Skip to main content

Heuristic Logic. A Kernel

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 41))

Abstract

In this paper I lay out a non-formal kernel for a heuristic logic—a set of rational procedures for scientific discovery and ampliative reasoning—specifically, the rules that govern how we generate hypotheses to solve problems. To this end, first I outline the reasons for a heuristic logic (Sect. 1) and then I discuss the theoretical framework needed to back it (Sect. 2). I examine the methodological machinery of a heuristic logic (Sect. 3), and the meaning of notions like ‘logic’, ‘rule’, and ‘method’. Then I offer a characterization of a heuristic logic (Sect. 4) by arguing that heuristics are ways of building problem-spaces (Sect. 4.1). I examine (Sect. 4.2) the role of background knowledge for the solution to problems, and how a heuristic logic builds upon a unity of problem-solving and problem-finding (Sect. 4.3). I offer a first classification of heuristic rules (Sect. 5): primitive and derived. Primitive heuristic procedures are basically analogy and induction of various kinds (Sect. 5.1). Examples of derived heuristic procedures (Sect. 6) are inversion heuristics (Sect. 6.1) and heuristics of switching (Sect. 6.2), as well as other kinds of derived heuristics (Sect. 6.3). I then show how derived heuristics can be reduced to primitive ones (Sect. 7). I examine another classification of heuristics, the generative and selective (Sect. 8), and I discuss the (lack of) ampliativity and the derivative nature of selective heuristics (Sect. 9). Lastly I show the power of combining heuristics for solving problems (Sect. 10).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See in particular Lakatos (1976, 1978), Laudan (1977, 1981), Nickles (1978, 1981), Popper (1999), Jaccard and Jacoby (2010), Cellucci (2013), Ippoliti and Cellucci (2016).

  2. 2.

    The most famous defender of this view is Herbert Simon (see Simon et al. 1987), who argued for an ‘algorithmic discovery’, a computational model for discovery, implemented in his software BACON. In the end we can consider this view untenable. At most it can model the result of the construction of a hypothesis—the only one that can be treated effectively by a computer, namely the one after the conceptualization, selection of data and choice of variables, has already been made by humans (for a critical appraisal of Simon’s approach see in particular Nickles 1980; Kantorovich 1993, 1994; Gillies 1996; Weisberg 2006).

  3. 3.

    A representation theorem is a theorem that states that an abstract structure with certain properties can be reduced to, or is isomorphic to, another structure.

  4. 4.

    See Cellucci (2013), Chap. 20.

  5. 5.

    An analogy is a type of inference that concludes, from the fact that two objects are similar in certain respects and that one of them has a certain property, that the other has the same property. It therefore enables the transfer of certain properties from a source (object or set of objects) to a target (object or set of objects). According to the meaning that we attach to the expression “to be similar”, we can define different kinds of analogies (e.g. analogy for quasi-equality, separate indistinguishability, inductive analogy, proportional analogy).

  6. 6.

    In their paper Spiro et al. discuss these ways of combining analogies only by means of didactical examples: they do not offer examples of real cases of scientific discovery, or hypotheses, obtained by these combinations. Nonetheless their taxonomy is effective and can be put in use.

References

  • Campbell, D. T. (1960). Blind variation and selective retention in creative thought as in other knowledge processes. Psychological Review, 67, 380–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. (2013). Rethinking Logic. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (2002). Induction and deduction in physics. In Albert Einstein (Ed.), Collected papers (Vol. 7, pp. 108–109). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1996). Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 103, 650–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Todd, P. M. (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2000). Adaptive thinking: Rationality in the real world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Why heuristics work. Perspective on Psychological Science, 3(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (1996). Artificial intelligence and scientific method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti, E. (2006). Il vero e il plausibile. Morrisville (USA): Lulu.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippoliti, E., & Celluci, C. (2016). Logica. Milano: Egea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaccard, J., & Jacoby, J. (2010). Theory construction and model-building. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich, A. (1993). Scientific discovery: Logic and tinkering. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich, A. (1994). Scientific discovery: A philosophical survey. Philosophia, 23(1), 3–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. The Journal of Business, 59(S4), S251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems. Berkeley and LA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A problem-solving approach to scientific progress. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions (pp. 144–155). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire, W. J. (1968). Personality and susceptibility to social influence. In E. F. Borgatta & W. W. Mabert (Eds.), Handbook of personality: theory and research (pp. 1130–1187). Chicago: Rand McNally.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). Is there a logic of scientific discovery? LSE Quarterly, 2–3, 205–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1978). Scientific problems and constraints. PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, I, 134–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (Ed.). (1980). Scientific discovery: Logic and rationality. Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1981). What is a problem that we may solve it? Synthese, Vol. 47, No. 1, Scientific Method as a Problem-Solving and Question-Answering Technique, pp. 85–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (2014). Heuristic appraisal at the frontier of research. In E. Ippoliti (Ed.), Heuristic reasoning (pp. 57–88). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, G (2002). The entropy formula for the Ricci flow and its geometric applications. arXiv:math. DG/0211159.

  • Perelman, G. (2003a). Ricci flow with surgery on three-manifolds. arXiv:math.DG/0303109.

  • Perelman, G. (2003b). Finite extinction time for the solutions to the Ricci flow on certain three-manifolds. arXiv:math.DG/0307245.

  • Polya, G. (1954). Mathematics and plausible reasoning. Vol. I—Induction and analogy in mathematics), Vol. II—Patterns of plausible inferences. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1934). The logic of scientific discovery (1959). London: Hutchinson & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1999). All life is problem solving. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quarantotto, D. (2017). Aristotle’s problemata style and aural textuality. In R. Polansky & W. Wians (Eds.), Reading Aristotle (pp. 75–122). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (2003). Multiple analogies in science and philosophy. Amsterdam: John Benjamins B.V.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spiro, R. J., Feltovich, P. J., Coulson, R. L., & Anderson, D. K. (1989). Multiple analogies for complex concepts: Antidotes for analogyinduced misconception in advanced knowledge acquisition. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 498–529). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H., Langley, P., Bradshaw, G. L., & Zytkow, M. (1987). Scientific discovery: Computational explorations of the creative processes. Boston: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ugaglia, M. (2004). Modelli idrostatici del moto da Aristotele a Galileo. Roma: Lateran University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulazia, A. (2016). Multiple roles for analogies in the genesis of fluid mechanics: How analogies can cooperate with other heuristic strategies. Foundation of Science, 21(4), 543–565. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9423-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, R. (2006). Creativity: Understanding innovation in problem solving, science, invention, and the arts. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1982). Productive thinking (Enlarged Ed.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. H. (1996). The lack of a priori distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation, 8, 1341–1390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D., & Macready, W. (1996). No Free Lunch Theorems for Search. Technical Report SFI-TR-95-02-010. Sante Fe, NM, USA: Santa Fe Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahar, E. (1989). Einstein’s Revolution: A Study In Heuristic. La Salle (Ilinois): Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank David Danks, Carlo Cellucci, the two anonymous referees, and the speakers at the conference ‘Building Theories’ (Rome, 16–18 June 2016) for their valuable comments on an early version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emiliano Ippoliti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ippoliti, E. (2018). Heuristic Logic. A Kernel. In: Danks, D., Ippoliti, E. (eds) Building Theories. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 41. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72787-5_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics