Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 347 Accesses

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Economics ((BRIEFSECONOMICS))

Abstract

Voting is a common way to resolve disagreements regarding policies to be adopted or candidates to be chosen for various positions and is therefore a necessary ingredient of democratic government. Yet there are numerous voting rules that differ from each other in processing the ballots into voting results. In other words, it is possible that for a given set of voters having a fixed distribution of preferences among the competing alternatives, one would obtain the election of a different alternative as a result of using a different voting rule. We focus on the most obvious desiderata associated with voting procedures, viz., the avoidance of paradoxical outcomes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The agenda of voting was devised by the Bundesrat, the upper chamber of the German federal parliament, while the voters were members of the lower chamber, the Bundestag.

References

  • Leininger, W. (1993). The fatal vote: Berlin versus Bonn. Finanzarchiv, 50, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (2002). Voting procedures under uncertainty. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York.: Springer Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan S. Felsenthal .

Appendices

Exercises

Problem 1.1

You are looking for a new bike and, on the basis of extensive study of relevant journals, three models stand out: Bike 1, Bike 2 and Bike 3. There are three bikes stores in your town: A, B and C. None of them has all these bike models. A has Bike 1 and Bike 2, B has Bike 2 and Bike 3 and C has Bike 1 and Bike 3. Suppose that you would prefer Bike 1 in store A, Bike 2 in store B and Bike 3 in store C. Does your choice behavior exhibit transitivity of underlying preferences? If it does, write down the ranking. If it doesn’t, which changes are needed to make it transitive?

Problem 1.2

Use now three criteria assumed to be of equal importance to you: price, weight, outlook. Suppose that in comparing any two bike models, your preference is determined by the respective ranking of these two models on a majority of criteria. Can you form a set of rankings over the three bike models with respect to the three criteria so that the resulting preference ranking is intransitive?

Problem 1.3

Construct a 3–voter, 3–alternative Condorcet Paradox. Switch the ranking of any two adjacent alternatives in one ranking. Analyze the ensuing profile: is there still an intransitive majority preference relation? Is there a Condorcet Winner?

Answers to Exercises

Problem 1.1

The answer to the first question: No, it doesn’t.

The answer to the second question: Choose Bike 1 in store C.

Problem 1.2

If the preference orderings for bikes (from top to bottom) in terms of the three criteria are as shown in the table below then the resulting ordering is intransitive.

Price

Weight

Outlook

Bike 1

Bike 2

Bike 3

Bike 2

Bike 3

Bike 1

Bike 3

Bike 1

Bike 2

Problem 1.3

Here’s a profile constituting a Condorcet Paradox in which the social preference ordering is intransitive (a \( \succ \) b \( \succ \) c \( \succ \) a):

No. of voters

Preference ordering

1

a \( \succ \) b \( \succ \) c

1

b \( \succ \) c \( \succ \) a

1

c \( \succ \) a \( \succ \) b

Now switch a and b in the first ranking to get:

No. of voters

Preference ordering

1

b \( \succ \) a \( \succ \) c

1

b \( \succ \) c \( \succ \) a

1

c \( \succ \) a \( \succ \) b

Here the social preference ordering is transitive (b \( \succ \) c \( \succ \) a), i.e., b is the Condorcet Winner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Felsenthal, D.S., Nurmi, H. (2018). Introduction. In: Voting Procedures for Electing a Single Candidate. SpringerBriefs in Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-74033-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics