Skip to main content

Conclusion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 308 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 19))

Abstract

Six chapters ago, I argued that philosophical worries about the qualitative dimension of consciousness should not be taken so seriously that they trigger a scientific search for qualia, but neither should those worries be belittled or dismissed. Throughout the book, I drew on the ideas of C. S. Peirce—specifically his ideas about prescission, tone, and iconicity—to articulate why/how those philosophical worries about consciousness make sense. In this concluding chapter, I summarize the resulting stance by clarifying what it can and cannot do. Philosophy of signs can show that the idea of qualia is licensed by reason. However, it cannot promise to capture such qualia by scientific means. Although artificially inspecting the incipient substructure of sign-action is in many ways a useless ability, it satisfies a distinctively human sense of curiosity and wonder.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

References

  • Block N (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 18(2):227–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2000) How not to find the neural correlate of consciousness. Intellectica 2(31):125–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2002) The harder problem of consciousness. J Philos 99(8):391–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (2010) The character of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne M (2016) Brandom, Peirce, and the overlooked friction of contrapiction. Synthese 193(8):2561–2576

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (2011) Consciousness and the introspection of “qualitative simples”. Eidos 15:12–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen MA, Dennett DC (2011) Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends Cogn Sci 15(8):358–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colapietro VM (1989) Peirce’s approach to the self: a semiotic perspective on human subjectivity. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman S (2012) Mental chemistry: combination for panpsychists. Dialectica 66(1):137–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2000) The origins of qualia. In: Crane T, Patterson S (eds) History of the mind-body problem. Routledge, London, pp 169–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham PF (2013) Explaining consciousness: a (very) different approach to the “hard problem”. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 34(1):41–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Little, Brown and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1998) Brain children: essays on designing minds. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2006) Sweet dreams: philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff P (2015) Real acquaintance and physicalism. In: Coates P, Coleman S (eds) Phenomenal qualities: sense, perception, and consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 121–146

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hill CS, McLaughlin BP (1999) There are fewer things in reality than are dreamt of in Chalmer’s philosophy. Philos Phenomenol Res 59(2):445–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (2007) The principles of psychology, vol 1. Cosimo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan MJ (1984) Duns Scotus on the formal distinction. Dissertation, Rutgers University

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J, Ross D, Spurrett D, Collier J (2007) Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (1983) Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pac Philos Q 64(4):354–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (2001) Purple haze: the puzzle of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Livingston PM (2004) Philosophical history and the problem of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loar B (1999) Should the explanatory gap perplex us? In: Rockmore T (ed) Proceedings of the twentieth world congress of philosophy, vol 2. Philosophy Documentation Center, Bowling Green, pp 99–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Majeed R (2013) Pleading ignorance in response to experiential primitivism. Philos Stud 163(1):251–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1931–58) The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 2. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (2005) Chalmers’s naturalistic dualism: a case study in the irrelevance of the mind-body problem to the scientific study of consciousness. In: Erneling CE, Johnson DM (eds) The mind as scientific object: between brain and culture. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 165–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager WE (1995) Consciousness, information, and panpsychism. J Conscious Stud 2(3):272–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager WE (2010) Panpsychism, aggregation and combinatorial infusion. Mind and Matter 8(2):167–184

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (2003) Consciousness and co-consciousness. In: Cleeremans A (ed) The unity of consciousness: binding, integration and dissociation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 59–71

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sommers T (2002) Of zombies, color scientists, and floating iron bars. Psyche 8(22)

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson G (1999) The self and the SESMET. J Conscious Stud 6(4):99–135

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson G (2015) Real direct realism: reflections on perception. In: Coates P, Coleman S (eds) Phenomenal qualities: sense, perception, and consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 214–253

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1996) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 3(4):330–349

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (2001) Philosophical investigations (trans: Anscombe GEM). Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo S (1993) Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philos Phenomenol Res 53(1):1–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Champagne, M. (2018). Conclusion. In: Consciousness and the Philosophy of Signs. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 19. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-73338-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics