Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 338 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 19))

Abstract

In this introductory chapter, I preview how philosophy of signs can advance current debates about consciousness. Many philosophers have urged us to distinguish between what an experience does and what an experience feels like. This distinction seems sensible enough, but it renders scientific inquiry insufficient, insofar as experimental methods can only track an experience’s detectable effects. However, Charles Sanders Peirce, the polymath who coined the term “qualia,” saw no tension in this function/quality distinction. Peirce was the founder of American pragmatism and a professional scientist, so he clearly valued tangible verification. Still, his philosophical system countenanced intrinsic qualities under the heading of “Firstness.” Since qualia are usually considered to be at odds with pragmatic verification, I set out to understand how Peirce could (or thought he could) have it both ways. The key, I suggest, is to see how we can sometimes insert distinctions between features that are always bound together. Such “prescissive” distinctions are essential to understanding how signs work. So, while semiotics is currently the least known branch of philosophy ending in –ics, a better understanding of that branch can remedy much of the current puzzlement about qualia.

The elements of every concept enter into logical thought at the gate of perception and make their exit at the gate of purposive action; and whatever cannot show its passports at both those two gates is to be arrested as unauthorized by reason.

Charles Sanders Peirce, “Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction” lecture delivered at Harvard on May 14, 1903

(Reprinted in Peirce 1998, 241)

Each quale is in itself what it is for itself, without reference to any other.

Charles Sanders Peirce, “Quale-Consciousness,” unpublished notes, circa 1898

(Reprinted in Peirce 1931–58, 6.224)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

References

  • Bellucci F, Pietarinen A-V, Stjernfelt F (eds) (2014) Peirce: 5 questions. Automatic Press/VIP, Copenhagen

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 18(2):227–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brent J (1998) Charles Sanders Peirce: a life. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1995) Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 2(3):200–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1996) The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: a philosophical journey into the brain. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen MA, Dennett DC (2011) Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends Cogn Sci 15(8):358–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colapietro VM (1989) Peirce’s approach to the self: a semiotic perspective on human subjectivity. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayton E (2016) Clarence Irving Lewis. In: Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. Available via http://www.iep.utm.edu/lewisci/. Accessed 5 July 2016

  • Deely JN (2009) Basics of semiotics, 5th edn. Tartu University Press, Tartu

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1976) A theory of semiotics (trans: Osmond-smith D). Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1990) The limits of interpretation. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (2000) Kant and the platypus: essays on language and cognition (trans: McEwen A). Harcourt Brace and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer JH (1988) Signs and minds: an introduction to the theory of semiotic systems. In: Fetzer JH (ed) Aspects of artificial intelligence. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, pp 133–161

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer JH (2003) Consciousness and cognition: semiotic conceptions of bodies and minds. In: Smith Q, Jokic A (eds) Consciousness: new philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 298–322

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisch MH (1983) Just how general is Peirce’s general theory of signs? Am J Semiot 2(1–2):55–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisch MH (1986) Peirce, semeiotic, and pragmatism. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1990) The intrinsic quality of experience. In: Tomberlin JE (ed) Philosophical perspectives, vol vol 4. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 31–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Hattiangadi J (2005) The mind as an object of scientific study. In: Erneling CE, Johnson DM (eds) The mind as scientific object: between brain and culture. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 342–366

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst RJ (1959) The problems of perception. George Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Houser N (1983) Peirce’s general taxonomy of consciousness. Trans Charles S Peirce Soc 19(4):331–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philos Q 32(127):127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson R (1971) Selected writings, volume II: word and language. Mouton, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson R (1979) Coup d’œil sur le développement de la sémiotique. In: Chatman S, Eco U, Klinkenberg J-M (eds) A semiotic landscape. Mouton, The Hague, pp 3–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson R (1988) A glance at the development of semiotics. In: Pomorska K, Rudy S (eds) Language in literature. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 436–454

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson R, Pomorska K (1983) Dialogues. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Käufer S, Chemero A (2015) Phenomenology. Polity, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Legg C (2013) What is a logical diagram? In: Moktefi A, Shin S-J (eds) Visual reasoning with diagrams. Birkhäuser, Heidelberg, pp 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (1997) On leaving out what it’s like. In: Block N, Flanagan O, Güzeldere G (eds) The nature of consciousness: philosophical debates. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 543–555

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis CI (1918) A survey of symbolic logic. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis CI (1946) An analysis of knowledge and valuation. Open Court, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Liszka JJ (1996) A general introduction to the semeiotic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Livingston PM (2004) Philosophical history and the problem of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDermott D (2007) Dodging the explanatory gap—or bridging it. Behav Brain Sci 30(5–6):518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philos Rev 83(4):435–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (2012) Mind and cosmos: why the materialist neo-Darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2002) Thinking about consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1931–58) The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1992) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 1. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 2. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen A-V (2006) Signs of logic: Peircean themes on the philosophy of language, games, and communication. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Polidoro P (2015) Umberto Eco and the problem of iconism. Semiotica 206:129–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz JJ (2012) The conscious brain: how attention engenders experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Proni G (2015) Umberto Eco and Charles Peirce: a slow and respectful convergence. Semiotica 206:13–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Queiroz J, Atã P (2014) Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive semiotics. In: Thellefsen T, Sørensen B (eds) Charles Sanders Peirce in his own words: 100 years of semiotics, communication and cognition. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 283–289

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1933) Reviews: collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Isis 19(1):220–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts DD (1973) The existential graphs of Charles S. Peirce. Mouton, The Hague

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross D, Spurrett D (2004) What to say to a skeptical metaphysician: a defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists. Behav Brain Sci 27(5):603–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1910–11) Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 11: 108–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1998) The philosophy of logical atomism. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rydenfelt H (2014) Peirce in Finland. European J Pragmatism Am Philos 6(1):51–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok TA (1979) The sign and its masters. University of Texas Press, Austin

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok TA (1991) Semiotics in the United States. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg H (1956) Husserl’s and Peirce’s phenomenologies: coincidence or interaction. Philos Phenomenol Res 17(2):164–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner P (2013) C. S. Peirce and artificial intelligence: historical heritage and (new) theoretical stakes. In: Müller VC (ed) Philosophy and theory of artificial intelligence. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 265–276

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt F (2007) Diagrammatology: an investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt F (2013) The generality of signs: the actual relevance of anti-psychologism. Semiotica 194(1–4):77–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1996) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 3(4):330–349

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Champagne, M. (2018). Introduction. In: Consciousness and the Philosophy of Signs. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 19. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-73338-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics