Keywords

1 Novus Ordo Seclorum

The motto Novus Ordo Seclorum (‘A new order of the ages’), appearing underneath the unfinished pyramid on the reverse side of the Great Seal of the United States, was coined in 1782 by Charles Thomson . He adapted it from Virgil’s Eclogue IV, a pastoral poem of the first century BCE, where a Sibyl prophesied the fate of the Roman Empire in her longing for a new era of peace and happiness.Footnote 1 Charles Thomson (1729–1824) was the secretary of the Continental Congress ; Footnote 2 his name appeared on the first published version of the Declaration of Independence in July 1776, alongside that of John Hancock, the congress’ president.Footnote 3 Thomson placed the motto beneath the unfinished pyramid,Footnote 4 whose vacant peak stood for the lost monarchy after the renegade colonies have declared themselves independent on 4 July 1776. The pyramid and its motto, therefore, acted as the graphical depiction that marked ‘the beginning of the new American Era’, commencing from the Declaration of Independence .

2 Definitions of Normativity and Precedence

Normativity in modern constitutional dogmaFootnote 5 means the obligatory character of the constitution as a legal regime to controlFootnote 6 and to restrict state power.Footnote 7 This amounts to the positivistic, compulsory, and justiciable nature of constitutional law, its differentiation from and hierarchical precedence over ordinary law Footnote 8 and, moreover, its aggravated alterability.Footnote 9 In the specific provisions of the German Basic Law (Articles 1 section 3, 20 section 3, 79 section 3)Footnote 10 the so-called ‘eternity clause’ in Article 79 section 3 restrains even the constituent power .

Reconsidering constitutional formation, one should be very aware that it is the normativity which is the novelty of the modern constitutional concept arisen out of the American and the French Revolutions at the end of the eighteenth century. Neither governmental legitimisation nor legal binding of political authority were new terms, but rather had long been part of the old constitutional semantics.Footnote 11 Also, the subordination of legislative assemblies—as in the founding document of the Colony of West New Jersey (1676)Footnote 12—remains on the traditional ground of the specific importance of fundamental laws (lois fondamentales) that were higher–ranking than ordinary laws .Footnote 13 In the case of America, it was the break with the English mother country that required a new legal fixture of the (whole) political order . ‘Constitution’ was now connoted as a legal text, fixing the political order into a legal order . This provided, according to the opening sentence of the Virginia Declaration of Rights of 12 June 1776, ‘the basis and foundation of government.’Footnote 14 Normativity is expressed by the positivation in one unified constitutional text. The textual ‘seclusiveness’ stands for the differentiation between constitutional law and ordinary legislature . The old constitutional semantics knew particularly important, fundamental laws ,Footnote 15 but not the idea of a unified law , which is a gauge for the legitimacy of all other laws. As James Iredell phrased it in his ‘Instructions to Chowan County Representatives’ (1783), this was to be a ‘Republic where the Law is superior to any or all the Individuals, and the Constitution superior even to the legislature, and of which the judges are guardians and protectors.’Footnote 16

The central consequence of normativity is the supremacy of the constitution, its precedence . With the American Revolution , constitutional law and other kinds of law were conceptually differentiated , contrary to English terminology.Footnote 17 For the English legal minds, such as Lord Bolingbroke (1678–1751)Footnote 18 or William Blackstone (1723–80),Footnote 19 there was an equivalence between the constitution (or frame) of government and the system of laws.Footnote 20 These theorists and practitioners neither distinguished between fundamental and statutory law , nor measured the latter against the first. By 1776, the American resistance against Westminster produced the notion of a constitution ‘as a written superior law set above the entire government against which all other law is to be measured.’ Footnote 21 The context for this was the American effort to justify the revolution as legitimate breach of law.Footnote 22 The taxation of the colonies by the Westminster Parliament without the consent of the inhabitants, as embodied in the Sugar Ac t (American Revenue Act/American Duties Act) of 1764Footnote 23 and the Stamp Act (Duties in American Colonies Act) of 1765,Footnote 24 was ‘unconstitutional’ , while the resistance of the colonies was, it was argued by those same resistors, ‘constitutional.’Footnote 25 In the context of the eighteenth-century British discourse ‘the terms constitutional and unconstitutional, mean legal and illegal’, as it was explained by William Paley in The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (Philadelphia 1788). It was exactly on this aspect that the Americans diverged from the English terminology. As John Adams Footnote 26 articulated in 1773—even before the American Revolutionary War had begun, and three years prior to the Declaration of Independence —the principal difficulty in the debate with England lay in the ‘different ideas [about] the words legally and constitutionally’,Footnote 27 and in the shift of Westminster from the highest common court to the sovereign lawmaker. This leads us to the analysis of the legal argumentation of the American colonies , and how they conducted their case like a common law litigation in the court of Anglophone public opinion.Footnote 28

3 The Constitutionality of the Colonies’ Legal Argumentation Conducting Their Case like a Common Law Litigation

The colonial lawyers, such as Richard Bland ,Footnote 29 James Otis ,Footnote 30 Daniel Dulany,Footnote 31 John Dickinson ,Footnote 32 James Wilson,Footnote 33 Thomas Jefferson,Footnote 34 John Adams , Alexander Hamilton ,Footnote 35 Charles Carroll of Carrollton,Footnote 36 and James IredellFootnote 37 seemed to ‘conduct their case like a common-law litigation in the court of Anglophone public opinion.’Footnote 38 Other lay leaders, merchants, printers and planters, including Stephen Hopkins ,Footnote 39 Benjamin Franklin ,Footnote 40 Samuel Adams ,Footnote 41 William Hicks , and William Henry Drayton,Footnote 42 showed such a substantive familiarity with the common law reasoning and constitutional thought that one could think of a discursive community between both sides of the Atlantic.

3.1 The British–American Discursive Common Law Community

Key to this common law community was the familiarity with the same textbooks. English and American lawyers alike learned from Blackstone ’s Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765–9),Footnote 43 whose American edition (1771–2) was the only legal textbook in the colonies en route to independence.Footnote 44 The reception of Blackstone in James Kent ’s Commentaries on American Law (1826) demonstrated his great significance for the American understanding of the common law ; indeed, it was the Blackstone commentaries that inspired the American constitutional fathers to conceive of the American president as a temporary, substitute monarch, founded after the ideal of the English king. Blackstone ’s conception of the ‘Rights of Englishmen’ as ‘Rights of Mankind’ is said to be an inspiration for the demand for universal human rights in the American Revolution .Footnote 45 He is also called a mentor for the strong judiciary in the American constitution of 1787 .Footnote 46

Blackstone ’s well-known comment on parliamentary sovereignty Footnote 47 is based on Sir Edward Coke ’s seventeenth-century definition of the supreme jurisdiction of the High Court of Parliament:

Of the power and jurisdiction of the parliament, for making of laws in proceeding by bill, it is so transcendent and absolute, as it cannot be confined either for causes or persons within any bounds. Of this court it is truly said: Si antiquitatem spectes, est vetustissima, si dignitatem, est honoratissima, si jurisdictionem, est capacissima.Footnote 48

Irrespective of this court conception, Blackstone required for Great Britain as an empire with colonies, ‘a supreme, irresistible, absolute uncontrolled authority , in which the jura summi imperii, or the rights of sovereignty reside[d]’Footnote 49 and, as the contemporary Agent for the Province of the Massachusetts Bay in London would have added, ‘to which all other Powers should be subordinate[d].’Footnote 50 This unitarian legislative supremacy in the imperial context was a logical violation of defining Parliament’s sovereignty on the basis of the court’s conception, and deprived the British discourse of any possibility to differentiate between legal and constitutional . This was exactly the legal point at which the colonists had to leave the motherland. They pleaded to be the ‘better Englishmen’, on the basis of the customary limitations for Westminster ’s supremacy in the imperial constitution , which they started to distinguish from the ordinary law .

3.2 Customary Old Liberties Against Parliamentary Absoluteness

The first legal point of the colonists was the differentiation between ‘legal’ and ‘constitutional.’ They argued that acts of Parliament, although legal, were against their ancient liberties under the common law and therefore unconstitutional . Faced with the Stamp Act and the Sugar Act , it became obvious in the colonies that Westminster ‘Parliament […] was no longer simply the highest court among others in the land, but had in truth become the sovereign law-maker of the realm, whose power, however arbitrary and unreasonable, was uncontrollable.’Footnote 51 What the colonists risked losing was the supremacy of common law , established by Sir Edward Coke since the seventeenth century. ‘His’ supremacy of common law translated the inherent customary consensus on liberties since time immemorial into legal arguments against the Stuart absolutism Footnote 52; This common law understanding was present at Westminster in the Whig differentiation between ordinary legislation and the fundamental laws of nature,Footnote 53 benefitting from the theories of natural law expounded by John Locke in his Second Treatise (1689),Footnote 54 and Thomas Rutherforth in his Institutes of Natural Law (1754–6). The fundamental laws of nature were held by the latter ‘to bind the legislative body itself, and not to be alterable by its authority.’Footnote 55 Whereas Rutherforth ’s statement saw Westminster as subject to the fundamental laws of nature, which seemed suitably straightforward for the colonists’ legal argumentation, it was the Locke an natural ‘Law antecedent and paramount to all positive Laws of men’Footnote 56 that lay at the heart of the sovereignty of the British Parliament . In the constitutional struggles against the absolutism of the Stuart dynasty, it provided Westminster with the authority of the last word on public good (publick good; common wealth),Footnote 57 which could not be left to the monarch’s discretion.Footnote 58 The common law background of the Lockean precepts gave significant persuasive weight to the colonial contention that Westminster had no jurisdiction over internal colonial affairs, as well as that the British king had ceased to be king for the colonies .Footnote 59 Indeed, the omnipotent reason of the common law —its reason-based supremacy—was the godfather of the American limitation of any state power by the state goal to protect property in the sense of life, liberty, and possession.Footnote 60 John Phillip Reid explicitly held the ‘American argument [was] similar to the old Whig case against Charles I and James II , except now the supremacy of parliament, not the royal prerogative , was the issue.’Footnote 61 While the British understanding of the unwritten British constitution puts the sovereign parliament at the core, the colonial comprehension of the British complex of statutes, common-law judicial precedents, particular documents having constitutional status (such as the famous Magna Carta of 1215), and constitutional conventions for the structure of government, was a restraint on arbitrary power. The threat of arbitrariness could emanate from any centre of power, be it the throne, the House of Lords, or the House of Commons. Therefore, in the American ‘reading’ of the unwritten British constitution , arbitrary power could also be vested in Parliament. If Parliament legislated for the colonies without a check or balance to call it to account, it ran into danger to act arbitrarily as the Sugar Act and Stamp Act proved.

3.2.1 American Sympathies for the Supremacy of Common Law

According to Sir Edward Coke , the specific historical legitimisation of common law , amounting to its supreme quality , is based on its age, since it is said to date back to the Norman Conquest (1066). This idea, however, did not originate with Coke . The equation of ‘old law’ as ‘good law’ was well established for the common law since the fifteenth century and its overall roots date back to ‘antiquity’. As John Fortescue wrote:

[T]he realm has been continuously regulated by the same custom as it is now, customs which, if they had not been the best, some of those kings would have changed for the sake of justice or by the impulse of caprice, and totally abolished them. [No other laws] are so rooted in antiquity. Hence there is no gainsaying nor legitimate doubt but that the customs of the English are not only good but the best.Footnote 62

This praise of the English law to which Fortescue ‘s oeuvre owes its name, In Praise of the Laws of England (about 1470), deems the proof of the quality of the common law to reside in its unaltered usage since the oldest ages, since time immemorial. The continuous general custom legitimised the unwritten common law : ‘because it is given to all in common it is called common law . And for that there is no other law than this, it exists as one from of old, and in general councils or parliament it is suffered to be observed.’Footnote 63 According to Christopher St. German , the general custom was a universal consensus: ‘the common law proper was divers general customs of old time used through all the realm, which have been accepted and approved by our sovereign lord the King and his progenitors and all their subjects.’Footnote 64

On the other hand, the common law was the purview of lawyers, unknown beyond the realms of the London Inns of Court.Footnote 65 How can a law, based on the technicalities of writs and developed by and for the knowledge of a legal elite, be traced back to the consensus of the people? Nobody, after all, is born as a lawyer.Footnote 66 How could common law lawyers explain that the customary law respected by the judiciary could bind the nation as a whole? This could only be achieved by the judicial consent faking the popular consent . The ‘collective mind of the profession’ thus subsumed and adopted the mantle of authority customarily represented by popular consent .Footnote 67 In this way, artificial reason replaced general custom , more as an interpretative authorityFootnote 68 rather than as legislative consensus.Footnote 69

The foundation for this reasoned concept of the common law was established by Sir Edward Coke in his Reports (1600-15)Footnote 70 and his quadripartite Institutes of the Laws of England (1628-44).Footnote 71 The reasonableness of the common law was the battle cry of the common law lawyers against Stuart absolutism .Footnote 72 It governed the arguments against the prerogative courts and against the royal prerogative . For instance, as the chief justice of the Common Pleas Court between 1606 and 1613, and of the King’s Bench Division between 1613 and 1616, Coke made use of this argumentation to establish the supremacy of the jurisdiction of the common law over the monarch in the writs of prohibition and the case law, namely the Prohibitions del Roy (1607), the Case of Proclamations (1611) and the Case of the Five Knights (1627).

Just as his equation of custom with lawfulness was not new, neither was Coke ’s association of law and reason. As early as Cicero, it had been argued that ‘law is the perfection of reason, which lies within the human nature.’Footnote 73 The synonymy of law and reason therefore marked the medieval Christian state theory by mediation of the scholasticism; law was, according to Thomas Aquinas , ‘nothing else than a certain order of reason for the common wealth, promulgated by the responsible for the community.’Footnote 74 The reason conception of common law , however, was less based on the political philosophical theory but more on the linguistic congruency. It was already in the earliest case law journals (the so-called year books from the thirteenth century onwards)Footnote 75 that Latin-ancient-French legal terminology of Norman originFootnote 76 proves the linguistic equation of the law (ley = law) and reason (reason, resoun) Footnote 77: ‘ley est resoun’Footnote 78; ‘le ley est fond de reason, et ceo que est reason est ley’Footnote 79; ‘[d]onq comon reason, quiest comon ley’Footnote 80; ‘carriens deins le monde parle si reasonablement come le ley parle.’Footnote 81 Occasionally, ‘reason’ and ‘justice’ appear synonymously . For instance, the medieval travel report Mandeville’s Travels from the fourteenth century demonstrates justice in England through the reasonable and equal treatment of the poor and the rich: ‘in that ile also er wonder rightwise iuggez, for they do resoun and trewth to like men, als wele to pouer as to riche.’Footnote 82 Reginald Pecock describes the law of England as reasonable law in The Folower to the Donet (ca. 1453) : ‘And as for the lawe of the kyng of englond, what is iugid bi iugis agens such constreyners, al is taken to be lawe of resoun, which thei callen her common lawe.’Footnote 83

When viewed together with common law , ‘reason’ not only means rationality of the highest degree (ratio summa), but also the intellectual method of the common law lawyers.Footnote 84 ‘Reason’ is the capability acquired by means of legal training to develop legal rules out of the formlessFootnote 85 entirety of the legal knowledge since time immemorial. This was achieved in an inductive manner, handed down through year books and reports of preceding lawyers since the thirteenth century. This is demonstrated by Coke’s terminology of ‘artificial reason’ ,Footnote 86 which found its way into the Prohibitions del Roy (1607).Footnote 87 Like an artist, the lawyer exercises his legal capabilities. The reasonableness of the law is perceived as its character; nobody could be legally knowledgeable if he had not understood that first: ‘The reason of the law is the life of the law, for though a man can tell the law, yet if he knows not the reason thereof, he shall soon forget his superficial knowledge.’ In the first part of his Institutes of the Laws of England, Coke adds to this the need for sustainable professionality. The reason of the law is nothing to be understood in passing: ‘But when he findeth the right reason of the law, and so bringeth it to his natural reason, that he comprehendeth it as his own, this will not only serve him for the understanding of that particular case, but also many others, for cognitio legis est copulata et complicata, and this knowledge will long remain with him.’Footnote 88 ‘Artificial reason’ is the collective knowledge of the common law judges and Coke seems to allude to the scholastic interconnection of human and divine ratio by Thomas Aquinas : ‘ratio est radius divini luminis.’ The metaphorical contrast between the ‘darkness of ignorance’ and the ‘light of legal reason’ super-elevates legal training ‘by reasoning and debating of grave learned men’Footnote 89 as ratio legis, and cements thereby the monopoly of interpretation for the learned lawyers and their superiority over the legally untrained monarch: ‘and thereupon judgement is given according to the law, which is the perfection of reason.’Footnote 90 This legitimation of the common law by means of judicial reasonablenessFootnote 91 corresponds to the authority of the general custom amended through the ages: ‘if all the reason that were dispersed into so many heads were united into one, yet would he not make such a law as the law of England is, because by many successions of ages it hath been fined and refined by so many learned men.’ Footnote 92

It is by making use of the reason conception that Coke justifies the supremacy of the common law : a perfect expression of reason that commands what must be done and bans the opposite. This highest degree of reasonableness as divine wisdomFootnote 93 may be completed in the human spirit in the form of judicial wisdom.Footnote 94 The common law is the judicial understanding of the divine reasonableness and hence of divine origin: ‘without question lex orta est cum mente divina, and this admirable unity and consent in such diversity of things proceeded from God the fountain and founder of all good laws and constitutions.’Footnote 95 Thereby common law defends liberty. In the case of the American colonies , the point of rupture was the liberty of no taxation without political, parliamentary representation. This, they argued, was in the spirit of the Magna Carta (1215); this was the occasion by which American theorists differentiated between a fundamental law of nature and ordinary legislation .

3.2.2 Liberty Defending Common Law Versus Discretion Granting Executive from an American Perspective

In the American colonies the reason-based supremacy of law set itself above all authority, not only above monarchical sovereignty . According to the American body of knowledge on Coke ’s impact on American liberalism ,Footnote 96 the obligation of the prerogative to adhere to an extra-statutory fundamental law (Fundamental Law of Nature and GovernmentFootnote 97; a Law antecedent and paramount to all positive Laws of menFootnote 98) was adapted to become the binding force of the state goal to protect life, liberty, and possession, after the Declaration of Independence (1776) has replaced the Lockean ‘property’Footnote 99 with the pursuit of happiness,Footnote 100 though still tracing Locke ’s idea of property as tied to liberty, consent, and limited government. Opposing Hobbes ’ fear of submission based on mortal danger,Footnote 101 Locke ’s idea of self-determination as an a priori ownership in oneself, in one’s own manpower and resources,Footnote 102 led to the assumption of freedom and equality as intrinsic rights.Footnote 103 The individual freedom to produce wealth by labour results in the material wealth of human society.Footnote 104 From the restriction of ruling onto the protection of life, liberty, and possession, together with the institutional transferral of rights to the powers of the community,Footnote 105 Locke concludes his conception of ruling and governance as akin to a legal-fiduciary trust, which is held in the interest of the ruled ones.Footnote 106 This amounts to a right of resistance of the people (residual power) in case of misconduct without questioning the institutional persistence of a common supreme power, the legislative power as a whole.Footnote 107

The opposition between common law (which defended liberty) and prerogative (which provided for monarchical discretion) was fundamental to Locke ’s differentiation between legislative and executive power : ‘Where the Legislative and Executive Power are in distinct hands, (as they are in all moderated Monarchies, and well-framed Governments) there the good of the Society requires, that several things should be left to the discretion of him, that has the Executive Power .’Footnote 108 To the extent that laws passed by the legislative branch did not contain any rule, the power of decision-making was afforded to the monarchical executive that had discretion: ‘Many things there are, which the Law can by no means provide for, and those must necessarily be left to the discretion of him, that has the Executive Power in hands, to be ordered by him.’Footnote 109 This executive, discretionary decision-making power corresponds to the monarchical prerogative : ‘This power to act according to discretion, for the publick good, without the prescription of the Law, and sometimes even against it, is that which is called Prerogative.’Footnote 110 The public good was the yardstick for discretionary decisions, ‘[f]or Prerogative is nothing but the Power of doing publick good without a Rule.’Footnote 111

Locke , however, was not prepared to leave the decision on the public good to the arbitrary decision of the monarch. While he acknowledged that some decisions were, by necessity, within the purview of the executive discretion ‘as the publick good and advantage shall require’, he continued: ‘nay, ‘tis fit that the Laws themselves should in some Cases give way to the Executive Power , or rather to this Fundamental Law of Nature and Government, viz.’Footnote 112 It was not the will of the ruler, but rather a natural law that existed a priori and was of the highest, extra-statutory nature (‘a Law antecedent and paramount to all positive Laws of men’) that determined the public good, and it was this natural law to which the discretionary decision of the prerogative had to adhere. As Locke pointed out, ‘[t]he old Question will be asked in this matter of Prerogative, But who shall be Judge when this Power is made a right use of?’Footnote 113 Locke ’s answer attributed the ‘ultimate determination’ of the limits of the prerogative to the ‘Law antecedent and paramount to all positive Laws of men’; this was not subject to the final adjudication of any earthly authority. Indeed, if a government were to continuously abuse its exercise of power, the only recourse of the people was to appeal to a morally just ‘supreme judge’ to vindicate their cause and resistance. Redress could thus be achieved through the acquiescence, alteration, or abolition of the offending government, if the popular appeal was based upon the rectitude of their intentions (‘approving consciences’), moral character capable of self-government, and justness of cause: ‘yet they have, by a Law antecedent and paramount to all positive Laws of men, reserv’d that ultimate Determination to themselves, which belongs to all Mankind, where there lies no Appeal on Earth, viz. to judges whether they have just Cause to make their Appeal to Heaven.’Footnote 114

What was ground-breaking for the decisive constitutional normativity in the revolutions of the eighteenth century was not the institutional realization of the Treatises’ separation of the legislative and executive power as different state functions, but the juridification of the starting point to ‘form themselves into a political Society […and to] become a sovereign State,’Footnote 115 which was achieved by building on Locke ’s notion of the natural right of people.Footnote 116 The reasoning of the Virginian planter and later delegate to the Continental Congress Richard Bland (1710–76) transformed the Lockean state of nature into the settlement ‘by Englishmen at their own Expense’, after they had decided ‘to quit the Society of which they are Members, and to retire to another Country.’Footnote 117 Bland ’s argumentation that ‘they recover their natural Freedom and Independence: The Jurisdiction and Sovereignty of the State they have quitted ceases’Footnote 118 was also employed by Benjamin Franklin in his essay ‘On the Tenure of the Manor of East Greenwich.’Footnote 119 This indicates the denial of the Parliament’s authority to legislate on colonial internals to be the second legal point of the common law litigation conducted by the Americans.

3.3 No Westminster Legislation on the Internal Colonial Polities

The next step in the common law litigation against the Sugar Act of 1764 was the argumentation that the Westminster Parliament should be excluded from all legislation over the domestic affairs of the colonies.Footnote 120 After the differentiation between ‘legal’ and ‘constitutional’ and the condemnation of legally-issued statutes infringing upon common law liberties as ‘unconstitutional ’, the American revolutionaries introduced the distinction of the internal colonial polities from the Empire as a whole. Whereas the first are governed by the old liberties and privileges as English subjects (specifically, the right of not being governed by laws made without consent, as indicated in the Magna Carta ), the latter falls under the general superintending power of the British Parliament. This protest, elaborated by the various provincial assemblies of the thirteen colonies, is remarkable in its references to the legal status quo of the British Empire. So, in 1764, the Connecticut Assembly articulated against the proposed stamp duties that it is a ‘fundamental principle of the British Constitution’ that ‘no law can be made or abrogated without the consent of the people by their representatives.’Footnote 121 The wording of the Virginia Assembly’s protest referred explicitly to the ‘ancient and inestimable Right of being governed by such Laws respecting their internal Polity and Taxation as are derived from their own Consent’Footnote 122—again claimed by the Virginia House of Burgesses and reiterated similarly in public resolutions by the assemblies of Rhode Island, Maryland, and Connecticut in September and October 1765.Footnote 123

Of the nine older North American colonies whose assemblies passed resolutions against the Stamp Act (those of Georgia, North Carolina, Delaware, and New Hampshire did not), four claimed exclusive jurisdiction over both taxation and internal legislation (Virginia, Rhode Island, Maryland, and Connecticut). If one also counts the Massachusetts House’s October message to Governor Bernard that the province’s authority to make laws for the ‘internal government and taxation ’ had ‘been never […] questioned; but has been constantly recognized by the King and Parliament’,Footnote 124 this exclusive jurisdiction applied to a majority of five of the nine colonies. When the American colonies pleaded for ‘an exclusive Power of making Laws for their internal Polity and Government,’ they made a recourse to ‘a perfect internal Liberty, as to the Choice of their own Laws, and in all other Matters that are purely provincial.’Footnote 125

3.3.1 Systematic Distinction of ‘Internal’ and ‘External’ Spheres of Colonial Government

The Virginian Richard Bland was the mastermind for the systematic distinction between ‘colonies’ “internal” and “external” spheres of government.’Footnote 126 In The Colonel Dismounted (1764), he explained that because Virginians were entitled to all of the ‘liberties and Privileges of English subjects, they must necessarily have a legal Constitution.’ For him the legal English constitution was defined by ‘a legislature composed in part of the representatives of the people who may enact laws for the INTERNAL government of the colony and suitable to its various circumstances and occasions.’Footnote 127 ‘Without such a representative,’ for Richard Bland ‘no law can be made’, and therefore he concluded that Westminster Parliament , in which the colonists were not represented, ‘had no authority to pass laws for the “INTERNAL government ”’ of the colonies without violating ‘the most valuable part’ of the colonists’ ‘Birthright’ as Englishmen: the right ‘of being governed by laws made with our own consent’, as embodied in chapter 12 of the Magna Carta (1215).Footnote 128 Parliament’s authority for all aspects of ‘EXTERNAL government ’, however, remained unquestioned.Footnote 129 This argument continued in Bland ’s second pamphlet, An Inquiry into the Rights of the British Colonies,Footnote 130 which was published early in 1766 after Westminster had passed the Stamp Act against widespread colonial resistance. Bland ’s associate in the Virginia House of Burgesses , Landon Carter (1710–78),Footnote 131 sang from the same hymn sheet against the Stamp Act and vigorously supported the colonists’ claim ‘of being solely governed and taxed by Laws made with the Consent of the Majority of their own Representatives, according to an Englishman’s inherent Birthright.’Footnote 132

The colonists’ contention that they were ‘the better Englishmen’ can also be traced in the note of four members of the Massachusetts Assembly , including Samuel Adams and James Otis ,Footnote 133 to a London correspondent in December 1765: ‘The general superintending Power of the Parliament over the whole British Empire is clearly admitted here, so far as in our Circumstances is consistent with the Enjoyment of our essential Rights, as Freemen, and British Subjects.’Footnote 134 As Adams pointed out, the ‘general superintending Power over the whole British Empire’ did not cover internal affairs of the colonies. If the colonists were ‘indeed […] British Subjects, (& they never can brook to be thought anything less) it seems necessary that they should exercise this Power within themselves; for they are not represented in the British Parliam[en]t & their great Distance renders it impracticable.’Footnote 135Only if each legislature within the Empire had an exclusive legislative authority within its own jurisdiction, according to the Massachusetts Assembly , was it able to ensure ‘that equality [of rights and status] which ought ever to subsist among all his Majesty’s subjects in his wide extended empire.’Footnote 136

3.3.2 Specific Matters of the Colonies’ Own Nature Versus General Matters of the Empire

Stephen Hopkins , Rhode’s Island’s elected governor, continued on this point still further. ‘In an imperial state, which consists of many separate governments each of which hath peculiar Privileges and of which kind it is evident that the empire of Great Britain is,’ he argued, ‘no single part, though greater than another part, is by that superiority entitled to make laws for or to tax such lesser part.’ This was the reason, Hopkins believed, why each of the colonies had to have ‘a legislature within itself to take care of its interests and provide for its peace and internal government .’Footnote 137 Again, as with Richard Bland and the Massachusetts representatives, Westminster ’s authority for matters of a general nature within the British Empire remained unquestioned. The New York pamphleteer William Hicks similarly stands in this line: To govern the colonies ‘according to the principles of the national constitution,’ he pointed out, required the colonies to be ‘vested with authority of legislation ’ over all provincial matters ‘and have right to be represented in their Assemblies, in whom [alone] that authority [was] lodged.’Footnote 138 A colonists’ supporter in London describes the autonomy of the internal government as the same for the English people and the American people : ‘Our Constitution is so tender of the Rights and Liberties of the Subject,’ wrote the anonymous author of A Vindication of the Rights of the Americans in 1765, ‘that the People of England have their Representatives, the Scotch theirs, the Welsh theirs, the Irish theirs, [and] the Americans theirs, for they have Assemblies and Parliaments, each of which represent the Bulk of the People, of that Generality, or Division, for which such Assembly or Parliament is appointed to be held.’Footnote 139 ‘In extensive Territories not confined to one Island, or one Continent, but dispersed through a great Part of the Globe,’ this British voice for the Rights of the American people carries on, ‘the Laws cannot be put into execution, nor the Rights of the People preserved, without their being arranged into several Classes’ of coordinate legislatures, because each, presumably, has its own exclusive jurisdiction over the internal affairs of its territory.Footnote 140

All these American statements of the second half of the seventeenth century, from Richard Bland to William Hicks , circumscribe the exemption of the imperial constitution from the English constitution of parliamentary supremacy . The customary coinage of the colonial status was furthermore elaborated in the third legal argument developed by the American in their own case.

3.4 Self-reliance of the British Imperial ‘Constitution’

The third legal point was the self-reliance of the imperial constitution with its principled customary limitation, to be differentiated from the British constitution of parliamentary supremac y that had emerged by the 1760s. In the line of arguments, which held Great Britain and the British Empire to be distinct political entities, the focus lies on history, when different groups of colonists each set forth to establish a new settlement in North America in different places, at different times, for different reasons. Some were commercial ventures, others havens of religious liberty for those who founded them, and at least Georgia began as a penal colony. How could the British Empire be administered and coordinated in the colonies, then, when the colonies were at least two months away by ship? One way would have been to forge a workable intercolonial union that could coordinate the individual colonial governments for shared goals without repeated recourse concerning individual policy decisions to the mother country. The failure of this goal narrowed the British options down to long-distance governance: holding the American colonies together for purposes of defense and foreign policy and dealing with them directly to regulate trade and raise revenue. Thus, by 1763, at the conclusion of the Seven Years’ War, the only certainty about constitutional arrangements with the colonies was uncertainty. Blackstone ’s Commentaries only provided his analysis of the state-organisational status of the ‘American plantations’ as ‘distinct dominions.’ He analysed them as ‘subject […] to the control of the parliament; though (like Ireland, Man and the rest) not bound by any acts of parliament, unless particularly named.’Footnote 141 He stressed the self-reliance of the colonial justice: ‘they have courts of justice of their own,’ with a line of appeal ‘to the king in council here in England.’Footnote 142 He acknowledged their own legislation: ‘Their general assemblies which are their house of commons, together with their council of state being their upper house, with the concurrence of the king or his representative the governor, make law suited to their own emergencies.’Footnote 143

The nature of Parliament’s relation to the colonies, however, had not been defined in the Commentaries. This was the gap for the legal argument of exempting the imperial constitution out of the sovereignty of Parliament . The reasoning was as follows: After the Glorious Revolution and the usage of the Bill of Rights during succeeding decades, Britain had obviously consented to the doctrine of parliamentary supremacy in the domestic sphere. In the colonies, though, neither the people at large through custom nor their representatives in the several colonial legislatures had given such consent. There was no point in extending the British constitution to the Empire conglomerate, as Richard Bland has put it, because it was ‘in vain to search into the civil Constitution of England for Directions in fixing the proper Connexion between the Colonies and the Mother Kingdom.’Footnote 144 Whereas the British constitution was based around the sovereignty of Parliament , the imperial constitution through which their colonies were connected to Great Britain remained based on the old common law liberties, usages, and customs, according to the American view.

It was the ‘loose texture’ of Britain’s ‘extended and diversified’ empire—to borrow from the wording of Colonel Isaac Barré’s speech in the House of Commons during the Stamp Act crisisFootnote 145—that allowed for its deviating interpretations, either in an unitarian way (from the perspective of London), or in a federal way (from the perspective of the colonies).Footnote 146 The metropolitan discourse thought the British Empire to be an unitarian state centred around the sovereign Parliament and ‘organized on the principle of devolution.’Footnote 147 From the colonial point of view, there was no concentration of authority within the Empire as being ‘predominantly federal in practice,’Footnote 148 with London’s authority limited by the delegated colonial authorities. These constitutional positions on both sides of the Atlantic were irreconcilable.

For the colonies the British move towards extending Westminster as an intercolonial Parliament with full authority in taxation and all other colonial concerns caused fear of ‘a dangerous federal union.’Footnote 149 In the metropolitan power centre only singular voices in the Commons and the Lords conceded that there were and have to be limits upon Parliament’s colonial authority. Charles Pratt , one of the architects of the Pratt -Yorke opinion of 1757,Footnote 150 had by now been elevated to the title of Lord Camden ; he favoured ‘the sovereign authority, the omnipotence of the legislature,’ but clearly pointed out that there were ‘some things it [Parliament] cannot do.’Footnote 151 In his view the sovereignty did not empower Parliament to act ‘contrary to the fundamental laws of nature, contrary to the fundamental laws of this Constitution.’Footnote 152 His speeches of 2 February and 7 March 1766 were pervaded by implicit distinctions between ordinary law and fundamental law , either borrowing ‘from the Law of Reason and of Nature’ or ‘from [the] Custom and Usage [of] our own Constitution.’Footnote 153 Lord Camden and the likeminded William Pitt the ElderFootnote 154 in the Commons were convinced that fundamental laws and old common law liberties restricted and bound also the legislative body itself and could not be abrogated by any parliamentary sovereignty . For them the ancient British principle of no taxation without representation (chapt. 12 Magna Carta 1215) ranked among these fundamental laws .Footnote 155 Due to the authoritative myth of the Magna Carta and this guarantee, which has already been into the articles of the Barons,Footnote 156 Parliament had ‘never levied Internal Taxes on any subject without their own consent.’Footnote 157 Before the differentiation between Parliament’s authority to tax and its authority to legislate for the colonies emerged in the colonial discourse, Pitt held it explicitly ‘essentially necessary to liberty.’Footnote 158 For the 1st Earl of Chatham and contrary to Robert Walpole, ‘this kingdom, as the supreme governing and legislative power , has always bound the colonies by her laws, by her regulations, and restrictions in trade, in navigation, in manufactures—in every thing, except that of taking their money out of their pockets without their consent.’Footnote 159

Most of the London establishment, though, regarded the power to tax as ‘a necessary part of every Supreme Legislative Authority’ and believed ‘if they have not that Power over America, they have none, & then America is at once a Kingdom of itself’,Footnote 160 as the Connecticut agent Jared Ingersoll reported to his constituents in February 1765. From the London perspective, the logic of the parliamentary supremacy left no space for customary restraints upon the authority of Parliament . Parliament was ‘the only natural, constitutional Seat of complete Jurisdiction in the Kingdom’ and that jurisdiction necessarily extended not just throughout the home islands but ‘over the property and person of every inhabitant of a British colony’ as well.Footnote 161 In his reply to Camden , William Murray, Lord Mansfield (1705–93)Footnote 162 stressed that Parliament represented ‘the whole British empire’ and had ‘authority to bind every part and every subject without the least distinction’ in matters of taxation as well as legislation.Footnote 163 This position in the debate over the repeal of the Stamp Act is consistent with his reasoning in the famous Somerset case ,Footnote 164 in which an American resident was barred from exercising his rights over his slave in England as against the natural laws of mankind and the common law liberty, ‘if not [allowed] by positive law .’Footnote 165 Though celebrated for his enlightened advocacy for freedom, Mansfield implicitly held that a statute could feasibly allow slavery, though the institution of slavery was contrary to fundamental laws .

Pitt and Camden were lone voices crying in the wilderness, whereas for most contemporaries unlimited sovereignty lay in the king-in-Parliament. The overwhelming majority position in the Stamp Act discourse held that customary restrictions upon Westminster ’s authority were synonymous with infringements against the sovereignty of the British crown over the colonies. Representing the metropolitan opinion, Lord Egmont argued that Parliament, by virtue of its ‘supreme, absolute and unlimited’ power, could levy taxes ‘upon the People not by right of their having representatives but [by virtue of their] being subjects to the Government.’Footnote 166

Regardless these arguments, the strength of colonial resistance against the Stamp Act forced Westminster to retract it. However, the repeal was accompanied by the Declaratory Act , which explicitly asserted that Westminster ‘had hath, and of right ought to have, full power and authority to make laws and statutes of sufficient force and validity to bind the colonies and people of America […] in all cases whatsoever.’Footnote 167 This consolidation of the unlimited and inimitable sovereignty of Parliament effectively meant, for the colonists, the fading of ‘the essence of all their British ancestors had fought for, took the very savour out of that fine Anglo-Saxon liberty for which the sages and patriots of England had died.’Footnote 168 Having slammed the door, London had thus set the last scene for the American case conducted like a common law litigation. The legal question of the binding authority of usage and custom for the colonial constitutions was still very much open to debate, and it was exactly this assessment which was needed for justification of the ‘rioting crowds’ in the upheavals against Stamp Act .Footnote 169

3.5 Legal Force of Custom in the Unsettled Connexion of the Colonies to Britain

In their protest against both interference in local affairs by Westminster through legislation and direct parliamentary taxation throughout the Stamp Act crisis, the American colonists put enormous stress on the traditional foundation of their rights in the old common law liberties. In making their arguments for exemption from Westminster legislation and taxation , the colonies’ spokesmen relied on the assumption that the colonial constitutions ‘had been established by long custom and’ that custom ‘was currently sanctioned by accepted usage.’Footnote 170 This redress to custom does not appear to be mere rhetoric. Of course, their argumentation would not have been so convincing if it had not exactly matched the supremacy of law concept established by Sir Edward Coke on the understanding of common law as immortal custom. ‘Times immemorial’ was and remains a commonly-employed phrase by English lawyers. Thus, the customary basis of colonial constitutions might have been felt by the colonists to be a legal argument in itself, one that could not be surmounted by common lawyers. The latter could not help but accept whatever had been done in a community in the very earliest times to be legal, and whatever had been abstained from to be illegal. When the colonists denounced London’s violation of their ‘old rights’ through the alteration of their ‘customary constitution[s]’,Footnote 171 they were in line with ‘a common law way of thinking about politics […] viewing each controversy as a matter, not for free invention or for fresh deduction from first principles, but for judicious choice, with attention to precedent always in order but authoritative solution always elusive.’Footnote 172 In the tradition of the seventeenth-century reasoning the colonists emphasised continuity rather than novelty and established ‘some reason greater than custom alone, for by common law , unreasonable customs have no legal force.’Footnote 173 At the heart of this reason-based customary longing for rights as Englishmen was the Sullivan Draft Footnote 174 of the Declaration and Resolves on Colonial rights of the First Continental Congress of 14 October 1774Footnote 175 which reads as an American adoption of the English Bill of Rights of 1689.Footnote 176 Indeed, as late as the nineteenth century, the attachment to the common law traditions was vivid, as could be heard in Edmund Burke ’s Speech on Conciliation with America: the colonists were ‘not only devoted to liberty, but to liberty according to English ideas, and on English principles. Abstract liberty, like other abstractions, is not to be found […] Their love of liberty, as with you, [is] fixed and attached on this specific point of taxation .’Footnote 177

Following the Boston Tea Party and the adoption of the Intolerable Acts, delegates gathered on 5 September 1774, at Philadelphia, in what was to become the First Continental Congress . Every colony but Georgia was represented. They voted on the next day to appoint a committee ‘to state the rights of the Colonies in general, the several instances in which these rights are violated or infringed, and the means most proper to be pursued for obtaining a restoration of them.’Footnote 178 This led to the proposal of Joseph Galloway , a prominent young Pennsylvanian lawyer.Footnote 179 Galloway ’s Plan of Union was a conservative attempt to unite the colonies within the Empire. In addition, it advocated the creation of an American colonial parliament to act in coordination with Westminster .Footnote 180 Though it achieved a not inconsiderable degree of support in the First Continental Congress , Galloway ’s Plan of Union was opposed by the more radical delegates in the Congress. Consequently, it was introduced to the Congress on 28 September 1774, with the latter formally declining to adopt the plan, six votes to five, on 22 or (sometimes reported) 27 October. With Galloway ’s proposal rejected, the delegates instead adopted the Declaration of Colonial Rights ,Footnote 181 based on Sullivan’s draft . This draft, formulated in the manner of common law ,Footnote 182 began by listing Westminster ’s unconstitutional acts; the three statutes of 1774Footnote 183 were denounced as ‘impolitic, unjust, and cruel, as well as unconstitutional, and most dangerous and destructive of American rights.’Footnote 184 Against ‘these arbitrary proceedings of Parliament and administration’, as the Sullivan Draft put it:

[t]he good people of the several colonies […] justly alarmed at these arbitrary proceedings of Parliament and administration, have severally elected, constituted, and appointed deputies to meet and sit in General Congress, in the city of Philadelphia, in order to obtain such establishment, as that their religion, laws, and liberties may not be subverted.Footnote 185

The Sullivan Draft continued with the justification of the colonists’ rights as the customary rights of Englishmen. As with those of Englishmen still on the Home Islands, these rights emanated from the ‘very earliest times’ of their ancestors:

Whereupon the deputies so appointed being now assembled, in a full and free representation of these colonies, taking into their most serious consideration, the best means of attaining the ends aforesaid, do, in the first place, as Englishmen, their ancestors in like cases have usually done, for asserting and vindicating their rights and liberties, declare, That the inhabitants of the English Colonies in North America, by the immutable laws of nature, the principles of the English constitution , and the several charters or compacts, have the following rights.Footnote 186

What followed was the explicit enumeration of these rights; these were related to ‘the rights, liberties, and immunities of free and natural-born subjects, within the realm of England.’Footnote 187 Finally, the draft concluded with reference to the immutability and irreversibility of the rights and liberties, ‘which cannot be legally taken from them, altered or abridged by any power whatever, without their own consent, by their representatives in their several provincial legislatures.’Footnote 188 The ending also reinforced the ‘Americans as fellow-subjects in Great Britain’, and framed the preceding text not as a revolutionary document, but rather a vehicle ‘to restore harmony between Great Britain and the American colonies .’Footnote 189

As long as the American colonists deemed themselves common subjects of the same king, and argued on the customary level of their old rights as Englishmen, there could not be the idea of the precedence of a written constitutional text . All questions of precedence were mere questions of the applicability of ordinary law . In the case of collision of colonial ‘laws , by-laws, usages and customs’ with English law, Blackstone held them to be ‘utterly void and of no effect.’Footnote 190 Only in 1776 did the Americans ‘substitute’ their old rights as Englishmen with ‘natural freedoms.’ Taking the plunge and reorienting the American conception of the law according to natural law reasoning instead of the immortal customs of common law appeared to be constitutional ‘pragmatism.’Footnote 191 In doing so, they declared independence and were no longer common subjects of the same king. Therefore, any invocation of their customary rights as Englishmen had been voided.

4 Establishing Constitution as Law

4.1 Emergence of the Constituent American People

4.1.1 Natural Law ‘Basis and Foundation of Government’

It was the Virginia Bill of Rights Footnote 192 that constituted the decisive move away from the colonists’ justifications on the grounds of traditional common law liberties. In this document, no reference at all was made to the customary rights and liberties of the colonists as Englishmen. The legitimising authority was not ‘custom’ but ‘nature’, the blueprint being the law of nature according to Locke , and the concept ‘[t]hat all men are by nature equally free and independent and have certain inherent rights, of which, when they enter into a state of society, they cannot, by any compact, deprive or divest their posterity; namely, the enjoyment of life and liberty, with the means of acquiring and possessing property, and pursuing and obtaining happiness and safety.’ Written by George Mason , and adopted by the Fifth Virginia Convention on 12 June 1776, the claimed generality as ‘the basis and foundation of government’ marked the Virginia Bill of Rights as a revolutionary caesura.Footnote 193 The first formulation of popular sovereignty can be found in Section 2: ‘That all power is vested in, and consequently derived from, the people; that magistrates are their trustees and servants and at all times amenable to them.’ The later constitutional framework of the United States Constitution (1787) is already evident here in the provision on the governmentFootnote 194 and the separation between the legislature and the executive.Footnote 195 Section 7 recalls the supremacy of legislation: ‘That all power of suspending laws, or the execution of laws, by any authority, without consent of the representatives of the people, is injurious to their rights and ought not to be exercised.’Footnote 196 Section 15 makes references to fundamental principles of higher-ranking authority, but does not yet recognise the precedence of the written constitution: ‘That no free government, or the blessings of liberty, can be preserved to any people but by a firm adherence to justice, moderation, temperance, frugality, and virtue and by frequent recurrence to fundamental principles.’Footnote 197 Nevertheless, the Virginia Bill of Rights was regarded at the level of ordinary legislation, not vested with any superior rank, and still analogous to common law . Later declarations of rights after the break with England included a series of rights in accordance with natural law preambles. These rights had previously been enjoyed by the Americans as rights of Englishman and codified law which has already existed; now, however, they had been elevated to the new level of superior constitutions.Footnote 198

4.1.2 Independence from Being Subjects of the ‘Same’ King

In his essay entitled ‘The Irrelevance of the Declaration,’ the New York historian John Phillip Reid argued that the important part of the Declaration was not its preamble , but rather the charges it levelled against George III.Footnote 199 He was right to do so. In summer 1775, John Dickinson ’s Olive Branch Petition addressed a catalogue of colonists’ complaints to Westminster ; its failure to elicit positive action encouraged the Americans to seriously consider the role of the king as a nonpartisan patriot monarch of his whole people. This, naturally, must have included the Americans themselves, as George III’s common, English subjects. Yet, as it became increasingly obvious in 1775–6 that the king was not willing to intervene in favour of the colonists against Westminster ’s self-understanding as a superior legislative power , the colonists resorted to formulating a new course of political action that included both independence from Britain and the creation of ‘an AMERICAN COMMONWEALTH.’ On their way to declaring themselves independent the American colonists made it clear that they were about to terminate the submission under British statehood as ‘common subjects of the same King.’Footnote 200

From the point of view of the Americans , Parliament had no say in the relations between Britain and the colonies; according to the Chief Justice of the Rhode Island Supreme Court, Stephen Hopkins , it was ‘absurd to suppose that the common people of Great Britain have a sovereign and absolute authority over their fellow subjects in America, or [indeed] any sort of power whatsoever over them.’Footnote 201 When George III refused his arbitration role requested by the colonies, he assumed in their view full responsibility for the injustices suffered by the colonies. This responsibility was subsequently established in the initial wording of the Declaration of Independence of 4 July 1776:

Such has been the patient sufferance of these Colonies; and such is now the necessity which constrains them to alter their former Systems of Government. The history of the present King of Great Britain is a history of repeated injuries and usurpations, all having in direct object the establishment of an absolute Tyranny over these States. To prove this, let Facts be submitted to a candid world.Footnote 202

A close reading of the Declaration immediately reminds the reader of the structure of the English Bill of Rights of 1689. This began with an enumeration of all the infringements of James II against the ‘lawes and liberties of this Kingdome.’Footnote 203

After the list of all these justifications for the revolution the Declaration states:

Nor have We been wanting in attentions to our British brethren. We have warned them from time to time of attempts by their legislature to extend an unwarrantable jurisdiction over us. We have reminded them of the circumstances of our emigration and settlement here. We have appealed to their native justice and magnanimity, and we have conjured them by the ties of our common kindred [sic!] to disavow these usurpations, which, would inevitably interrupt our connections and correspondence.

Even at this seemingly terminal point in Anglo-American relations, the Declaration of Independence still highlighted their discursive commonalities. Nonetheless, the ‘British brethren’ left their common, transatlantic kin no other choice, but to declare themselves independent, as ‘[t]hey […] have been deaf to the voice of justice and of consanguinity.’ By addressing ‘necessity’ the American colonies claimed their right of resistance as a measure of self-defence, just as Parliament itself has done standing against the Stuart king, Charles I , when it issued the Militia Ordinance of 1642.Footnote 204 The Declaration concluded its justifications by stating that ‘[w]e must, therefore, acquiesce in the necessity, which denounces our Separation, and hold them, as we hold the rest of mankind, Enemies in War, in Peace Friends.’Footnote 205 The connection with the decision for war and peace in the ending wording makes the range of this recourse to ‘necessity’ obvious. The central issue was the question of sovereignty: who had the final say when it really mattered.Footnote 206

4.1.3 Constitutional American People of the United Colonies (1776–8)

The Declaration of Independence invoked a united American people , one singular constitutional population, distinct from the British colonial power: ‘When […] it becomes necessary for one people to dissolve the political bands which have connected them with another.’Footnote 207 The redress of the initial wording to ‘the separate and equal station to which the Laws of Nature and of Nature’s God entitle them,’ thereby alluding to the old phrase from Bracton (‘under God and the law’) increases the appearance of unity. In spite of this, the American people did not enter the stage of history homogenously, in the form of a unitarian state, but rather as a federal union of thirteen individual states. Moreover, though the unanimity of the Declaration suggested unity, the Declaration itself included the seemingly irreconcilable concept that ‘these United Colonies […] ought to be Free and Independent States […] And that as Free and Independent states, they have full power to levy War, conclude Peace, contract Alliances, establish Commerce, and do all other Acts and Things which Independent States may of right do.’Footnote 208

This fundamental contradiction of 1776, in which (supposedly) one people was divided amongst and represented by thirteen autonomous states, was determinative for the history of the United States, as almost all discussions on the rights of the individual states vis-à-vis the central government—for instance, the various States’ Rights debates, the Jacksonian Nullification Crisis of 1832–7, and the secession of the Confederate states in 1860–1Footnote 209—may be traced back to it. Indeed, common political discourse customarily referred to the United States in the plural (‘the United States are’), with the modern singular usage (‘the United States is’) only entering general usage after the end of the Civil War in 1865.Footnote 210 Furthermore, South Carolina’s Declaration of Secession (24 December 1860), which was one of the direct casus belli of the Civil War, explicitly justified the separation from the Union by invoking the Declaration of Independence and the Articles of Confederation:

In pursuance of this Declaration of Independence [1776], each of the thirteen States proceeded to exercise its separate sovereignty; adopted for itself a Constitution, and appointed officers for the administration of government in all its departments – Legislative, Executive and Judicial. For purposes of defense, they united their arms and their counsels; and, in 1777, they entered into a League known as the Articles of Confederation, whereby they agreed to entrust the administration of their external relations to a common agent, known as the Congress of the United States, expressly declaring in the first article, that each State retains its sovereignty, freedom and independence, and every power, jurisdiction and right which is not, by this Confederation, expressly delegated to the United States in Congress assembled.Footnote 211

South Carolina’s justification for secession was that it had never surrendered the sovereignty it had won as an independent state in 1776, neither to the Continental Congress under the Articles, nor to the Union under the 1787 Constitution . With the explicit reference to the Treaty of Paris of September 1783, which brought the War of Independence to a close, and the acknowledgement of the individually-named ‘United States’ by the ‘Britannic Majesty’, this single-state legal focus position was even more underlined and emphasised. In the line of the South Carolinian arguments for the separation from the United States lay also the recourse to the ‘two great principles asserted by the Colonies, namely: the right of a State to govern itself; and the right of a people to abolish a Government when it becomes destructive of the ends for which it was instituted.’Footnote 212 Undisputable was the final conclusion of the secessionist state, ‘that each Colony became and was recognized by the mother Country as a free, sovereign and independent State.’Footnote 213

This nineteenth-century reasoning reflects the debates at the end of the Stamp Act crisis, revolving around the legitimacy and desirability of a federal union or an incorporating union. For a Barbadian pamphleteer, ‘Our Governments […] are founded on similar Principles’,Footnote 214 and in March 1766 an anonymous writer in the Pennsylvania Journal proposed ‘a confederacy of states, independent of each other, yet united under one head’, concluding that ‘all the powers of legislation may subsist full and complete in each part, and their respective legislatures be absolutely independent of each other.’Footnote 215 The struggle of the ‘Colonies [to be] coordinate members with each other and with Great Britain, of an empire united by a common executive sovereign, but not united by any common legislative sovereign’ was the driving force behind the American Revolution , more so than any other claim or grievance, as James Madison later observed.Footnote 216 The necessity of a federative union was highlighted by the Declaration of Independence , since only a united action in the war against Great Britain seemed likely to bring success to the colonies. But separation from Britain by no means resolved this ancient question. To the contrary, it made it even more challenging by complementing it with the equally vexing problem of how to forge a viable political and constitutional union out of thirteen distinct polities that had previously been tied together only by their common relationship to the British Empire through the emerging imperial constitution .Footnote 217 Therefore the Articles of Confederation and perpetual Union between the States of New Hampshire, Massachusetts Bay, Rhode Island and Providence Plantations, Connecticut, New York, New Jersey, Pennsylvania, Delaware, Maryland, Virginia, North Carolina, South Carolina and Georgia were only adopted on 15 November 1777 after long discussions,Footnote 218 though any incorporating union (such as the example of England and Scotland since 1707) was out of question. The first two articles stipulated that ‘[t]he style of this confederacy shall be “The United States of America.”’, and ‘[e]ach state retains its sovereignty, freedom and independence […] which is not expressly delegated to the United States in Congress assembled.’Footnote 219 The longest of all the provisions, Article IX, amounted to half of the text of the Articles of Confederation. It regulated that ‘the united states in congress assembled, shall have the sole and exclusive right and power of determining on peace and war […] of sending and receiving ambassadors—entering into treaties and alliances […] The united states in congress assembled shall never engage in a war […] nor enter into any treaties or alliances […] unless nine states assent to the same.’

All decisions of importance and relevance had to be made by nine out of thirteen states, which amounted to a necessary majority of seventy percent of the individual states represented in Congress. Ten years later, the majority in the debates of the federative United States Constitution of 30 July till 1 August 1787, borrowing from the historical examples of the Netherlands, the Swiss Confederation, and the Holy Roman Empire, pointed out that not individuals but individual states were represented in Congress,Footnote 220 which was to be done equally and with the need of unanimity for general and fundamental matters.Footnote 221 This proves that winning independence in 1783, though effectively securing the original goal of the revolutionaries to gain local control over local affairs, left the question of how to bring the individual states into an ‘effective union.’ The state organisational issue to distribute authority between the centre and the peripheries was the primary concern of the American constitutional discourse during the 1780s and particularly during the national debate over the establishment of a new federal union 1787–8. Indeed, it might have been the driving force behind the recovering of the constitution as one legal written document at the core of a polity, defining its government’s powers and responsibilities and the limits on those powers and specifying the rights of the people. In examining the United States Constitution of 1787, its focus on sovereignty issues between the Union and single states and its understanding as supreme legal codex for the existence of the union (and therefore nation) becomes readily apparent .

4.2 Constitution as Supreme Legal Codex for Central State Issues

4.2.1 Focus on the Division of Sovereignty Between Union and Single States

The United States Constitution was meant to be a ground-breaking document. Given this, its preamble , beginning with the phraseology ‘[w]e the people of America do hereby declare’, seems uncharacteristically cautious. There is no other explicit reference to the sovereignty question within the preamble . This is perhaps because of the perceived experimental character of the Constitution itself, and its aim to establish an expansive federal republic by majority decision. The architects of the Constitution were well aware of this character. In his Federalist Paper No. 85, Alexander Hamilton invoked the words the Scottish Enlightenment philosopher David Hume , in order to point out that ‘[t]o balance a large state or society […] on general laws, is a work of so great difficulty [that] time must bring it to perfection, and the feeling of inconveniences must correct the mistakes which they INEVITABLY fall into in their first trials and experiments.’Footnote 222

The delineation of competencies between the Union and the States (Art. 1, sec. 8, 9, 10) is, along with the separation of powers (Art. I, sec. 1 and Art. 2, sec. 1)Footnote 223 the leading constitutional theme in the organisation of the United States. The address to an internal and external defensive sovereigntyFootnote 224 is not necessary. The Constitution articulated the rights of the Congress in legislation (Art. I, sec. 8)—the classical rights of sovereignty—and reduced correspondingly the rights of the union states, thus demonstrating the focus on the division of sovereignty between union and union states. It designed a federal state with a strong centralised power. With the American founding fathers having Blackstone ’s Commentaries as a model, the image of the President as surrogate monarch was already on the table, and elucidated in Art. 2, sec. 1’s provision that ‘the executive power shall be vested in a President.’Footnote 225 Legislation (Art. I sec. 1, 8) and budgetary sovereignty (Art. I, sec. 7) were subject to the two chambers of Congress: the House of Representatives, being the elected representatives of the people (Art. I, sec. 2), and the Senate, being the representatives of the individual states (Art. I, sec. 3). The bicameral system was created to enable compromises between the interests of the big states and the small ones. In the House of Representatives, every state was to have representatives according to its size (Art. I, sec. 2); in the Senate, according to the principle of equality of the states, every state was to have two senators (Art. I, sec. 3).

4.2.2 The Constitution as Guarantee for the Existence of the Union

According to the Federalists, such as Hamilton , Madison , and John Jay, the supremacy of the constitution was self-evident, because it was the benchmark for the action of all political powers. In the constitution, not only a political order that is able to protect freedom and property is manifested, but it is also the only system that can guarantee the existence of the nation . According to Federalist Paper No. 84, written by Hamilton (writing under the pseudonym ‘Publius’, meaning ‘of the people’), ‘[t]he great bulk of the citizens of America are with reason convinced, that Union is the basis of their political happiness.’Footnote 226 This conviction arose because this ‘great bulk of the citizens’ was represented by ‘a national government’ (No. 85).Footnote 227 As for his rhetorical question ‘whether […] the proposed Constitution has not been satisfactorily vindicated from the aspersions thrown upon it; and whether it has not been shown to be worthy of the public approbation, and necessary to the public safety and prosperity’, Hamilton explained that a decision upon the constitution was a decision upon the ‘very existence of the nation .’Footnote 228 His explanations that the consent to the constitution should be governed by ‘[n]o partial motive, no particular interest, no pride of opinion, no temporary passion or prejudice,’Footnote 229 with the decisive aspect being ‘not a particular interest of the community, but the very existence of the nation’, marks the superiority of the general will approving the constitution over the consensus to a statute.

The opposition to the federal Constitution, which in 1787 fostered the development of hierarchical laws , has been extensively investigated by Gerald Stourzh, who likened it to the political thought of the nineteenth-century Austrian theorist Adolf J. Merkl.Footnote 230 As an example of this, Stourzh referred to the correspondence of an anonymous anti-Federalist farmer. In his sixth letter, the farmer (assumed to be the New Yorker Melancton Smith) wrote:

Of rights, some are natural and unalienable, of which even the people cannot deprive individuals: Some are constitutional or fundamental; these cannot be altered or abolished by the ordinary laws ; but the people, by express acts, may alter or abolish them. These, such as the trial by jury, the benefits of the writ of habeas corpus, &c., individuals claim under the solemn compacts of the people, as constitutions, or at least under laws so strengthened by long usage as not to be repealable by the ordinary legislature – and some are common or mere legal rights, that is, such as individuals claim under laws which the ordinary legislature may alter or abolish at pleasure.Footnote 231

From this anti-Federalist opposition against the precedence of constitution over the ordinary laws (both of the union and of the federated states), it becomes clear that the development of the supremacy of constitution in the American constitutional discourse also comprised the political issue of the state-organisational relationship between union and single federated states ; its preeminence was fostered by the equivalence of the existence of the Union and the coming-into-existence of the Constitution.

4.2.3 Constitutional Silence on Precedence

The supremacy of the Constitution as proclaimed in Art. VI clause 2 of the 1787 text was left without statement how to implement the precedence at either federal or single state level.Footnote 232 This seems to owe to the discussion leading from the 1760s, which saw judicial review as a contradiction of popular sovereignty ; according to the introductory preamble , it was this popular sovereignty that legitimated constitutional legislation .Footnote 233 This reluctance to affirm constitutional supremacy should also be understood by reference to the common law context of the American discourse. In the leading Bonham’s Case ,Footnote 234 known also in the colonies, Coke formulated the precedence of common law even over the laws of Parliament.Footnote 235 The willingness of the colonies to adhere to this reasoning was only bolstered during their struggles against Westminster legislation.

The counter-position of the sovereignty of Parliament Footnote 236 was about to cause much unease in the colonies. Contrary to Coke , Blackstone ’s Commentaries stipulated that, ‘[w]here the common law and a statute differ, the common law gives place to the statute.’Footnote 237 This established the precedence of the legislative over the judicial. But even before Blackstone ’s definition of parliamentary sovereignty was able to gain a foothold in the colonies, the American discourse had already adopted the position that there must be limitations to Westminster ’s jurisdiction.

With this we return to the justification of the American Revolution as an act of resistance against the unconstitutional action of the English Parliament. It is true that the elected colonial representative bodies did not expressly confess to the invalidity of unpopular parliamentary laws in the protest against the motherland,Footnote 238 but popular sovereignty took parliamentary sovereignty off the table. The idea of popular sovereignty was formulated by the Committee of Correspondence of the city of Boston for the first time in 1772, which quickly spread to the other colonies.Footnote 239 With the Virginia Bill of Rights of 1776, the dam broke.Footnote 240

Nonetheless, the 1787 Constitution remained cautious in its implementation of popular sovereignty , in contrast to the celebratory rhetoric of its preamble . Regardless the importance of the Virginia Bill of Rights eleven years earlier, by 1787 conservative reservations against the people as the sovereign power were still insurmountable. In the Philadelphia Constitutional Convention , the conviction that unlimited popular sovereignty could actually endanger the Constitution still prevailed.Footnote 241 The exclusion of direct popular involvement in the constitutional amendment process, and the introduction of the bicameral system went in the same direction.Footnote 242 Art. V of the 1787 Constitution clearly demonstrates the distrust of direct popular involvement in this amendment process:

The Congress, whenever two thirds of both Houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose Amendments to this Constitution, or, on the Application of the Legislatures of two thirds of the several States, shall call a Convention for proposing Amendments , which, in either Case, shall be valid to all Intents and Purposes, as Part of this Constitution, when ratified by the Legislatures of three fourths of the several States, or by Conventions in three fourths thereof, as the one or the other Mode of Ratification may be proposed by the Congress; Provided that no Amendment which may be made prior to the Year One thousand eight hundred and eight shall in any Manner affect the first and fourth Clauses in the Ninth Section of the first Article; and that no State, without its Consent, shall be deprived of its equal Suffrage in the Senate.Footnote 243

Furthermore, the 1787 text contained no declaration of human rights. It was only in 1791 that the Bill of Rights became part of the Constitution due to conditions set out during the debates of ratification in the individual states (Amendments). They lay down a catalogue of individual rights, including those of freedom of religion , speech , and assembly , as well as the inviolability of the person and property . In America—the New World—class differentiations were a memory of the old continent. For that reason, the idea of equality was not as much emphasised as in the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen , while the American guarantees of freedom of assembly and the right of petition (Article 1 of the Amendments) have no equivalent in the French Declaration. At this point the beginning of a tradition becomes noticeable, through which the United States fostered a unique self-characterisation that differentiated it from its European forebears. This continued after independence and was strongly emphasised in the First Amendment of the United States Constitution 15 December 1791: The federal legislature was prohibited from passing resolutions concerning the creation of a state religion or the prohibition of the free practice of religion. This prohibition for the federal legislature also includes the restriction of the freedom of speech and press , as well as the freedom of assembly and the right to petition .Footnote 244

Constitutional jurisdiction , which was crucial for the precedence of constitution , was not included into the 1787 text, as there was no majority in the Convention for so strong a constitutional jurisdiction.Footnote 245 Nevertheless, the need for an authoritative final judge in disputes between the centre and the periphery—disputes that had been unsolvable in the years between 1765 and 1776—contributed to the American development of a judicial review and to the revision of Locke ’s concept of there being no competent earthly judge between the legislature and the population.

4.3 Farewell to the Lockean ‘Inter legislatorem et populum nullus in terris est judex’

According to his letter about tolerance (‘Epistola de tolerantia’, 1689), for John Locke there was no judge on earth between the legislation and the people. This role could only be occupied by God, and it was God who personified the figure of judgemental resistance against executive or legislative excess.Footnote 246 With the separation of legislation and constitution , or the distinction between superior constitutional law and ordinary statutory law , the Americans entertained the possibility of having a secular judge between the legislation and the people. This would take the form of judges who were authorised to measure the statutory law against the ‘higher’ will of the American people , as embodied by the constitution. The higher legitimation by the constituent general will was explained by Hamilton in his Federalist Paper No. 85.

This process indeed commenced during the 1780s in some of the federal states of America, especially in the state of North Carolina. By the competence for ordinary jurisdiction to measure the statutory law against the ‘higher’ will of the people , in other words the constitution, the feudal right of resistance , as it is assumed by Locke —where God as judge means resistance—was replaced by the (constitutional) courts .Footnote 247 The federal jurisdiction adopted this opinion; as a result, it was applied to the famous legal case of Marbury v. Madison (1803), which is considered to be the foundation of the ‘judicial review ’—the prerogative of the judges to examine constitutionality or unconstitutionality. Marbury v. Madison held praeter legem that ‘[i]t is emphatically the duty of the Judicial Department to say what the law is. Those who apply the rule to particular cases must, of necessity, expound and interpret the rule’, and that the Constitution was the superior measurement for ordinary statutes (‘If two laws conflict with each other, the Court must decide on the operation of each. If courts are to regard the Constitution, and the Constitution is superior to any ordinary act of the legislature, the Constitution, and not such ordinary act, must govern the case to which they both apply’). However, it is crucial to analyse the context of this decision. That context is provided by Hamilton ’s plea for the introduction of a judicial review , made fifteen years earlier.

The interpretative authority of jurisdiction and the fundamental character of the Constitution were the starting points for the argumentation set forth in The Federalist No. 78. According to Hamilton :

The interpretation of the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts. A constitution is, in fact, and must be regarded by the judges, as a fundamental law . It therefore belongs to them to ascertain its meaning, as well as the meaning of any particular act proceeding from the legislative body. If there should happen to be an irreconcilable variance between the two, that which has the superior obligation and validity ought, of course, to be preferred; or, in other words, the Constitution ought to be preferred to the statute, the intention of the people to the intention of their agents.Footnote 248

James R. Stoner arguesFootnote 249 that Hamilton ’s plea for the judicial review relied on common law reasoning, irrespective the latter’s super-elevation of Parliament’s wisdom (also: ultimum sapientiae)Footnote 250 not to enact any statute ‘against the truth’ due to the knowledge of the represented subjects of the whole realm.Footnote 251 Hamilton overcame this well-known line of precedence against judicial review , also attached to Bonham’s case ,Footnote 252 by asserting that a written constitution is a law and therefore examining the violation of constitution by statute is to be held analogous to the clash of two statutes. If two statutes on the level of the same legislative authority were incompatible, it is ‘the nature and reason of thing’Footnote 253 that decides for the preference of the more recent . A minore ad maius the analogy leads to preference for a constitutional provision over a conflicting statute, as ‘the nature and reason of thing’ says so a fortiori, if the legal provisions of a superior authority were at risk of being infringed. Hamilton ’s statement of the different legal quality of a constitution relied on his assessment of the uniqueness of the constituent power , which he expressed in The Federalist No. 83,Footnote 254 and his tolerance towards implicit, unwritten powers, as argued in The Federalist No. 33.Footnote 255 Irrespective of the lack of express constitutional competences to enforce the goals and limits of a written constitution, such a judicial power of ‘mitigating the severity and confining the operation of [unjust and partial] laws,’Footnote 256 was inferred from the Constitution.Footnote 257 Anti-Federalist critics, writing under the pseudonym ‘Brutus’, condemned the idea of judicial review , on the grounds of unelected judges having the competence to review and nullify acts of elected legislative representatives.Footnote 258 In response,Footnote 259 Hamilton argued that ‘in voiding unconstitutional acts the courts serve as the people’s champion.’Footnote 260

This defence of judicial review in No. 78 can only be understood in the common law context of artificial reason, which was established as the seventeenth-century basis for supremacy of law under the auspices of the oft-quoted Sir Edward Coke . The conception of ‘artificial reason’, elucidated in the seventeenth-century precedent Prohibitions des Roy,Footnote 261 was established as being superior to the ‘natural reason’ of the monarch; this was transformed in the Federalists’ discourse into the ‘solemn and authoritative’ reason of a constituent assembly fully aware of the ‘Decisive Constitutional Normativity ’ and its necessity to prevail over the ‘momentary inclination’ of the people represented by legislature.Footnote 262 To continue this argument, it is the spirit (or, rather, reason) of the common law that no particular legislative act nor any specific legal ruling has the final word on what is just,Footnote 263 but only the ‘collective mind of the profession’ which adopted the mantle of authority customarily represented by popular consent .Footnote 264

It was in this manner that seventeenth-century common law was the bulwark against Stuart absolutism ;Footnote 265 artificial reason replaced general custom , more as an interpretative authorityFootnote 266 rather than as legislative consensus.Footnote 267 With this as the common law basis of Hamilton ’s argumentation, it is not difficult to follow Publius (Hamilton ) in assessing the judges as ‘the bulwarks of a limited Constitution’Footnote 268 and ‘faithful guardians of the Constitution,’Footnote 269 the people as its ‘natural Guardians,’Footnote 270 and ‘the general spirit of the people and of the government’Footnote 271 as ‘the only solid basis of all our rights.’Footnote 272

5 Summary of Sections 3 and 4

For all that the American Revolution and the subsequent United States Constitution were, indeed, revolutionary, this does not mean that either was unprecedented or unheralded. On the contrary: at every step in the struggle, first with Britain and then amongst themselves, the minds fashioning the American future continually referred back to the concepts of law and legitimacy. Unsurprisingly, these concepts had their origins in the Old World of Europe, as befitting a new society consecrated upon the foundations of the old. The push for independence was not solely a military endeavour but also a legal one, as the leading figures of the Revolution referred to the guiding lights of English common law —William Blackstone and Edward Coke —in order to demonstrate that it was, in fact, England that had forsaken English law, by denying loyal English subjects (as the American colonists, until the very end, argued themselves to be) their rights as Englishmen. This included the right of representation (which could not conceivably be achieved through the institution of the Westminster Parliament) and the right not to be taxed without this aforementioned representation. In part, this explains the ultimate appeal of rebellion: to the Americans, it was not they who were breaking the law by revolting against Britain, but in fact the British who were acting illegally by denying fundamental rights under common law . To the Americans, they were the ‘better Englishmen’ than the English.

Having established this legitimacy of revolution, the Americans were next faced with the challenge of legitimising their own governance. This they accomplished again with reference to European precedent, adapted to their own needs. King George III was replaced by his secular stand-in, President George Washington . However, to avoid the very pitfalls that had catalysed the Revolution in the first place, the Founding Fathers aimed to delineate clear responsibilities and powers through the use of an explicit, written law of higher character than ordinary law . The resultant United States Constitutional system, enhanced by the federal precedent Marbury v. Madison (1803), insisted upon formalised mechanisms, such as judicial review to protect constitutionally-granted rights and liberties, thus introducing not only a founding body of law but also the means by which that body of law gained normative precedence. Once again, such a development in some ways jettisoned existing European ideas (such as the Lockean model of God-as-resistance), while adapting others, such as Coke ’s superiority of ‘artificial reason’ over ‘natural reason.’ Ultimately, networks and connections across the Atlantic amounted to a hoard remaking traditional understandings of constitutionalism.Footnote 273 Regardless its substance, by the early nineteenth century, the United States Constitution was established as the normative, precedential body of law in the fledgling United States of America. Having been influenced by Europe, America was, through this development, able to turn the tables, and itself influence the Old World, while Europe itself went through a major period of transition.

6 Legal Transition of Philosophical Truths

The American Revolution had brought about a Novus Ordo Seclorum on one side of the Atlantic. Continental Europe’s ‘new order of ages’, which would establish both normativity and precedence , roughly coincided with the same period. The starting point for this new order, though, was totally different from that of the American colonies , as were many of the assumptions and processes that would shape it.

In 1827, the German poet and playwright Johann Wolfgang von Goethe lyricised the existence of America in his poem Den Vereinigten Staaten (To the United States):

America, you are better off than

Our continent, the old.

You have no castles which are fallen,

No basalt to behold.

You’re not disturbed within your innermost being,

Right up till today’s life

By useless remembering

And unrewarding strife.Footnote 274

Goethe ’s verse is, however, less praise of the United States, so much as a lament of Europe’s ‘historical baggage’—the ‘fallen castles’ and perpetual ‘strife’ that would colour any radical shift to a new era. Goethe himself had been a witness to this roughly three decades earlier, as the newly-minted French Republic began its own constitutional experiment, similar yet distinct to that begun by Washington , Madison , Hamilton , and the American constitutionalists.

The critical, formative years of this experiment were between the Years III and VIII (1794/5-9/1800); this period marked the interval between the establishment of the Directorate and its apotheosis into Bonaparte’s single rule.Footnote 275 The National Convention (Convention nationale = la Convention),Footnote 276 as the first French assembly elected by a suffrage without class distinctions, set forth the draft of the radical democratic ‘Jacobin ’ or ‘Mountain’ Constitution of the Year I ( Acte constitutionnel du 24 juin 1793 ),Footnote 277 which planned to wipe out the monarchy. In the following eight months (from autumn 1793 to spring 1794) these radical democratic ambitions were discredited by the Terror of the Committee of Public Safety ( comité de Salut public ) under the auspices of Maximilien de Robespierre Footnote 278 and his Jacobins . During the ThermidorianFootnote 279 constitutional debate, the majority of the members of the Convention (conventionnels) had no intention whatsoever to bring the Jacobin constitution of 1793 into force. With the beginning of the Parisian sans-culottes insurrection on 1 Prairial III (20 May 1795), which resulted in the storming of the Convention with the battle cry ‘bread and the constitution of 1793’, the willingness to promulgate the implementing laws (lois organiques) for the enforcement of the Mountain Constitution faded. It was only after Robespierre ’s fall that the National Convention could turn to the ‘commission of the eleven ’Footnote 280 to formulate a new constitution. The eleven commissioners proposed the Directory Constitution of the Year III (1795), which passed on 22 August 1795 (5 Fructidor of the Year III).Footnote 281 Its pillars were the return to the 1791 constitution, the affirmation of equality within the limits of civil equality, and the ruthless protection of the Republic against any legislative omnipotence or executive dictatorship. Similarly, protection was needed against the revolutionary subversive ghost of the faubourg Saint-Antoine,Footnote 282 bordering the Bastille. The bicameral legislature was composed of the Council of Five Hundred , with its right to legislative initiative, and of the Council of Ancients (sometimes referred to as the Council of Elders; Conseil des Anciens), whose 250 deputies accepted or rejected proposed bills. Crucially, the executive power in the hand of five directorsFootnote 283 was vested in an executive college as the Committee for Public Safety had been. Thus, even if concentration of executive power was to be avoided by the re-election of one of the directors each year within the five-year term, the Directory still retained great power. This included emergency powers to curb freedom of the press and freedom of association .

6.1 Sieyès’ Constitutional Jury (jury constituionnaire)

In this discursive context, the task of legally protecting the Revolution, from itself as well as outsiders, fell to Emmanuel Joseph Sieyès (1748–1836), the Roman Catholic abbot and political theorist whose 1789 pamphlet Qu’est-ce que le tiers-état? (What is the Third Estate?) had become the French Revolution ’s guiding manifesto. Sieyès proposed the introduction of a constitutional jury whose juridical-political competences comprised the adjudication of complaints, even by individuals, regarding constitutional infringements by constituted powers ,Footnote 284 reform and review of the Constitution itself every ten years. It also included, rather uniquely, an equitable jurisdiction as ‘court for human rights’Footnote 285 if asked by official judicial referral of ordinary courts . This supplementary constitutional equity was based on natural law (most likely reflecting the character of 1789 Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen ) and planned to be accessible if courts declared themselves unable to reach a decision in the absence of an applicable positive law or if they held the decision according to the legal text to be against their conscience.Footnote 286

Sieyès ’ proposal was put forward at a time when normativity and constitutional precedence were very hard to establish. During the Revolution, the constitution was primarily conceived as a mean to guarantee the organisation of the powers and their functions. As Michel Pertué has demonstrated, the Revolution ‘refused always to convey to any institution outside the legislative body the competence to verify and to guarantee the democratic process of the legislation and its conformity with the laws, the principles of the declaration of rights of man and citizen and with the constitution.’ The dominant légi-centrisme was, in Pertué’s reading, the Rousseauist understanding of law as the expression of the volonté générale , immunising the sovereign legislative assembly against the obligation to follow superior rules.Footnote 287 Unsurprisingly, then, Sieyès ’ draft was rejected unanimously, but the course of debates illustrates decisive milestones of the French constitutional ‘belief’ after 1789.Footnote 288

It goes without saying that, in the unpreceded constitutional debates in Revolutionary France, nominalist certainty or even autonomy of constitutional semantics was an illusion. Yet, as the ReConFort project with its functional approach has consistently demonstrated, there was and is a mutual interdependency between the artifice or constituent making of a constitution and the discourse of public opinion and understanding.Footnote 289 With this in mind, the debates in the National Convention on the 2 and 18 Thermidor Year III (20 July and 5 August 1795) are crucial not only for the understanding of French constitutional history. More expansively, they are vital for determining whether there is a common European core of normativity and precedence or whether modern European integration, though built since the grounding treaties as legal community, has ignored or not been fully aware of different national concepts of constitutional normativity and precedence .Footnote 290

In contrast to the American recourse to the feudal-medieval common law right to resistance and the British reasoning of supreme parliamentary wisdom, the French starting point of 1789 was completely different. Judges had been figures of privilege within the Ancien Régime , which made them most suspicious for the revolutionaries. At the same time, they enthusiastically adopted the dogmatic concept of the supreme general will by Jean-Jacques Rousseau . In conflating the two the revolutionaries ‘invented’ the French aversion to having the acts of sovereign legislative assemblies controlled by judges.Footnote 291 This suspicion continues today; modern French constitutional discourse does not speak of judiciary power (pouvoir), but of judiciary authority (authorité). Freedom by (fraternal-political) equality (liberté, egalité, fraternité), according to their condensation in Art. 6 Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen , had the consequence that the veritable counter-power remained with the French people (Art. 2 and 14 Declaration), represented a priori in the constituent assembly and thus entrusting the constituted legislative assembly with supreme legitimisation.

As the preeminent theorist of the national constituent sovereignty of the nation ,Footnote 292 and as a major contributor to the September Constitution (1791), Sieyès had gone into hiding during the Terror, before he reentered the political stage in the national convention after 9 Thermidor II (27 July 1794) with his intention, stronger as with other thermidoriens, to ‘finish the revolution.’Footnote 293 In this pragmatic constitutional thinking the constitution was the legal mean to reach this goal. Therefore the draft of a constitutional jury of the 18 Thermidor IIIFootnote 294 was meant as part of the legal instruments to end the Revolutionary Terror.Footnote 295 When the work of the ‘commission of the eleven ’ had nearly finished, Sieyès , who was not one of the eleven, presented his draft on the constitutional jury in the constitutional debates of 2 and 18 Thermidor III (20 July and 5 August 1795).

By his concept of national sovereignty , Sieyès had been the first to differentiate the constituent power from the constituted power , in order to explain the decisive process of juridification of sovereignty.Footnote 296 Concluding from his paradigms that the will of the nation itself is always lawful and that it is the law in itself, Sieyès established the inviolability of the constitution against the (constituted) legislative body. The exclusion of any absolutistic political power on the basis of the immanent differentiation of ordinary legislative bodies from constituent assemblies led to a ‘superlegality of the constitution’ (superlégalité de la constitution).Footnote 297 If the legislative power could not ‘without contradiction and absurdity touch the constitution’ (‘sans contradiction et sans absurdité toucher à la Constitution’), as Sieyès wrote in his report of the third estate (Compte rendu de Qu’est-ce que le tiers état?),Footnote 298 this necessarily implied the existence of a control institution.

Though he was a moderate Jacobin of the Girondin faction, for which he was persecuted during Robespierre ’s Mountain-led Terror, at no point did Sieyès consider accommodation with monarchists of any stripe. He dismissed attempts by the Friends of the Monarchist Constitution (Les amis de la Constitution Monarchique) to reconcile pre-constitutional monarchical prerogative with the Revolution’s stated principle of the rights of man and the sovereign nation , and insisted on the a priori undivided sovereignty of nation which brought forth the constitutional monarchy as constituted power just as the ordinary legislative assembly.Footnote 299 This constitutional liberalism ,Footnote 300 built on the differentiation between constitution and ordinary legislation, left the door ajar for a guardian of the constitution, with the explicit function of declaring statutory law to be unconstitutional and the ability to overrule it, without this guardian being necessarily conceivable as judicial body. Taking into account the centrality of Rousseau ’s ‘general will’ in Revolutionary ideology, combined with the distrust against any ‘heirs’ of the noblesse de robe, Sieyès did not propose that his drafted constitutional jury would consist of professional judges, but of former members of the constituent assemblies, the legislative bodies, or the Convention .Footnote 301

6.1.1 Constitutional Debates of 2 and 18 Thermidor III (20 July and 5 August 1795)

Sieyès ’ prevailing motive in his interventions before the convention on 2 and 18 Thermidor III (20 July and 5 August 1795) was to reconcile constituent power —as he had established six years earlier in What is the Third Estate?—with a subordinate authority to control the constitutionality. The constitutional jury proposal followed the logic which began 1789 with the differentiation between the constituent and the constituted power .Footnote 302 On the 2 Thermidor III (20 July 1795) Sieyès presented his ideas on the government and the political constitution:

In regard to the government and the constitution, unity on its own means despotism, and division on its own means anarchy. Division with the unity gives social guarantee, without which liberty would be only precarious […] Divide, for hindrance of despotism; centralise for avoiding the anarchy […] I only know two systems of the division of powers: equilibrium and competition, or in nearly similar terms, the system of counter-powers and of organised unity.Footnote 303

In response to the Jacobin argument that the representative system was anti-democratic (expressed among others by Hérault de Séchelles and Maximilien de Robespierre ), Sieyès employed a celebrated, though prosaic, metaphor of the post. Denying representation would be the same as ‘to reserve the right to carry your letters yourself without trusting them to the public establishment [the post office] in charge of conveying them.’Footnote 304 He concluded by demanding the institution of a constitutional jury , a political organ more than a juridical one: ‘This is the real body of representatives which I demand, with a special mission to judge the reclamations against every infringement onto the constitution.’Footnote 305

In the discourse of 18 Thermidor III (5 August 1795), Sieyès explained the attributions and the organisation of the constitutional jury , organised according his draft in seventeen articlesFootnote 306 and charged with the control over the legislature about the respect of the constitution: ‘The necessity of a constitutional jury ’, Sieyès asserted in front of the National Convention ,

forms a sort of preliminary question; it does not suffer from difficulty. How in fact could the preview of the legislator accustom itself to the idea of an abandoned constitution, in the very moment of its coming-into-existence? A constitution is a body of obligatory laws or it does not exist; if it is body of laws, one asks oneself where is the guardian, where is the magistrate of this code.Footnote 307

The constitutional jury , or the ‘depository keeper of the constitutional act’/dépositaire conservateur de l’acte constitutionnel, as it was named by Sieyès in Art. I of his proposal, ‘is to be composed of 108 members, a third of them renewed every year, in the same period as the legislative body’ (Art. II).Footnote 308 ‘The first formation of the constitutional jury ’, the draft proposed, ‘is constituted by the convention by means of a secret ballot, in the manner that a third of its members is chosen among those of the constituent assembly [la Constituante], another third among the members of the legislative, and the last third among the members of the Convention [la Convention]’ (Art. IV).Footnote 309 It also stipulated that ‘the 36 newcomers each year are to be chosen by the jury itself among the 250 members who have to leave the one or the other of the two councils of the legislative bodies’ (Art. III),Footnote 310 ‘[t]he sessions of the constitutional jury will not be open to the public’ (Art. V),Footnote 311 and ‘the decisions of the constitutional jury will bear the name “decision” [arrêt].’ (Art. VII).Footnote 312

According to Sieyès ’ ‘opinion about the attributions and the organisation of the constitutional jury ’, the jury had three functions. The first competence was to safeguard the Constitution by functioning as a supreme tribunal for the constitutional order (tribunal de cassation dans l’ordre constitutionnel).Footnote 313 The second was to perfect the constitution by presenting projects of constitutional revision as an atelier de propositions pour les amendemens.Footnote 314 The third prerogative of the jury was the most inventive one: it was an equitable constitutional jurisdiction on the basis of natural law as supplement de juridiction naturelle, if judgements could not be issued by ordinary courts due to lacking or to unjust positive law .Footnote 315 None of these functions could be exercised on the jury’s initiative itself (Art. XVII).Footnote 316

6.1.1.1 ‘Jury de Cassation’

The first function of controlling constitutionality was very complex, due to the Rousseauist preference for supreme legislative legitimacy. The acts that fell under the jury’s control, according to Sieyès ’ plans, were the acts of the legislative councils (the Council of Five Hundred and the Council of Ancients ), unconstitutional acts regarding matters related to ballots, unconstitutional acts of the primary assemblies, and those of the court of cassation . Art. VIII of the Sieyès project provided for the annulment of unconstitutional legislative acts: ‘The acts declared as unconstitutional by the decision of the constitutional jury are null and void.’Footnote 317 In any case, the jury could never declare acts to be unconstitutional on its own initiative, but only if asked to do so by any applicant entitled according to Art. VI of the draft: ‘The constitutional jury will comment on the violations or the impairments of the Constitution, which will be denounced to them, against the acts, either by the council of ancients, or by the council of five hundred , or by the electoral assemblies, or by the primary assemblies, or by the tribunal of cassation .’Footnote 318 Any minority out of the said constitutional bodies and even individual citizen could bring such a denunciation forward.Footnote 319 The jury de cassation had the legal function of a supreme constitutional court , annulling acts contrary to the fundamental law .Footnote 320 It was the expression of a particular vision of the separation of powers ,Footnote 321 and assured ‘the permanent political relevance of a revolutionary impact finds itself beyond the year III.’Footnote 322

Sieyès ’ proposal to establish a constitutional jury contributed—beyond the control of the constitutionality of laws—in an original manner to a transition of the concept of a constitution as mechanism, as the simple distribution of powers, to a constitution as an obligatory rule, supreme above all the others .Footnote 323 The consequence of this ‘super-legality’Footnote 324 of the Constitution was the possibility to annul unconstitutional acts.Footnote 325 For Sieyès ’ contemporaries, though, Paul Bastid identifies ‘an incontestable confusion.’Footnote 326 Michel Troper has substantiated the probable source of this confusion, noting that the majority of acts addressed as ‘unconstitutional’ in section one of Art. VI of the project were neither laws nor necessarily legislative acts of the two branches of the legislative body under the Directorate, and therefore unconstitutionality is hard to imagine.Footnote 327 The conventionalists as a whole were averse to establishing a power of superior control of that of the legislative assemblies: ‘Due to their preference for the predominance of the law,’ writes Marcel Morabito, ‘the revolutionary exaltation of the representation remained incompatible with any idea of controlling the constitutionality.’Footnote 328 For them, the constitution of 1795 provided internal guarantee s to protect itself: firstly, by the separation between the councils and the executive power and, secondly, by the fact that the Council of the Ancients could exercise its own control of constitutionality; it could refuse its approval for the acts taken by the council of 500 due to the disrespect for the formes and proceedings previewed in the constitution (Art. 88 of the Directory Constitution 1795).Footnote 329

6.1.1.2 ‘Jury de Proposition’

The mastermind of French national sovereignty planned his constitutional jury not only to be the ‘guardian and defensor of the constitution’,Footnote 330 but attributed to the control organ the mandate to improve and perfect the Constitution and the Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen , responding to new developments and societal changes.Footnote 331 This was meant to restrain the Revolution and to control the a priori unlimited pouvoir constituant , represented in 1789 by the French nation, which Sieyès ’ pamphlet What is the Third Estate? declared ‘to be the supreme master of any positive law .’Footnote 332 The revision competence of the jury was a disciplinary restriction of the constituent power . In the words of Michel Pertué,Footnote 333 ‘the constituent power attributed to the nation in 1789 by Sieyès [as an] unconditioned and unlimited [one] became regulated and more and more restricted in the hands of the constitutional jury of the year III (1795), and afterwards in the hands of the college of conversators of the Consulate Constitution of the Year VIII (Constitution de l’an VIII/1799).’Footnote 334 The challenge to be tackled by the spiritus rector of the constituent sovereignty and its different uniqueness compared to the constituted sovereignty was to bring the constituent power under the legal regime of the normative constitution, without eliminating the differences to the constituted powers.Footnote 335 Whereas the latter act only according to the norms of the positive law , the domain of the constituent power is the natural law . To bridge this gap, Sieyès intended a periodical progressive amendment of the Constitution by the jury. The constituent power could then rest with the people, but as a regulated one. In the midst of the discourse of 18 Thermidor III (5 August 1795), which dealt with the rights of future generations, Sieyès claimed the unquestionable right of future generations to make their own constitutional amendments that ‘the authentic motives of a political constitution rest with the nation, and especially with the generation which has passed it.’ This singularity of the Constitution’s origins led, in Sieyès ’ words, to ‘the legal need to provide our constitution with the principle of unlimited perfection, which allows for concession to the needs of every epoch but never for any possibility of a total reproduction or destruction, neither an abandonment by hazard.’Footnote 336

As the constituent sovereignty rested with the people, the jury could not directly intervene for constitutional reforms; its role was only to make propositions. To avoid popular unrest and upheaval during a period of constitutional reform , the jury had to present every ten years a notebook of constitutional amendments to the legislative councils and primary assemblies (Art. XI, section 1 and 2).Footnote 337 The primary assemblies—reunited every year for the election of the people’s representatives—could speak themselves in favour of or against the possibility to delegate a temporary constituent power to the actual legislature (Art. XII, section 1).Footnote 338 ‘If the majority of the primary assemblies said no,’ the wording of the draft continued, ‘the notebook with amendments will be seen as void and its propositions cannot be reproduced before the following tenth year’ (Art. XII, section 2).Footnote 339 Art. XII makes it furthermore explicit that the Council of Ancients , if delegated, had no power to make changes to the jury’s propositions (section 3).Footnote 340 Art. XIII limits the sessions of the council of Ancients exercising constituent power on the primary assemblies’ mandate to twelve in total or to two in a decade (section 2).Footnote 341 ‘There will be, for the sessions of the constituent power , a separated written report, in a particular register, which will be, in the end, solemnly placed in the archives of the constitutional jury ’ (Art. XIII, section 3).Footnote 342 The particularity of the mandate with constituent power is highlighted in section 1 of the XIII, which declares ‘the sessions to be exclusively affected.’Footnote 343

6.1.1.3 ‘Jury of Natural Equity’

The third function of the jury was an equitable control—based in the natural law —of the judgements of the ordinary courts . Art. XIV section one of Sieyès ’ proposal provided that ‘every year, at least one-tenth of the members of the constitutional jury , to be taken randomly, will build a jury of natural equity.’Footnote 344 This function of an equitable court could only be exercised ‘on the official requests of different courts, for having a decision of natural equity in the case that the courts declare not having been able to judge, due to the absence of a positive law which can apply to that, or to being forced to judge only against their conscience, only according to the text of the law’ (Art. XIV, section 2).Footnote 345 These decisions of natural equity were to be enacted by the relevant tribunal that had made the request in the first place; the constitutional jury could also select other tribunals to enforce the decisions (Art. XV).Footnote 346 They ‘will be officially communicated, within one month, to the Council of Five Hundred ’ (Art. XVI).Footnote 347 In this way, Sieyès intended that the constitutional jury would function as a court of natural equity, if the ordinary courts identified or believed there to be loopholes or iniquities in positive law .

6.1.2 Communicative Implications of the Jury’s Attributions in the Thermidorian Constitutional Debates

6.1.2.1 ‘Jury de Cassation’

In regard to the communicative interdependencies of constitutional debates , Sieyès ’ idea to control the constitutionality of ordinary laws addressed the precedence of constitution . For this legal function of the constitutional jury he relied on jury members elected by citizens and having already sat in the legislative assemblies, in order to avoid any allusions to a formal court with professional judges. Like old wine in new skins, Sieyès referred back to the prerevolutionary parliamentary right of remonstrance in an attempt to convince his contemporaries of a long-standing French tradition of legally-restrained sovereignty. Literally borrowing from Montesquieu ’s praise of the French parlement in the Spirit of the Laws (II 4),Footnote 348 the jurors are said to fulfill their conservative function ‘with fidelity in the guard of the constitutional deposit’ (avec fidélité à la garde du dépôt constitutionnel).Footnote 349

The control of the constitutionality of laws was the attribute of Sieyès ’ planned jury that met with the most acceptance, especially as there were many other commutated proposals. As demonstrated by the research of Marco Fioravanti the Girondin Arman-Guy de KersaintFootnote 350 had already proposed a tribunal of censors to control the legislative and the executive in their accordance with the constitution.Footnote 351 Condorcet had discussed popular veto as a means of protecting the citizens against legislative arbitrariness,Footnote 352 which provided for the dissolution of the legislative assembly if the primary assemblies were against the legislative act.Footnote 353 Also, the debate on the Mountain Constitution witnessed proposals to control the constitutionality of legislative acts. Chapter XV of the project of the Mountain Constitution included provisions for a ‘national grand jury’, though this was rejected.Footnote 354 Nevertheless, Marie-Jean Hérault de Séchelles ,Footnote 355 the main redactor of the Constitutional Act of 1793 , positioned himself in favour of a protection against ‘oppression by the legislative body’,Footnote 356 and found himself in the company of Robespierre .Footnote 357 All these proposals, together with le Balancier politiqueFootnote 358 and the Articles proposés pour la réforme de la Constitution 1793,Footnote 359 accepted the superiority of a control organ not democratically legitimised and seemed to have prepared the path for the legal attribution of cassation of unconstitutional acts in Sieyès ’ drafted jury.

6.1.2.2 ‘Jury de Proposition’

For the revision competence, the communicative readiness was different. Fioravanti notes that the problem of constitutional revision was appreciated by the contemporaries of the Revolution ,Footnote 360 but none of them had Sieyès ’ clarity to differentiate the constituent process of juridification by constitution from the ordinary legislative proceedings within the constituted legislative assembly . Sieyès explained the revision or amendment function of the jury by contrasting it with the permanent subliminal dangers of revolutionary turmoil that could result from radical constitutional changes. As an incremental policy of reform, rather than one employing great leaps, Sieyès ’ constitutional jury would rely on decennial progressive amelioration to secure the Revolutionary acquis of 1791 against recidivism, but also against overruling. Sieyès did not want to see the convention, like a figure from old mythology, constantly reborn, because this would invite danger. ‘Will we amuse ourselves by saying, like the phoenix, that it [the convention] will rise like a phoenix out of its ashes’, he asked rhetorically. ‘[T]he rebirth of the phoenix is a chimaera and the periodical return of a convention can be a real calamity.’Footnote 361 The revision function of the proposed constitutional jury , however, would avoid the alternative solution of periodical conventions, which seemed to him at best naïvely utopian, and at worst dangerous. The proposed amendment , or more exactly the proposed perfection of the Constitution, rewritten every ten years by the jury, was planned to be presented to the primary assemblies. The assembly members would then have the ability to grant or not to grant the legislative body the mandate to exercise constituent power , limited, in this case, to the simple acceptance or to the refusal of the proposition of the amendment . This was Sieyès ’ ‘project of amelioration of the constitutional act’ (projet d’amélioration de l’acte constitutionnel).Footnote 362 This complex procedure aimed, on the one hand, to involve the citizens in the process of revision and, on the other hand, to separate the responsible organs in charge of the revision’s proposition and its ratification. By his plea for partial changes at regular intervals, Sieyès communicated the singularity of the constituent assembly : any repetition carried in itself the risk of radical transformation, a vocabulary far too familiar to the contemporaries of the Thermodorian debates .

6.1.2.3 ‘Jury of Natural Equity’

The idea of a ‘natural jurisdiction as equitable supplement of the positive jurisdiction’ (supplément de juridiction naturelle aux vides de la juridiction positive)Footnote 363 was the attribution of the planned constitutional jury that challenged the contemporaries most. It raised the constitutional jury not only to an institutional standing as a court, but in doing so raised concerns that it was little more than a new edition of the ‘arbitrary jurisprudence’ of the Ancien Régime and its denounced cohorts of ‘commentators and interpreters.’Footnote 364 Being inspired by the English common law , Sieyès had drafted the equitable function of the constitutional jury Footnote 365 and tried to communicate its supplementary character by the prerequisite that cases could only be heard before it if they were officially referred to it by other courts. This would occur if these other courts declared themselves incapable of adjudicating, owing to the absence of applicable positive law , or if such judgement would occur contrary to the ‘conscience’ of the court, only according to the text of the law (exclusivement chargé de se prononcer sur les demandes officielles qui lui seraient portées par les divers tribunaux, à l’effet d’avoir un arrêt d’équité naturelle sur les cas qu’ils déclareraient n’avoir pu juger, faute de loi positive qui pût s’y appliquer, ou ne pouvoir juger que contre leur conscience, d’après le texte seul de la loi).Footnote 366 Continental Europe had typically understood ‘equity’ to be equivalent to aequitas, and thus the purview of God. Mercy, in this understanding, was not just a category of human law but divine will. Therefore, by attributing equity to his constitutional jury , Sieyès presumed that the jury would hold supreme authority over the ordinary courts .Footnote 367 This, however, could not be inferred; whereas Sieyès pretended a simple application of equity in the mere English correction manner, the vague character of natural equity was immediately assumed to be a pass for excessive, even arbitrary power.Footnote 368

Analysing the Thermodorian debates , it is evident that this competence of natural equity enshrined in the proposed constitutional jury might well have been the decisive issue that led to its unanimous rejection on 25 Thermidor III (12 August 1795).Footnote 369 All members of the Convention seemed to have gathered behind Antoine-Claire Thibaudeau ,Footnote 370 the Mountain deputy and former member of the Committee of Public Safety . Thibaudeau ’s speech before the Assembly on 24 Thermidor III (11 August 1795)Footnote 371 was symptomatic of the dismissive atmosphere against the project of the constitutional jury . Thibaudeau opposed two models of ‘limiting the power of the organs of the state’ (limitation du pouvoir des organes de l’État)—essentially, the models of ‘rule’ and ‘balance’Footnote 372—when concluding the lack of utility of constitutional control. He preferred, as he suggested vividly, ‘the liberal constitutionalism of the counterpowers.’ Thibaudeau continued:

If one examines the result of their researches [that of the publicists which have been interested in the separation of the powers] one will see that they have found two types of means to contain the powers, the ones which are external for them and the others which are inherent for them [to the organization even of the powers]. Among the first ones, one can classify the appeal to the people, the censors, or any other body established for judging the infractions of the constitution.Footnote 373

After rejecting the idea of the appeal to the people (l’appel au peuple),Footnote 374 Thibaudeau examined the question posed at the assembly by Sieyès :

Let us now see if a body instituted above the public powers, for examining their acts, as he [Sieyès ] proposes, is capable of guaranteeing their independence and integrity of the constitution, and I immediately pose myself this question: if the constitutional jury , the functions of which will be determined by the constitution, exceeds the limits thereof, who will suppress their usurpation?

According to Thibaudeau no answer could be found to the question who supervises the jurors:

I admit that I am searching for an answer but can’t find anything satisfying […] I would be justified in asking that supervisors be given to this jury and this gradual surveillance will be understood ad infinitum. Thus, [this reminds me of] the people of the Indies, they say that they commonly believe that the world is carried by an elephant and this elephant by a turtle; but when they arrive at asking on what the turtle rests, goodbye erudition.Footnote 375

Subsequent to this criticism, Thibaudeau arrived at exposing his model of the ‘guarantee of the limitation of the powers ’ (garantie de la limitation des pouvoirs):

The most sure and natural guardians of the whole constitution are the depositary bodies of the powers, then all the citizens. […] To prevent the confusion or the usurpation of the powers, one must give to them who exercise these powers means that sufficiently resist the attempts directed against them, that they are forced to respect each other by the feeling of their force and their dignity. In the organisation of the government each of these parts have to be established and posed in such a manner that they keep all the others at their places; one must oppose the ambition to the ambition.Footnote 376

With the paradox of the elephant and the turtle, Thibaudeau asks anew the old question: who watches the watchers (quis custodiet ipsos custodes?), only to conclude that there could be no reasonable, erudite solution to this intractable problem.Footnote 377

6.2 Defeat of Sieyès’ Jury Proposal and Its Consequences on the French Constitutional Jurisdiction

Thibaudeau was only one voice in the Convention against Sieyès ’ project. The lawyer Joseph Eschassériaux,Footnote 378 for example, was better disposed towards the constitutional jury than Thibaudeau , but he too rejected the function of natural equity, declaring it ‘useless in our system of civil legislation, and dangerous in politics.’Footnote 379 Others, including Louis-Marie de La Révellière-Lépeaux,Footnote 380 Denis Toussaint Lesage,Footnote 381 and Jean-Baptiste Louvet de Couvray,Footnote 382 also intervened in the Convention . According to Louvet de Couvray on 30 Thermidor III (17 August 1795), the control of the constitutionality was already present in the Constitution of the Year III itself, given the obligation ‘imposed on the executive power to annul the acts of its subordinates which are unconstitutional and in regard with this obligation it [the executive] is responsible, as it is for the infringements that it could committed itself to the constitutional act.’Footnote 383

Though Sieyès ’ ideas of a constitutional jury were roundly defeated in the discourses of 1795, the concept nevertheless found its way into the Consulate Constitution of the Year VIII (1799),Footnote 384 in the form of the College of Conservators (Collège des conservateurs), later the Conservatory Senate (Sénat).Footnote 385 This constitution replaced the centrality of the legislative power as characteristic for the revolutionary tradition with the primacy of the governmental function,Footnote 386 and therefore made the control of constitutionality more a political than a juridical question. As Paul Bastid has demonstrated, ‘[considered] under its political aspect, the jury or the college represented a kind of great revolutionary academy, where the traditions of 1789 became seen to be piously conserved and maintained.’Footnote 387 This shift away from a legal understanding towards a more political constitutionalism was also indicated by the renaming of Sieyès ’ jury as a ‘college’ and ‘senate.’Footnote 388

The college or senate as the a priori highest organ in the constitutional hierarchy was composed of eighty members, both under the name of the college and the senate ; for becoming member it was necessary to be at least forty years old. The choice of members was less free because the senate was obliged to choose among three candidates presented, one by the legislative body (corps législatif), the second by the tribunat,Footnote 389 and the third by the first consul; furthermore, if the same candidate was presented by all three of them, the Senate had to accept him.

Art. 21 of the 1799 Constitution mandated the Senate with the control of constitutionality of laws and governmental acts,Footnote 390 but the control authority was limited in Art. 29 to non-binding recommendations. The Senate’s opinions on the unconstitutionality ‘do not have a necessary consequence nor obliges any constituted authority to a deliberation’ (Art. 29).Footnote 391 This was the negation of the jury and the end of Sieyès ’ project, in the very moment where it seemed to be realised. The role of the Senate , namely to control the respect of the constitution and to guarantee the constitution’s superiority in relation to other norms via a preventive control (Art. 37),Footnote 392 remained theoretical. In practice, the disposition of Art. 21 had no effect: on the one hand, the Senate could not decide all alone and the tribunat was hesitant in entering any conflict with the government; on the other hand, no governmental act was ever revoked by the Senate. One historian has correctly remarked that, ‘[u]nder the consulate and under the two empires, one established a senate as guardian of the constitution. But this guardian was always a docile instrument between the hands of the first consul and the emperor.’Footnote 393

Therefore, the control of constitutionality of laws—theorised by Sieyès in Year III and constitutionalised in Year VIII—as an important and perhaps the most innovative part of the Consulate Constitution , was in practice never a functional element, and its defeat represented the first and the last attempt to create in France a neutral power of a political-jurisdictional nature.Footnote 394 Even today, the refusal of Sieyès ’ ideas continues to have an effect. The law as expression of the volonté générale , issued by a sovereign legislative assembly, was also the basis of the 1958 Constitution of the Fifth Republic ; this introduced the Constitutional Council (Conseil constitutionnel),Footnote 395 but the constitution itself is only very reluctantly exposed to control of constitutionality embodied in the Conseil, as the priority question of constitutionality expressed in Art. 61-1 demonstrates. In Art. 89, the 1958 Constitution expressly forbids constitutional revision , because the people are held to be continuously constituent (le peuple constituant toujours), and there is no control of constitutionality of constitutional amendments . It is, therefore, unsurprising that there is no scholarly consensus as to the precedential role played by Sieyès ’ draft in relation to modern constitutional courts .Footnote 396

The unanimous refusal of Sieyès ’ draft in the Convention was introduced by Thibaudeau ’s statement that ‘one must oppose the ambition to the ambition.’ In doing so Thibaudeau echoed James Madison ’s contention that ‘[a]mbition must be made to counteract ambition.’Footnote 397 Though Madison and Thibaudeau seem here to agree on the issue of the separation of powers, the paradox remains that, at the end of the eighteenth century, the American constitutional system was able to introduce a control mechanism for the constitutionality of the laws—the first of its type. France, on the other hand, found itself unable to countenance this control, or to reconcile it with the nature of constitutionalism . Thus, while constitutional control remains a hallmark of the American political system, and has been so since the time of Madison , the modern French Fifth Republic, like the First, still views such controls with suspicion and reluctance.

7 Avenues of New Constitutional Research: Sketching Germany, 1848–9

Reconsidering constitutional formation, it is clear that the early period of European constitutionalism was characterised by the establishment of constitutional normativity . This establishment adapted the different ideas of the American and French Revolutions, though this was hardly a straightforward process. As Goethe ’s Zahme Xenien poetically suggested, the Old World’s transition to the new juridification of the political order was always destined to be significantly more complex than that of the (relatively) clean slate of North America. A key example of this complexity was the struggle for national unification in Germany during the revolutionary years of 1848–9. On the one hand, German theorists and activists did not exist in a historical vacuum, and could draw upon the examples and lessons of both the United States and France.Footnote 398 On the other hand, half a century after the efforts of Hamilton and Madison in the United States, and Sieyès in France, the constitutional debates of St. Paul’s Church occurred within the context of a substantive politicisation of the broad population, creating a public discourse of constitutional legal matters in newspapers and pamphlets.

French theorists tended to view fundamental laws as philosophical truths. The German protagonists of imperial constitutionalism , on the other hand, relied on legal techniques against the complicated and irreconcilable backdrop of liberal claims for an unified government backed with popular representation and democratic claims for popular representation, together with the demands of the Prussian and Austrian Ultras, the Hegelian Left and the Junge Deutschland national literary movement, and political Catholicism.Footnote 399 By means of a statute the National Assembly proclaimed the ‘Fundamental Rights of the German People ’ ( Grundrechte des deutschen Volkes ) and provided for their immediate application disregarding all the unsolved questions in the constituent St. Paul’s Church assembly . The Act Relating to the Fundamental Rights of the German People (Reichsgesetz betreffend die Grundrechte des deutschen Volkes) was proclaimed on 27 December 1848 due to the National Assembly’s resolution six days before, months before the Frankfurt Imperial Constitution of 28 March 1849, coming into force on 17 January 1849 before being abrogated by federal decision on 23 August 1851. Prussia, Austria, Bavaria, and Hanover refused the publication of the fundamental rights .

Recent research, conducted under the auspices of the ReConFort project by Franziska Meyer (University of Passau) and Joachim Kummer (Free University of Berlin), has demonstrated that the public interest surrounding the juridification of the German national unification movement extended well into the legal aspects and challenges facing the St. Paul’s delegates.Footnote 400 This public engagement with the issue of constitutionalism was facilitated by the publication of numerous newspapers and pamphlets, and broadly addressed three themes: the aforementioned juridification, supremacy, and revision.Footnote 401

7.1 Juridification Matters in the Public Sphere Around the Constituent St. Paul’s Church Assembly

The differentiation between constitution and ordinary law was addressed in the German Constitutional Newspaper ( Deutsche constitutionelle Zeitung ) as basic legal framework and detailed singular provisions. In an article comparing the constitutions of Belgium and the United States to the constitution of Bavaria , an author for the paper distinguished ‘a well drafted constitution [which] should only regulate fundamental principles and not every detailed legal question’ from the ordinary law .Footnote 402 The People’s Friend ( Volksfreund ) claimed the constituent power for the people instead for the monarch ‘because it is the most important law .’Footnote 403 Conversely, the National-Newspaper (National-Zeitung ) built the new order on the unification more than on the constitution: ‘The constitution is necessary, but the statal unification gives a new quality of legal bonding to the powers.’Footnote 404 In the same vein, the criticism of the written crystallization of the constitution in a single document used the unwritten British constitutional framework as its exemplar, arguing that its foundation ‘on a solid political custom is far stronger than any written text’.Footnote 405

The juridification by constitution was further reflected by reporting on the oath to be taken by the king, the ministers, parliamentarians, and the military on the constitution.Footnote 406 The communicative message of the obligatory oath taken on the constitution before entering into office was twofold. On the one hand, it raised the prospect that all political power could only exist as constituted power . On the other hand, it was a solemn promise to respect the constitution. The latter was noted as being fragile,Footnote 407 owing to the lack of a legal consequence in its enforcement.Footnote 408 Consequences for the breach of oath were left to the regulation by the practical custom. Referring to the oath of Charles X of France , the constitutional oath of the king, in particular, was considered to be easily compromised.Footnote 409

Of primary importance was the potential conflict between the oath sworn on the constitution by the military and the obligations to the supreme command of a federal state.Footnote 410 This originated in the simple fact that, though the St. Paul’s debates concerned the German ‘nation ’, the practical institutions of governance remained the purview of the federal states. This meant that the German armies were answerable not to the nation —as, indeed, there was no national German army—but to their individual states, such as Prussia, Hanover, Bavaria, and Württemberg. Therefore, if the military sworn to uphold a particular command and to serve a particular state had to pledge loyalty to the national constitution, it would be caught between two camps. If a federal state were to raise its military forces against the imperial constitution , to which oath would the military pledge its loyalty: the nation and its constitution, or the federal state?Footnote 411 In the same vein, the Prussian politician and minister of finance, David Justus Ludwig Hansemann , argued ‘that the oath of the military [on the Constitution] would be a threat to its discipline.’Footnote 412 Whether this intractable problem could, in fact, be resolved ultimately became a moot point; as the Imperial Constitution was never enacted, the fundamental test of the loyalty and discipline of the armies never came to pass. Nonetheless, as Hansemann had alluded, at the heart of the military issue was a basic and vital question of precedence , and what the Imperial Constitution (or, indeed, any constitution) represented in terms of vested power.

7.2 Supremacy Matters in the Public Sphere Around the Constituent St. Paul’s Church Assembly

The introductory statute to the Act Relating to the Fundamental Rights of the German People (hereafter Fundamental Rights Act ; 1848)Footnote 413 ruled that every federal law contradicting the fundamental law act was either immediately null and void, or else must be amended within a certain period of time. The fundamental laws were communicated as obligatory legal standards to be complied with by the federative governments while also setting the legal requirements to change singular legal structures accordingly.Footnote 414 Most prominently, Art. 2 of the Fundamental Rights Act attracted journalistic attention by abolishing the estates’ privileges. Liberal newspapers, such as the Deutsche constitutionelle Zeitung , even demanded the closing of the first chamber of Bavaria, which acted as a legislative body of hereditary privilege similar to the British House of Lords.Footnote 415 As an expression of noble entitlement, the first chamber could no longer be tolerated under Art. 2 of the Fundamental Rights Act .

What was particularly remarkable was the liberal linguistic turn away from seeing the Fundamental Rights Act as a protective right, and instead conceptualising it as an active measure to be wielded to change the structure and law of the federal states. This, however, did not occur without opposition, and conservative protest was widespread. The New Munich Journal ( Neue Münchener Zeitung ), for instance, argued that fundamental laws were not immediately effective; instead, they had to be approved by the federative government and parliament respectively. For conservatives, such an implementing approval was the only constitutional way to introduce the fundamental laws into a federal state.Footnote 416 This amounted to a constitutional understanding not as a paramount law but rather as a mere societal contract.

The nullification of anterior law started as a matter of course . The National Assembly already agreed in May 1848 that a law contradicting the constitution was null and void.Footnote 417 Art. 30 of the draft constitution went so far as to state explicitly that ‘[e]very resolution, federal law or treaty between federal states, are void, insofar as they contradict the National Constitution.’Footnote 418 The Frankfurt Imperial Constitution (Reichsverfassung; 1849), however, lacked legal consequences for laws contradicting the constitution. The relevant Art. 194 simply stated ‘that the ordinary law must not contradict the national constitution .’Footnote 419 Despite the hierarchisation of constitution and statutes, an explicit nullification of contradictory statutes was missing. Centre-left newspapers criticised this oversight, and justified their demand of the nullification with comparative arguments, though these often included inaccuracies and mischaracterisations.Footnote 420 So, for example, the Free People’s Gazette ( Freie Volksblätter ) reported that the Belgian Constitution (1831) allowed state officials to refuse the execution of laws they thought to be issued unconstitutionally.Footnote 421 In fact, the relevant provision—Art. 107—only referred to judges, and no other officials.

The public interest in the establishment of a constitutional jurisdiction and the introduction of a judicial review corresponded with the prominence of judicial administration and legally established courts within liberal legal thought. Deeply influenced by Immanuel Kant’s formulation of the liberal state under the rule of law, Paul Johann Anselm von Feuerbach ’s essay on the Bavarian court constitutionFootnote 422 and its unaffectedness by means of ministerial and cabinet regulations defined the court constitution as the ‘exterior appearance’ of justice and the essence of the liberal rule of law state.Footnote 423 In Feuerbach ’s words, the court constitutional legal reservation correlated to the legal commitment of the adjudicating power: ‘If this court constitution does not by itself exist as a law but as a simple regulation, then the judiciary in its most interior circle is made dependent on a non-statute as the highest fundamental rule.’Footnote 424 Any regulatory competence of the executive in regard to the court constitution would nip judiciary independence in the bud, as then the legal validity of judicial actions would not alone be measured by laws but also by executive orders.Footnote 425 As opposed to the Rousseau -inspired super-elevation of the general will and the French distrust against judges, German liberal writers, such as Klüber, Mittermaier, Pfeiffer, and Zachariae, were interested in the court constitutional legal reservation as prerequisite of judicial independenceFootnote 426 and of the justiciability of subjective rights.Footnote 427

The plea for the introduction of the constitutional complaint was an obvious step. For the activists, the next obvious step was to publish this plea in newspapers and pamphlets. The Württemberg political scientist Robert von Mohl , a member of the Frankfurt Parliament, argued in the German Newspaper ( Deutsche Zeitung ) that the fundamental rights of each citizen should be secured by an independent and permanent constitutional court .Footnote 428 Its competences should among others include a constitutional complaint .Footnote 429 This frequent liberal demand was combatted by the state governments,Footnote 430 also using the newspapers as medium. They proposed that a query should first be raised in a federal parliament by a sitting member; only if this failed would the representatives be entitled to appeal to the constitutional court .Footnote 431 In this version, power would be vested in the political process through the representatives in the parliament; no ordinary citizen would ever be allowed to appeal to the constitutional court personally. Ultimately, though, this obstructive position was not successful. Instead, the St. Paul’s delegates wrote § 126g and § 126h into the Imperial Constitution . These sections provided for the constitutional complaint of citizens to the planned ‘Constitutional Court.’Footnote 432 § 126g determined that ‘law suits of German citizens against the infringement of their rights guaranteed by the constitution’ had to be ruled by the Imperial Court (Reichsgericht).Footnote 433 The most important textual template was the provision in Title VII, § 21 of the Bavarian Constitution of 1818 , which granted citizens the right to appeal ‘to the assembly of estates against the infringement of constitutional rights.’Footnote 434 However, this did not allow for a constitutional complaint , rather for a petition in regard to a lawful administration.Footnote 435

Even if the reasons for Sieyès’ caution with the choice of the constitutional jurors were not applicable to the Frankfurt constitutional debates , there was a particular public interest in the question of how constitutional judges would be elected. Mohl proposed a court with judges and a jury, both of them consisting of members of the parliament. He wanted the judges to be elected by the parliament. The jury of the court should not be elected but rather chosen by lots. For him it was self-explanatory that the king should have no say in the election of the judges and the jury.Footnote 436 Adolph Bach, an otherwise unknown author, preferred the judges to be elected by other judges of lower courts.Footnote 437 He also argued that no one should be able to control them.Footnote 438 A third voice, a professor of philosophy by the name of Braniß, voted for the judges to be elected by the courts and faculties of law.Footnote 439 Despite this vivid discussion around the constituent assembly, the goals of the debates inside its chamber were rather meagre in this respect. In the final analysis, § 128 of the Imperial Constitution held the organisation of the courts to be a matter of ordinary and not constitutional law.Footnote 440

The failure of the Imperial Constitution specifically, and the Frankfurt Assembly as a whole, often distracts from developments further south. But Frankfurt was not the only centre of debate, negotiation, and compromise during this period of European upheaval. In Austria, the so-called ‘Kremsierer Constitutional draft ’ (1848–9) held the provision that the highest imperial court should be the only competent instance for ‘lawsuits for compensation due to the infringement of constitutional rights by an official act of state employees.’Footnote 441 This draft was not present in the analysed public discourse around the St. Paul’s Assembly, and it was not before the Austro-Hungarian Compromise of 1867 that an individual constitutional complaint was introduced in Austria. Regarding the establishment of an imperial court, the Austrian Fundamental Law attributed to this court the competence for ‘complaints of citizens on the infringement of their political rights guaranteed by the constitution’ (after the exhaustion of all legal measures provided by the administrative law).Footnote 442 However, the verdicts of this imperial court had no annulling effect, but instead were only declarative. The detailed drafting of the Austrian imperial court (excluding the Hungarian territories of the Austro-Hungarian Empire) was left to the implementing law of 18 April 1869,Footnote 443 which coincided with the court coming into life. § 17 of the implementing law regulated the proceedings of the individual constitutional complaint and made the legal nature of the genuine complaint explicit in § 35, providing for the wording of the ruling that citizens’ rights were infringed.Footnote 444

7.3 Revision Matters in the Public Sphere Around the Constituent St. Paul’s Church Assembly

In regard to constitutional amendments , the St. Paul’s Constitution imposed the right to amendment proposals to the king and to both houses of the parliament.Footnote 445 Newspapers or pamphlets did not discuss this topic, as the right to initiate for both powers had been generally accepted. The constitutional draft presented on 26 April 1848 by the committee of seventeen under Friedrich Christoph Dahlmann also included the same regulation.Footnote 446 Rather, the procedure, or the means by which amendments would be enacted, attracted more interest. For some newspapers, like the Deutsche constitutionelle Zeitung , juridification by constitution was an irreversible truth once a constitution had come into force. This was similar to Sieyès ’ concept of constitutionalism ; the transformation from pouvoir constituant to pouvoir constitué was understood as one-way track and, providing that it was passed in a constitutional way, could not be overturned without risking a revolution.Footnote 447 The same could be heard from Heinrich von Gagern , president of the National Assembly , when he called in April 1849 for an adherence to the Constitution ‘not because the constitution would be perfect or he would be totally convinced by all of the provisions, but the constitution itself determines the procedure for modifications which has to be observed.’Footnote 448 Such a statement is embedded in the legal understanding of constitutional precedence ; the ratified constitution stood above all, and even a complete modification could only be done in the way the constitution describes. It had to be observed, even if it did not fulfil all of its expectations.

In regard to the modifying quora and majorities, the St. Paul’s Constitution determined in Art. 196 that two-thirds of the members had to be present at the voting and a majority of two thirds has to be achieved. These requirements had to be complied with in both chambers.Footnote 449 Many pamphlets advocated for a two-third majority as well,Footnote 450 whereas the constitutional draft of the seventeen demanded a quorum of three-quarters to modify the constitution. Footnote 451 The two-thirds quorum and majority earned some critics. The Deutsche constitutionelle Zeitung viewed quorum provisions as too complicated at best, and constitutionally dangerous at worst; in the case of minority parties that could not hope to achieve quorum, the paper argued, disillusionment with the process could lead to these parties pursuing extrajudicial means to enact constitutional amendment , including rioting and revolution.Footnote 452

Another branch of criticism was followed by David Hansemann , the Prussian minister of finance, who played a pivotal role in Prussian politics during the revolutionary years of 1848–9. In response to the proposal that the Prussian king should accept the united German crown and modify the constitution afterwards, Hansemann declared that this would set a dangerous precedent, because the constitution could be modified later in a more liberal and republican way.Footnote 453

The royal veto on constitutional amendments was a bastion for royalists. At the other end of the line one, several municipalities petitioned the National Assembly in March 1849 that the executive should be excluded from participating in the process of constitutional revision .Footnote 454 The non-integration of the crown into the amendment process was not a position held by the majority, and the Imperial Constitution included the king’s right to a suspensive veto on constitutional amendments or modifications. ‘Suspensive’ meant, in this case, that the parliament could overcome the veto of the king in three successive sessions.Footnote 455 This was a thorn in David Hansemann ’s side. According to him, it revealed the ‘true’ constituent intention to establish a republic ‘hiding behind the title of a monarchy.’Footnote 456 Because of this, the Prussian government insisted on an absolute veto , which it believed was necessary in the enacting, abolishing, and amending of law.Footnote 457

The voices in favour of a suspensive veto met in their assessment for a necessary balance between parliament and monarch. The issue of a veto had been raised in the pages of the Deutsches Volksblatt as early as December 1848, in which the author pointed out that the question of the veto was neither a question of the divine right of kings nor liberty, but rather a simple question of power. Indeed, the parliamentarian Friedrich Dahlmann had defended the instrument of the veto in the German National Assembly by saying that England’s political situation would be better if the instrument of the veto would nowadays not be practically impossible. There was no other option than implementing a veto —the examples of Norway and North America showed that the alternative would be only a delay of requests.Footnote 458 The instrument of the veto was also generally supported by the National-Zeitung . One correspondent to this newspaper disapproved of an absolute veto , on the grounds that it would in fact weaken, rather than strengthen, the position of the king. Again, the English example was pertinent, as the monarchy’s power of absolute veto had become so impractical that it had fallen into complete disuse. On the other hand, the example of Norway showed that a suspensive veto provided a reasonable avenue to deal with overhasty decisions of the parliament. In this argument, though, the newspaper distinguished between the territorial states and the federal state. In the territorial states, the king should have the right of a two-times suspensive veto , while in the federal state the king should just hold the right for a single suspensive veto . The reason for this lay in the position of the king and the role he played in the body politic. In the federal state, the king would not be the sovereign; rather, he would simply be the highest executive organ.Footnote 459

This opinion was also followed by Johann Gottlieb Kuechler , who also argued that an absolute veto damaged the venerability of the king. An absolute veto implied that the dignity and will of the people could be disregarded by the king using an arbitrary prerogative. In doing so, it therefore alienated the person of the king from the will of the population, thereby affecting the prestige of his position, and the love and esteem in which he was held. The absolute veto , in other words, was not a symbol of the dignity of the king. Kuechler ’s solution, like that of the proprietors of the National-Zeitung , was the suspensive veto , which would confirm the king’s position as the highest power in the state, while also ensuring that this power was subject to existing laws that the king has to observe. The examples of North America, Norway, and Brazil had amply demonstrated that the suspensive veto was both useful and reasonable, and made hasty and ill-considered decisions (both on the part of the legislature and the executive) impossible.Footnote 460 Thus, as Kuechler conceived it, the suspensive veto served a dual purpose. Pragmatically, it offered a reasonable monarchical check and balance to parliamentarianism, much as the constitution itself was a popular check and balance on monarchical power . Beyond this, it would help to cement the image of the king as a benevolent but not omnipotent leader, working in the best interests of his subjects.

The purpose of the ReConFort project has been to investigate European constitutional heritage. However, in this sketch of the German case study, the project has also opened new avenues of research and inquiry. The American and French discourses are necessary for understanding the contributions in this volume regarding the Belgian, Italian, and Polish case studies, but even in the necessarily brief discussion of the German example presented here, it is clear that there are heretofore unrecognised patterns of continuity and conformity, as well as adaptation to local conditions. The American ‘invention’ of the judicial review and the French reluctance to limit the legislative consent representing the continuous sovereignty of the people provided European formulations of constitutional precedence with both positive and negative poles; what Hansemann , Gagern , and their compatriots in the St. Paul’s Assembly demonstrated was that there was still a spectrum in between those poles, in which political and judicial actors and constitutional theorists would attempt to set their own course. The form that this course took, and the influences upon it, provide us with further insight into the development of Europe’s ‘community’ of constitutionalism , and it is these elements that promise and afford further opportunities for research.

8 Conclusion

In 1782, Charles Thomson found inspiration in Virgil’s Eclogue IV, when he sketched his unfinished pyramid and proclaimed the Novus Ordo Seclorum for the newly-founded United States of America. Thomson ’s choice of expression implied a clean break from Europe and the birth of a new society unencumbered by Europe’s old iniquities. Four decades later, Johann Wolfgang von Goethe believed that America’s ‘new order’ had succeeded, when he lamented Europe’s continued ‘useless remembering and unrewarding strife.’

As it turns out, neither was entirely correct. The ‘new order’ ushered in an unprecedented constitutional experiment, but one which borrowed liberally from the precedent of the Old World. Nor—in spite of Goethe ’s pessimism—was Europe unwilling (or unable) to learn. Remembrance, in this case, was hardly as ‘useless’ as Goethe imagined, and constitutional theorists and practitioners of nineteenth-century Europe looked to historical examples for their own inspiration. This amounted not necessarily to a preoccupation, but more to a desire to avoid the mistakes of the past by learning from them. Emmanuel Joseph Sieyès and Antoine-Claire Thibaudeau , for example, were opponents whose clashes in the French National Convention appear to have been irreconcilable; certainly, they were never able to resolve these differences before the Revolution was overtaken by Bonapartism and embarked on a new course. However, though their approaches differed, fundamentally they were addressing the same questions: who does a constitution serve? How does it do so? How can the integrity of the constitution be maintained? Most ambitious of all: what is a constitution in the pantheon of law and order, politics and society? These were the same questions posed to and by James Madison , Alexander Hamilton , and the American constitutionalists at the end of the nineteenth century, and they were the same questions debated in St. Paul’s Church in Frankfurt in 1848 and 1849. Though the specific circumstances and contexts have changed, they are also, at a basic level, the questions facing western liberal democracy as a whole, and the European Union in particular, as we near the end of the first fifth of the twenty-first century.

If we return to Virgil’s Eclogue, we find not just an appeal to a ‘new order of ages’, but also the prophecy of the Cumaean Sibyl:

Now the last age by Cumae’s Sibyl sung

Has come and gone, and the majestic roll

Of circling centuries begins anew:

Justice returns, returns old Saturn’s reign,

With a new breed of men sent down from heaven.

Only do thou, at the boy’s birth in whom

The iron shall cease, the golden age arise.Footnote 461

Thomson believed Virgil’s words to be an appropriate conception of his new society; here, too, the Sybil’s prognosis appears prophetic in light of the challenges facing the European Union today. Thomson ’s unfinished pyramid, in its original iteration, symbolised the absence of the monarch in the new American system, but it can also be read as an indicator, in the words of Barack Obama, that ‘[t]he unfinished work of perfecting our union falls to each of us.’Footnote 462 This sentiment is as applicable to Europe as it is to the United States.

The enduring lesson of ReConFort is not one of ‘useless remembering’, as Goethe has phrased it in his poem To the United States, but rather that remembering serves a purpose in opening a window on to the challenges and opportunities faced by the European Union now and in the future. The individual member states of the Union have their own, unique contexts and complexities. Yet it is also true that European constitutionalism shares certain commonalities—even when that definition of ‘Europe’ extended to settlement away from the Old World, and even when that constitutionalism was a concerted attempt to break away from Europe. By acknowledging these commonalities, and by investigating their histories, ReConFort provides a greater framework for understanding the present day. In this way, ReConFort is a further stone in the gradual construction of Europe’s own incomplete pyramid and, it is to be hoped, a contribution to the ‘unfinished work of perfecting our union.’