 2003. Making Human Rights Work Globally. London: The Glass House Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodiwiss, Anthony. 2005. Human Rights. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodiwiss, Anthony. 2012. “Asia, Enforceable Benevolence and the Future of Human Rights.” Sociology 46 (5):966–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, Slavoj. 2005. “Against Human Rights.” New Left Review 34 (July–August):115–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zolo, Danilo. 2009. Victors’ Justice: From Nuremberg to Baghdad. London: Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zulaika, Joseba, and William A. Douglass. 1996. Terror and Taboo: The Follies, Fables, and Faces of Terrorism. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Julián López, J. (2018). Human Rights as Political Imaginary. In: Human Rights as Political Imaginary. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74274-8_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74274-8_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-74273-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-74274-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics