Skip to main content

Using Prescission and the Type/Token/Tone Distinction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Consciousness and the Philosophy of Signs

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 19))

  • 321 Accesses

Abstract

In the previous chapter, I argued that Peirce was on the right track when he approached the mind from a semiotic perspective. Having offered a primer on semiotics, I now want to use some of those helpful resources. Ned Block distinguishes access-consciousness and phenomenal-consciousness. Convinced that his distinction is a real one, Block posits a module in the brain responsible for phenomenal experiences. However, I argue that we can make better sense of Block’s distinction if we regard it as a prescissive one. In order to clarify this stance, I examine experiments conducted by George Sperling. Sperling designed tasks that let test subjects access visual experiences that they previously could not act upon. Block thinks that Sperling’s results vindicate his claims, but strictly speaking Sperling’s experiments tracked only access-consciousness. I thus conclude that, to establish that phenomenal experiences were present prior to being accessed, we must prescissively suppose the subjects’ tasks absent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Armstrong DM (1989) Universals: an opinionated introduction. Westview Press, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne T (2010) The unity of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne T, Chalmers DJ (2003) What is the unity of consciousness? In: Cleeremans A (ed) The unity of consciousness: binding, integration and dissociation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 23–58

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1978) Troubles with functionalism. In: Savage CW (ed) Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol 9. Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis, pp 261–325

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1992) Begging the question against phenomenal consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 15(2):205–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1995a) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 18(2):227–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1995b) Mental paint and mental latex. In: Villanueva E (ed) Philosophical issues, vol 7. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 19–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1997) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness: philosophical debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 375–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1999) Ridiculing social constructivism about phenomenal consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 22(1):199–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2000) How not to find the neural correlate of consciousness. Intellectica 2(31):125–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2003) Mental paint. In: Hahn M, Ramberg B (eds) Reflections and replies: essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 165–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2007) Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behav Brain Sci 30(5–6):481–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2011) Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends Cogn Sci 15(12):567–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bornstein RF, Pittman TS (eds) (1992) Perception without awareness: cognitive, clinical, and social perspectives. Guilford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (1997) Some like it hot: consciousness and higher-order thoughts. Philos Stud 86(2):103–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1997) Availability: the cognitive basis of experience. Behav Brain Sci 20(1):148–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne M (2009) Some semiotic constraints on metarepresentational accounts of consciousness. In: Deely JN, Sbrocchi LG (eds) Semiotics 2008. Legas Press, Toronto, pp 557–564

    Google Scholar 

  • Champagne M (2016) Diagrams of the past: how timelines can aid the growth of historical knowledge. Cogn Semiot 9(1):11–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1988) Matter and consciousness. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Chalmers DJ (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58(1):7–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen MA, Dennett DC (2011) Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends Cogn Sci 15(8):358–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colapietro VM (1989) Peirce’s approach to the self: a semiotic perspective on human subjectivity. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart M (1980) Iconic memory and visible persistence. Percept Psychophys 27(3):183–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick F (1993) The astonishing hypothesis: the scientific search for the soul. Scribner’s, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson DH (1970) Mental events. In: Foster L, Swanson JW (eds) Experience and theory. University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, pp 79–101

    Google Scholar 

  • De Gardelle V, Sackur J, Kouider S (2009) Perceptual illusions in brief visual presentations. Conscious Cogn 18(3):569–577

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deely JN (2005) Defining the semiotic animal: how the postmodern understanding of human being supersedes the modern definition “res cogitans”. In: Deely JN, Petrilli S, Ponzio A (eds) The semiotic animal. Legas Press, Toronto, pp 145–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Deledalle G (2000) Charles S. Peirce’s philosophy of signs: essays in comparative semiotics. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1988) Quining qualia. In: Marcel AJ, Bisiach E (eds) Consciousness in modern science. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 42–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2001) Are we explaining consciousness yet? Cognition 79(1–2):221–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1896) The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychol Rev 3(4):357–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J (1946) Peirce’s theory of linguistic signs, thought, and meaning. J Philos 43(4):85–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrell BA (1950) Experience. Mind 59(234):170–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1992) Consciousness reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1974) Special sciences (or: the disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese 28(2):97–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foulquié P, Saint-Jean R (eds) (1962) Dictionnaire de la langue philosophique. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm H (2009) The nature of being human: from environmentalism to consciousness. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Gamble D (1997) P-consciousness presentation / A-consciousness representation. Behav Brain Sci 20(1):149–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gozzano S, Hill CS (eds) (2015) New perspectives on type identity: the mental and the physical. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Güzeldere G (1997) The many faces of consciousness: a field guide. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness: philosophical debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (1988) Privileged access. Mind 97(386):238–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houser N (2010) Peirce, phenomenology and semiotics. In: Cobley P (ed) The Routledge companion to semiotics. Routledge, London, pp 89–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey N (1992) A history of the mind: evolution and the birth of consciousness. Simon and Schuster, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jack AI, Shallice T (2001) Introspective physicalism as an approach to the science of consciousness. Cognition 79(1–2):161–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (2007) The principles of psychology, vol 1. Cosimo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1990) Supervenience as a philosophical concept. Metaphilosophy 21(1–2):1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk R (1974) Zombies versus materialists. Proc Aristot Soc 48:135–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk R (2005) Zombies and consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Legg C (2003) This is simply what I do. Philos Phenomenol Res 66(1):58–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (1983) Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pac Philos Q 64(4):354–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (1997) On leaving out what it’s like. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness: philosophical debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 543–555

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1825) An essay concerning human understanding. Thomas Davison, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner AD, Rugg MD (eds) (1992) The neuropsychology of consciousness. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser U (1967) Cognitive psychology. Appleton Century Crofts, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin N (1996) Consciousness and the origins of thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nöth W (1995) Handbook of semiotics. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Nöth W (2003) Crisis of representation? Semiotica 143(1–4):9–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2007) Reuniting (scene) phenomenology with (scene) access. Behav Brain Sci 30(5–6):521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1931–58) The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1992) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 1. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 2. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen A-V (2006) Signs of logic: Peircean themes on the philosophy of language, games, and communication. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Place UT (1956) Is consciousness a brain process? Br J Psychol 47(1):44–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz JJ (2012) The conscious brain: how attention engenders experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal DM (1997) A theory of consciousness. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness: philosophical debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 729–753

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal DM (2005) Consciousness and mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter DL (1989) On the relation between memory and consciousness: dissociable interactions and conscious experience. In: Roediger HL, Craik FIM (eds) Varieties of memory and consciousness: essays in honour of Endel Tulving. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 355–389

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlicht T (2012) Phenomenal consciousness, attention and accessibility. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 11(3):309–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1992) The rediscovery of the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2012) Methodological encounters with the phenomenal kind. Philos Phenomenol Res 84(2):307–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skagestad P (1999) Peirce’s inkstand as an external embodiment of mind. Trans Charles S Peirce Soc 35(3):551–561

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E (2003) Privileged access. In: Smith Q, Jokic A (eds) Consciousness: new philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 273–292

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperling G (1960) The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychol Monogr Gen Appl 74(498):1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt F (2007) Diagrammatology: an investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stoerig P, Cowey A (1997) Blindsight in man and monkey. Brain 120(3):535–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (1995) Blindsight, orgasm and representational overlap. Behav Brain Sci 18(2):268–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (1996) The function of consciousness. Noûs 30(3):287–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg J (2011) Abusing the notion of what-it’s-likeness: a response to Block. Analysis 71(3):438–443

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz L (1986) Blindsight: a case study and implications. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams J (2016) A process philosophy of signs. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2007) Killing the straw man: Dennett and phenomenology. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6(1):21–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Champagne, M. (2018). Using Prescission and the Type/Token/Tone Distinction. In: Consciousness and the Philosophy of Signs. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 19. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-73338-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics