Skip to main content

ABDUCTIVE INFERENCES IN PRAGMATIC PROCESSES

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 18))

Abstract

In pragmatic theories, the notion of inference plays a central role, together with the communicative act in which it is activated. Although some scholars, such as Levinson, Sperber and Wilson, propose detailed and accurate analyses of this notion, we will maintain that these analyses can be better systematized if seen through Peirce’s notion of abduction. We will try to maintain that the variety of inferential processes in play in a linguistic act is mostly of an abductive nature. Moreover, we will maintain that the typological tripartition of abductions discussed by Eco (1981) allows to account for a significant part of the mechanisms involved in the comprehension of an utterance, ranging from quasi-immediate and spontaneous levels of understanding to processes that draw on creative resources. In our proposal the vast majority of our linguistic activities implies the automatic retrieval of a habit of action (automatic abduction). In the other cases we need more onerous processes. We might need to identify, among a range of possibilities, the appropriate rule (habit of action/linguistic routine) to be applied to the contextual situation (abduction by selection) or, depending on the context and on our background knowledge, we might be forced to create ex novo a new linguistic routine (creative abduction). In our view, this typology of abductive inferences (Eco, 1981; see also Bonfantini and Proni, 1980) provides us with all the necessary tools to account for the different inferential demands entailed by different levels of the process of language comprehension. On the basis of this typology we can, develop a fine-grained model of linguistic inferences and, thus, simplify the terms of some problematic nodes debated within contextualist approaches.

The benefits of this fine-grained model is that it provides a unitary framework in which all the levels of the process of language comprehension are shown to be inferential and have the same logic structure (the structure of abduction). At the same time, it is also able to account for all the different inferential efforts entailed by different linguistic processes. Thus, this model gives us both a unitary account of the structure of linguistic inferences and a fine-grained description of the differences existing between them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We selected this quotation from Bonfantini (1983; Bonfantini and Proni 1980) because Eco himself, in presenting his typology made reference to Bonfantini and Proni’s work. In Eco’s typology the three categories of abduction are called respectively ipercodified abduction, ipocodified abduction and creative abduction. Considering that both Bonfantini and Proni’s and Eco’s typology identify the same types of abductive inferences, we prefer here to use Bonfantini and Proni’s terminology.

  2. 2.

    It is worth noting that abduction is a hypothetical form of reasoning. The interpretative hypothesis automatically provided by primary pragmatic processes is usually put forth in parallel with the output of secondary pragmatic processes. The latter can be considered as an empirical test to evaluate the former.

References

  • Bonfantini, M. (1983). Abduction. A priori, brain: For a research program. Versus, 34, 3–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonfantini, M., & Proni, G. (1980). To guess or not to guess? Scienze Umane, 6, 249–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2011). The attributive/referential distinction, pragmatics, modularity of mind and modularization. Australian Journal of Linguistics, 31(2), 153–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2007). How many pragmatic systems are there? In M. J. Frapolli (Ed.), Saying, meaning, referring. Essays on the philosophy of François Recanati (pp. 1–17). New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H., & Gerrig, R. J. (1983). Understanding old word with new meanings. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 591–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1981). “Guessing: From Aristotle to Sherlock Holmes”. Versus, vol. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferraresi, M. (1983). Le abduzioni nel testo. Versus, 34, 59–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Mantia, F. (2012). Che senso ha? Polisemia e attività di linguaggio. Milano: Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazzone, M. (2013). Automatic and controlled process in pragmatics. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics (pp. 443–467). Heidelberg/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reasons? Argument for an argomentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 57–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (CP). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6, 1931–1935, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, eds., vols. 7–8. Arthur W. Burks, ed., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, V. ( 2005). Relevance theory through pragmatic theories of meaning. In Proceedings of the XXVII meeting cognitive sciences (pp. 1767–1772). L: Erbaum, Alpha.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Reply to Carston. In M. J. Frapolli (Ed.), Saying, meaning, referring. Essays on the philosophy of François Recanati (pp. 49–54). New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Literal meaning. In Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). The background of meaning. In J. R. Searle, F. Kiefer, & M. Bierwisch (Eds.), Speech act theory and pragmatics (pp. 221–232). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. (2009). http://www.phon.ucl.ac.uk/home/relevance/relevance_archives_new/0477.html

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1996). Relevance. Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (2002). Pragmatics, modularity and mind-reading. Mind & Language, 17, 3–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., & Sperber, D. (2002). Truthfulness and relevance. Mind, 111, 583–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., & Sperber, D. (2004). Relevance theory. In L. R. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), The Blackwell’s handbook of pragmatics (pp. 607–633). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors want to thank Roberta Rocca and Stefania Garello for their useful comments on the paper.

Although both authors discussed and designed the article together, sections 2, 3, 4 were written by Marco Carapezza, while sections 5, 6 were written by Valentina Cuccio, sections 1 and 7 were written jointly by both the authors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Carapezza .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Carapezza, M., Cuccio, V. (2018). ABDUCTIVE INFERENCES IN PRAGMATIC PROCESSES. In: Capone, A., Carapezza, M., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 18. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72173-6_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72173-6_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-72172-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-72173-6

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics