Skip to main content

Hallucination and the Text: “Circe” Between Narrative, Epistemology, and Neurosciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cognitive Joyce

Part of the book series: Cognitive Studies in Literature and Performance ((CSLP))

  • 325 Accesses

Abstract

This article explores the “Circe” episode of Ulysses in the light of recent debates on hallucination in neurosciences and the philosophy of mind. Bridging the gap between these two fields, it offers an alternative to the traditionally vague definition of hallucination as an intuitively grasped experience which deviates from ordinary perception. Arguing that the technique of the episode is similar to phantasmagoria, a pre-cinematic genre whose deceptive nature foreshadows the shifting viewpoints of “Circe”, and drawing on the works of Lev Vygotsky and Charles Fernyhough, it arrives at an integrated definition of the status of “hallucination” in art, which does justice to both its epistemological and narrative implications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the schema which Joyce produced for Gilbert , see Gilbert (1930).

  2. 2.

    See also the dialogue between the scientific and the philosophical approaches to the study of the functioning of the mind proposed by Changeux and Ricœur .

  3. 3.

    In his article, Dorsch proposes a theory that not only requires the cooperation of philosophy and cognitive sciences, but also aims at providing a philosophical view applicable to both perceptual (i.e. subjectively indistinguishable from perceptions ) and non-perceptual hallucinations (Dorsch 2010). See also Dorsch’s article in Fiona Macpherson and Dimitris Platchias eds. (2013), a collection of essays which represents a first attempt at analysing hallucination from the point of view of both philosophy and cognitive sciences. The volume adopts the perspective of Disjunctivism (see n. 10 below) and features several scholars that I will come to quote in this essay (Bentall , Fernyhough , Macpherson ).

  4. 4.

    The focus has been mainly on the relation between “Circe” and early cinema : see especially Keith Williams (2003), Carla Marengo Vaglio (2007), Maria DiBattista (2010), and Philip Sicker (2010). I have already proposed an analysis of the features which link “Circe” to phantasmagoria in Prudente (2015).

  5. 5.

    For instance, Briggs’s seminal study in the field mentions this device when stating that “cinema —child of the Phantasmagoria and the Magick Lantern […]—is even more suggestive than is pantomime of the technique of ʻCirce,ʼ Hallucination, and the art of ʻCirce,ʼ Magic” (Briggs 149).

  6. 6.

    One very recent example is Catherine Flynn’s examination of the surrealist elements in “Circe,” where the phantasmagoria is employed in the way Benjamin used the term to describe urban experience (see Benjamin 2002).

  7. 7.

    The Belgian Etienne Gaspard-Robert claimed to be the inventor of the phantasmagoria , but, as Mannoni demonstrates, he drew for his shows on devices already employed by others, mainly by Philidor (Mannoni and Brewster 1996, 390–3).

  8. 8.

    “The Argument from Illusion” and “The Argument from Hallucination” are the founding elements of the opposition between the perceptual theories of direct or “naïve” realism and those of indirect or “representational ” realism . While the first argues that in perception the subject establishes a relation with “real,” mind-independent objects, the latter maintains that what we experience is an internal representation or replica of the world. The two mentioned arguments—which emerged in the eighteenth century (BonJour 2013)—were brought forward by representationalists so as to prove the existence of sense-data testifying to the mediate quality of our perception . Representational realism argues that since hallucination is subjectively indistinguishable from veridical perception , these two experiences share common qualities which render them equally real to the subject, thus undermining direct realism’s belief into the subject’s perception of the object itself, “real” and mind-independent. For an overview of the issue, see Lowe 102–58.

  9. 9.

    As opposed to previous interpretations of the cinematic medium as based on “transparency” (Cavell ), “illusion” (of Derridian matrix ), “imagination ” and “recognition” (deriving from cognitive analysis). Allen (1999) associates the four theories with the causal theory of perception (see n. 9 below).

  10. 10.

    In the history of philosophy , causal theories of perception (CTP) have been attributed to thinkers like Descartes , Locke , Kant , and Russell , although obviously not in the form of unified theories, but rather as inscribed in their different theorizations. In the twentieth century, Grice has revived the argument by proposing what has been defined as a “stronger” version of the founding principles of this theory. In general terms, the CTP maintains that the condition to perception is not that the perceiver establishes a relation with the percept, but rather that the percept causes the sense-datum which the subject perceives. In this sense, the CTP is directly connected to representational realism , and objections to this theory stem mainly from philosophers belonging to naïve realism (see especially Hyman ). As for the implications in film studies, Allen’s confutation is directed towards the CTP intended as comprising all the filmic theories implying the act of seeing as caused by the seen object.

  11. 11.

    Hallucination’s indistinguishability from veridical experience is another central concern of the debate between naïve and representational realisms . The most recent outcome of this discussion has been the founding of Disjunctivism , a specific current of direct realism that maintains the non-equivalence between genuine and hallucinatory perceptions on which Allen’s film theory is grounded. Disjunctivism has argued this principle from two different perspectives, one related to an epistemic and the other to a metaphysical conception of hallucination. The first holds that veridical and hallucinatory experiences do not share common qualities, as the only quality that can be attributed to hallucination is precisely its being indistinguishable from veridical perceptions (Martin 2004, 72). For an overview of Disjunctivism see Macpherson and Haddock (2008).

  12. 12.

    On the nature of subjective shots in early cinema , see also Gaudreault .

  13. 13.

    Gregory Currie (1995b) has analysed how unreliability works in cinema and narrative by focusing especially on the figure of the implied author which, in his view, is always present in narrative, but absent in cinema (for a more recent elaboration of his theory of point of view in narration, see also Currie 2009). Also in relation to this issue, the unique form of “Circe” proves a significant case study, where the boundaries between the two media are blurred and give rise to a representational technique escaping categories.

  14. 14.

    See also Ferrer’s emphasis on how “the theatricality makes real the hallucination, and, reciprocally, hallucinates reality ” (Ferrer 1984, 141).

  15. 15.

    For a study of the narrative consequences of inserting a hallucinatory point of view in narration, see also Ferrer’s analysis of the episode of the “solitary traveller” in Woolf’s Mrs. Dalloway (Ferrer 1990, 130–9).

  16. 16.

    See es pe ci ally Briggs (1989), Williams (2003), Hanaway (2010), DiBattista (2010), Sicker (2010).

  17. 17.

    See, for instance, “The Sun Woman,” a phantasmagoria slide held at the “Cabinet of Physics,” Helsinki University Museum.

  18. 18.

    “Hallucinatory and related perceptual experiences are essentially private and subjective . That is, at the instant in time at which the experience occurs, no other person shares the same experience” (Slade and Bentall 16).

  19. 19.

    It is useful to remember how psychological studies on hallucination have only recently come to investigate this phenomenon in itself and not as pertaining exclusively to psychopathology : see Slade and Bentall (1988), Aleman (1998)) and Aleman and Laroi (2008).

  20. 20.

    Although his position as a naïve realist continues to be debated, Wittgenstein is considered a landmark opponent of representational realism . In addition, Allen’s film theory proclaims its debt to Wittgenstein’s argument against the causal theory of perception (see Allen 1999, 2001). For an overview of Wittgenstein’s theory of perception see Good (2006).

  21. 21.

    In earlier works, I have specifically investigated the relation between hallucination, seen as both a theme and a narrative technique, and ineffability in the modernist text (Prudente 2005, 2010).

  22. 22.

    Vygotsky’s theories have long been debated, with both praise and criticism of the relevance given to social interaction in his developmental approach. Recent rediscussion has proposed to reformulate Vygotsky’s “segregational” theory (language seen as a self-contained and stable system) in the form of a more “integrational” view (Jones 2009). As for narrative theory, Vygotsky’s conception of inner speech has been related to Bakhtin’s dialogism (Emerson 1983).

  23. 23.

    Significantly, in his Language and Thought, Vygotsky largely employs examples from Russian authors (Tolstoy and Dostoevsky ) to show the interplay between internal and external speech.

  24. 24.

    “The effect is the most extreme version of discontinuity in the novel between an apparently empirical world, existing in real space and time (created by infinitesimally painstaking mimesis) and a self-contained ‘elsewhere’ with its own physical rules, just like the screen” (Williams 100).

  25. 25.

    In Slade and Bentall’s “working definition,” hallucination is “[a]ny percept-like experience which (a) occurs in the absence of an appropriate stimulus , (b) has the full force or impact of the corresponding actual (real) perception , and (c) is not amenable to direct and voluntary control by the experiencer” (Slade and Bentall 23). Interestingly, as Liester , drawing on McNichol’s work for a history of the concept, underlines, “the Ancient Greek originally employed a single word, phantasia, to describe both hallucinations and delusions. Later, this was divided into two terms, one involving misperception of an object (illusion), the other describing the hearing or seeing of things that others do not (hallucination)” (Liester 308). This coinciding was still present when the term was first employed in English in 1572 “deriving from the Latin allucinatio (wondering of the mind, idle talk) […] at this time no distinction was made between ‘hallucinations’ and the phenomenon now subsumed by the word ‘illusion’ (derived from Latin illusio meaning mocking, jeering, or bantering)” (Slade and Bentall 7).

  26. 26.

    Not only, as underlined, did phantasmagoria work by concealing its projectors, but also the settings of the screenings (“into the most lugubrious of rooms,” Robertson quoted in Castle 34), the darkness, and, above all, the aerial pictures approaching the viewers represented an innovatively involving experience for spectators, which did not entail separation between themselves and the screen (which was concealed): “The Phantascope could move towards or away from the screen on wheels that rolled smoothly along polished brass rails. Combined with new controls that made adjustments in focus easier, such movement caused the projected image on the screen either to enlarge or decrease in size. Since these movements and adjustments could be done both rapidly and invisibly, and since the spectator was placed in darkness without any visible spatial reference, the rapidly enlarging image appeared to be charging out at the audience (or, if the lantern were rolled backwards, withdrawing)” (Gunning 2004).

  27. 27.

    As underlined by Mannoni , the very etymology of the word “phantasmagoria ” entails exchange between the ghostly figures and the spectator: “From the Greek phantasma, phantom —deriving from phantazo, I produce an illusion; and agoreuo, I speak—as the etymology suggests, a dialogue may take place between the audience and the spectre resurrected by the magic lantern” (Mannoni and Brewster 1996, 390).

Bibliography

  • Aleman, André. On Redefining Hallucination. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 68 (4) (1998): 656–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aleman, André, and Frank Laroi. Hallucinations: The Science of Idiosyncratic Perception. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, Richard. Projecting Illusion: Film Spectatorship and the Impression of Reality. Cambridge Studies in Film. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Looking at Motion Pictures. In Film Theory and Philosophy, ed. Richard Allen and Murray Smith, 76–94. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Cognitive Film Theory. In Wittgenstein, Theory and the Arts, ed. Richard Allen and Malcolm Turvey, 177–211. London: Routledge, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banfield, Ann. Unspeakable Sentences: Narration and Representation in the Language of Fiction. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bénéjam, Valérie. The Re-Processing of Trash in Ulysses: Re-Cycling and Post-Creation. Hypermedia Joyce Studies 5 (1) (2004). Web.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Walter. The Arcades Project. Ed. Rolf Tiedemann. Trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin. New York: Belknap Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, Laurence. Epistemological Problems of Perception. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/perception-episprob/.

  • Bordwell, David, and Noël Carroll. Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bordwell, David. Making Meaning: Inference and Rhetoric in the Interpretation of Cinema. Harvard Film Studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewster, David. Letters on Natural Magic Addressed to Sir Walter Scott. London: Chatto & Windus, 1843.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, Austin. ‘Roll Away the Reel World, the Reel World’: ‘Circe’ and Cinema. In Coping with Joyce, Essays from the Copenhagen Symposium, ed. Morris Beja and Shari Benstock, 145–157. Columbus: Ohio State University, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Noël. Mystifying Movies: Fads & Fallacies in Contemporary Film Theory. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castle, Terry. Phantasmagoria: Spectral Technology and the Metaphorics of Modern Reverie. Critical Inquiry 15 (1) (1988): 26–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, Stanley. The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Changeux, Jean-Pierre, and Paul Ricœur. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue About Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohn, Dorrit. Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for Presenting Consciousness in Fiction. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, Gregory. Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995a.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Unreliability Refigured: Narrative in Literature and Film. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1) (Winter 1995b): 19–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Narration, Imitation, and Point of View. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature, ed. Garry L. Hagberg and Walter Jost, 331–350. Oxford: Blackwell, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagrada, Elena. The Diegetic Look: Pragmatics of the Point-of-View Shot. IRIS 7 (1986). Web.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. La rappresentazione dello sguardo nel cinema delle origini in Europa: nascita della soggettiva. Bologna: CLUEB, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. Capitalism and Schizophrenia: A Thousand Plateaus. Trans. Brian Massumi. London: Continuum Books, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiBattista, Maria. The Ghost Walks: Joyce and the Spectres of Silent Cinema. In Roll Away the Reel World, James Joyce and Cinema, ed. John McCourt, 57–69. Cork: Cork University Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsch, Fabian. The Unity of Hallucinations. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9 (1) (2010): 171–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Experience and Introspection. In Hallucination: Philosophy and Psychology, ed. Fiona Macpherson and Dimitris Platchias, 175–220. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellmann, Richard. Ulysses on the Liffey. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emerson, Caryl. The Outer Word and Inner Speech: Bakhtin, Vygotsky, and the Internalization of Language. Critical Inquiry 10 (2) (Dec. 1983): 245–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernyhough, Charles. Alien Voices and Inner Dialogue: Towards a Developmental Account of Auditory Verbal Hallucination. New Ideas in Psychology 22 (2004): 49–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernyhough, Charles, and Simon McCarthy-Jones. Thinking Aloud about Mental Voices. In Hallucination, ed. Fiona Macpherson and D. Platchias, 87–105. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrer, Daniel. Circe, Regret and Regression. In Post-Structuralist Joyce: Essays from the French, ed. Derek Attridge and Daniel Ferrer, 127–145. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Virginia Woolf and the Madness of Language. London and New York: Routledge, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flynn, Catherine. ‘Circe’ and Surrealism: Joyce and the Avant-Garde. Journal of Modern Literature 34 (2) (2011): 121–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaudreault, André. Ce que je vois de mon ciné: la représentation du regard dans le cinéma des premiers temps. Paris: Méridiens Klincksieck, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, Andrew. Introduction to Reading Joyce’s “Circe”. Ed. Andrew Gibson. European Joyce Studies 3. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Stuart. James Joyce’s Ulysses: A Study. London: Faber & Faber, 1930.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, Justine. Wittgenstein and the Theory of Perception. London: Continuum Books, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. The Causal Theory of Perception, part I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 121 (1961): 121–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunning, Tom. Illusions Past and Future: The Phantasmagoria and Its Specters, programmatic key text for the First International Conference on the histories of Art, Science and Technologies, 2004. http://www.mediaarthistory.org/refresh/Programmatic%20key%20texts/pdfs/Gunning.pdf.

  • Haddock, Adrian, and Fiona Macpherson. Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampson, R. G. ‘Toft’s Cumbersome Whirligig’: Hallucination, Theatricality and Mnemotechnic in V.A. 19 and the First Edition Text of ‘Circe.’ In Reading Joyce’s “Circe, ed. Andrew Gibson, 143–179. European Joyce Studies 3. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanaway, Cleo. See Ourselves as Others See Us: Cinematic Seeing and Being in Ulysses. In Roll Away the Reel World, James Joyce and Cinema, ed. John McCourt, 122–136. Cork: Cork University Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hernadi, Paul. Why Is Literature: A Coevolutionary Perspective on Imaginative Worldmaking. Poetics Today 23 (1) (2002): 22–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, John. The Causal Theory of Perception. Philosophical Quarterly 42 (168) (1992): 277–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter E. From ‘External Speech’ to ‘Inner Speech’ in Vygotsky: A Critical Appraisal and Fresh Perspectives. Language & Communication 29 (2009): 166–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenner, Hugh. Circe. In James Joyce’s Ulysses: Critical Essays, ed. Clive Hart and David Hayman, 341–362. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, Udaya. The Joycean Labyrinth: Repetition, Time and Tradition in “Ulysses.” Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liester, Mitchell B. Toward a New Definition of Hallucination. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 68 (2) (1998): 305–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, P., and Charles Fernyhough, eds. Lev Vygotsky: Critical Assessments. London: Routledge, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Jonathan. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannoni, Laurent, and Ben Brewster. The Phantasmagoria. Film History 8 (4) (1996): 390–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannoni, Laurent, and Richard Crangle. The Great Art of Light and Shadow: Archaeology of the Cinema. Exeter: University of Exeter Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marengo Vaglio, Carla. Cinematic Joyce. Mediterranean Joyce. In Joyce in Trieste, ed. Sebastian Knowles, Geert Lernout and John McCourt, 223–240. Gainesville: University of Florida Press, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. The Limits of Self-Awareness. Philosophical Studies 120 (2004): 37–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNichol, R. W. Hallucination. In International Encyclopedia of Psychiatry, Psychology, Psychoanalysis and Neurology, ed. B. B. Wolman, vol. 5, 310–313. New York: von Nostrand Reinhold, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, Fiona, and Adrian Haddock, eds. Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, Fiona, and Dimitris Platchias, eds. Hallucination: Philosophy and Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, Max. La fantasmagorie: essai sur l’optique fantastique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshima, Yukio. Recycling in ‘Circe’ in Ulysses: How Are the Techniques of Other Episodes Applied Here? Journal of the Tokyo University of Marine Science and Technology 1 (2005): 47–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prudente, Teresa. ‘By Dot and Dash System’: Punctuation and the Void in ‘Ithaca’. In Doubtful Points: Joyce and Punctuation, ed. Elizabeth M. Bonapfel and Tim Conley, 109–127. European Joyce Studies 23. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Gazing and Unseeing: Phantasmagoria and Perception in ‘Circe’. In James Joyce: Whence, Whither and How. Studies in Honour of Carla Vaglio, ed. Giuseppina Cortese, Giuliana Ferreccio, Maria Teresa Giaveri, and Teresa Prudente, 433–450. Alessandria: Edizioni dell’Orso, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Orlando: The Mind as Phantasmagoria. The Virginia Woolf Miscellany 67 (Spring/Summer 2005): 13–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. To Write Is Always to Rave A Little: the Hallucinatory Point of View in Elizabeth Bowen’s and Virginia Woolf’s Writing. Consciousness, Literature and the Arts 11 (2) (2010). Web.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riquelme, John Paul. Teller and Tale in Joyce’s Fiction: Oscillating Perspectives. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sicker, Philip. Mirages in the Lampglow: Joyce’s ‘Circe’ and Méliès’ Dream Cinema. In Roll Away the Reel World, James Joyce and Cinema, ed. John McCourt, 69–86. Cork: Cork University Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slade Peter, D., and Richard P. Bentall. Sensory Deception: A Scientific Analysis of Hallucination. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, Lev S. Thought and Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. The Genetic Roots of Thinking and Speech (1929). In The Collected Works of L. Vygotsky, ed. Robert W. Rieber and Aaron S. Carton, vol. 1, 101–121. New York: Plenum Press, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wales, Katie. ‘Bloom Passes Through Several Walls’: The Stage Directions in ‘Circe.’ In Reading Joyce’s “Circe, ed. Andrew Gibson, 241–277. European Joyce Studies 3, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Kendall L. Mimesis As Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Keith. Ulysses in Toontown: ‘Vision Animated to Bursting Point’ in Joyce’s ‘Circe’. In Literature and Visual Technologies: Writing After Cinema, ed. J. Murphet, 96–121. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Prudente, T. (2018). Hallucination and the Text: “Circe” Between Narrative, Epistemology, and Neurosciences. In: Belluc, S., Bénéjam, V. (eds) Cognitive Joyce. Cognitive Studies in Literature and Performance. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-71994-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics