Skip to main content

Frege on Dichtung and Elucidation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Essays on Frege

Part of the book series: Nordic Wittgenstein Studies ((NRWS,volume 3))

  • 309 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper, I identify an assumption at play in anti-semantic interpretative approaches to Frege: the notion that translatability to Frege’s concept script functions as a criterion for deciding whether a thought is expressed in a sentence or utterance. I question the viability of this assumption by pointing to Frege’s accounts of the aim and character of his logical language and scientific discourse more generally, and by looking at his remarks on poetic forms of language, literature and fiction (Dichtung). Since it seems clear that the sentences used in poetic and literary forms of language that Frege discusses, have Sinn and are possible to understand, in his view, I argue that the translatability criterion for thoughts is flawed. A discussion of Frege’s appeal to an approach of willingness to understand in a reader, and the relation between Frege’s use of elucidatory discourse and his conception of Dichtung is central to my exposition in this paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. here e.g. von Wright (1994), Quine (1981), and Glock (2008).

  2. 2.

    Gabriel and Polimenov (2012).

  3. 3.

    Frege (1879, V).

  4. 4.

    Cf. here Wittgenstein (2001, §§ 90, 110, 593).

  5. 5.

    “If our language were logically more perfect, we would perhaps have no further need of logic, or we might read it off from the language. But we are far from being in such a position. Work in logic just is, to a large extent, a struggle with the logical defects of language, and yet language remains for us an indispensable tool. Only after our logical work has been completed shall we possess a more perfect instrument ” (Frege 1969/1979, 272/ 252).

  6. 6.

    Cf. Frege (1892a/1997, 27–29/153).

  7. 7.

    “Since mutual cooperation in a science is impossible without mutual understanding of the investigators, we must have confidence that such an understanding can be reached through elucidations [Erläuterungen], although theoretically, the contrary is not excluded” (Frege 1906/1984, 301/301).

  8. 8.

    Cf. Weiner’s discussion in “Frege’s Unmetaphysical Story about Natural Language and Truth” (Weiner, forthcoming).

  9. 9.

    See Frege (1884, §§ 26–27) where he ends a discussion about objectivity with these words: “Der Grund der Objectivität kann ja nicht in dem Sinneseindrucke liegen, der als Affection unserer Seele ganz subjectiv ist, sondern, soweit ich sehe, nur in der Vernunft . Es wäre wunderbar, wenn die aller exacteste Wissenschaft sich auf die noch zu unsicher tastende Psychologie stützen sollte.” See also Frege (1884, § 105), especially the second footnote to this section, and Frege (1969/1979, 133/122).

  10. 10.

    Cf. Frege’s discussions of the relation between reason (Vernunft ) and science in Frege (1882, 55), and Frege (1918, 74) where he suggests that “[d]em Fassen der Gedanken muß ein besonderes geistiges Vermögen, die Denkkraft, entsprechen” and goes on to discuss the relation between thinking, truth and the foundation of science. See also Frege (1969/1979, 288/269).

  11. 11.

    The three principles introduced in The Foundations of Arithmetic should perhaps be added to this list (Frege 1884, X).

  12. 12.

    Cf. Frege (1969/1979, 139/128): “[The] task we assign to logic is only that of saying what holds with the utmost generality for all thinking, whatever its subject matter.”

  13. 13.

    In several passages, Frege points out to a reader that his words must not be taken literally as this will lead to misunderstandings (e.g. Frege 1892b/1997, 205/193).

  14. 14.

    van Heijenoort (1967b) , Goldfarb (1979) .

  15. 15.

    At this point, she draws a parallel to Kant’s words about logic: “Logic must teach us the correct use of the understanding , i.e. that in which it is in agreement with itself ” (Kant 1974, 16). See also Frege (1884, § 105).

  16. 16.

    Cf. also Alnes (1998, 50) and Goldfarb (1997, 62) .

  17. 17.

    Cf. e.g. Frege (1906/1984, 301–302/301).

  18. 18.

    This example connects with what we saw in the quotation from the Preface to the Begriffsschrift , where Frege suggests that it is a task of philosophy to “break the domination of words over the human spirit by laying bare illusions that through the use of language often almost unavoidably arise”. Here, Frege points at a potentially liberating and therapeutic aim that the philosopher might reach that corresponds with the overall picture of similarities between Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and Frege’s work that is presented in the work of Conant and Diamond .

  19. 19.

    Cf. also Frege (1969/1979, 201/185).

  20. 20.

    Cf. Frege (1969/1979, 161/149).

  21. 21.

    It has been suggested by Gabriel that Frege’s avoidance of “metaphor” when speaking of his use of figurative language is connected with a wish to put a distance between his work and the work of a poet. It is reasonable to conceive of Frege’s choice of words in this case from the perspective of his struggle against psychologism . See Gabriel (1991, 679), and my discussion below.

  22. 22.

    Cf. Frege’s discussion in the essay “My Basic Logical Insights” (Frege 1969/1979, 271–272/251–252), and his discussion of assertoric force in connection with a distinction between a “Hilfssprache” and a “Darlegungssprache” (1969/1979, 281/260).

  23. 23.

    Cf. Frege (1884, § 88), Frege (1969/1979, 37/33), Gabriel (1991, 71–79) , Ricketts (1985) , Goldfarb (1979, 353) , and Weiner (2001) .

  24. 24.

    Cf. Frege (1969/1979, 142/130).

  25. 25.

    The relation between Sinn and Bedeutung in cases like this (in Dichtung) is not as in scientific discourse, but unscientific.

  26. 26.

    One might compare Frege’s appeal in these cases to Kant’s notion of sensus communis, and his distinction between sensus communis aestheticus and sensus communis logicus in the Third Critique, § 40. Cf. also Cavell’s implicit reference to this Kantian notion in his famous essay “Aesthetic Problems of Modern Philosophy ” (Cavell 2002, 73–96).

  27. 27.

    Cf. Ishiguro (1969, 32–33) on Wittgenstein’s conception of ‘elucidation ’ in the Tractatus.

  28. 28.

    Cf. Frege (1892b/1997, 195, 205/184, 193), (1893, 4), (1969/1979, 254/235).

  29. 29.

    Cf. here Frege (1918/1997, 60–61/327–328).

  30. 30.

    I would like to thank Jan Harald Alnes for helpful suggestions and very valuable comments to drafts for this paper. I’m also grateful for comments and suggestions from participants at the workshop “Frege zwischen Dichtung und Wissenschaft” in Bergen, and from participants of the research seminars at Uppsala University, the University of Oslo and Tampere University. In particular, I would like to thank Joan Weiner , Juliet Floyd , Leila Haaparanta, Mirja Hartimo and Sharon Rider. Work on this paper was financed by the Research Council of Norway.

References

  • Alnes, J. H. (1998). Frege on logic and logicism. Oslo: Acta Humaniora.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. (2002). Must we mean what we say?: A book of essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. (2000). Elucidation and nonsense in Frege and early Wittgenstein. In A. Crary & R. Read (Eds.), The new Wittgenstein (pp. 174–217). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (1991). The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy and the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floyd, J. (1998). Frege, semantics, and the double definition stroke. In A. Biletzki & A. Matar (Eds.), The story of analytic philosophy: Plot and heroes (pp. 141–166). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle: Louis Nebert.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1882). Ueber die wissenschaftliche Berechtigung einer Begriffsschrift. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 81, 48–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). Grundlagen der Arithmetik: Eine-logisch mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl. Breslau: Verlag von W. Koebner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1891). Function und Begriff: Vortrag, gehalten in der Sitzung vom 9. Januar 1891 der Jenaischen Gesellschaft für Medizin und Naturwissenschaft. Jena: Hermann Pohle. English edition: Frege, G. (1997). Function and concept. In G. Frege, The Frege reader (pp. 130–148). M. Beaney (Ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892a). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50. English edition: Frege, G. (1997). On Sinn and Bedeutung. In G. Frege, The Frege reader (pp. 151–172). M. Beaney (Ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892b). Über Begriff und Gegenstand. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 16, 192–205. English edition: Frege, G. (1997). On concept and object. In G. Frege, The Frege reader (pp. 181–193). M. Beaney (Ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1893/2013). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik: Begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet, I. Band. Jena: Verlag von Hermann Pohle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1906). Über die Grundlagen der Geometrie [second series]. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, 15, 293–309 (Part I), 377–403 (Part II), 423–430 (Part III). English edition: Frege, G. (1984). On the foundations of geometry: Second series. In G. Frege, Collected papers (pp. 293–340). B. McGuinness (Ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1918). Der Gedanke: Eine logische Untersuchung. Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus, I, 58–77. English edition: Frege, G. (1997). Thought. In G. Frege, The Frege reader (pp. 325–345). M. Beaney (Ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1919). Die Verneinung: Eine Logische Untersuchung. Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus, I, 2, 143–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1969). Nachgelassene Schriften. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, &, F. Kaulbach (Eds.). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag. English edition: Frege, G. (1979). Posthumous writings. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, & F. Kaulback (Eds.), P. Long, & R. White (Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. G. Gabriel, H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, C. Thiel, & A. Veraart (Eds.), H. Kaal (Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1997). The Frege reader. M. Beaney (Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1992). Kant and the exact sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, G. (1984). Fregean connection: Bedeutung, value and truth-value. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34(136), 374–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, G. (1991). Zwischen Logik und Literatur: Erkenntnisformen von Dichtung, Philosophie und Wissenschaft. Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, G., & Polimenov, T. (2012). Analytical philosophy and its forgetfulness of the Continent: Gottfried Gabriel in conversation with Todor Polimenov. Nordic Wittgenstein Review, 1(2012), 155–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (2008). What is analytic philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldfarb, W. (1979). Logic in the twenties: The nature of the quantifier. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47, 351–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldfarb, W. (1997). Metaphysics and nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit. Journal of Philosophical Research, 22, 57–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishiguro, H. (1969). Use and reference of names. In P. Winch (Ed.), Studies in the philosophy of Wittgenstein (pp. 20–50). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1974). Logic. L. Hartman & W. Schwartz (Trans.). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1981). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricketts, T. (1985). Frege, the Tractatus, and the logocentric predicament. Noûs, 9, 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricketts, T. (1996). Logic and truth in Frege: I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 70, 121–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J. (Ed.). (1967a). From Frege to Gödel. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J. (1967b). Logic as language and logic as calculus. Synthese, 17, 324–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1994). Analytische Philosophie: Eine historisch-kritische Betrachtung. In G. Meggle & U. Wessels (Eds.), Analyomen 1, proceedings of the 1st conference ‘Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy’ (pp. 3–30). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, J. (1990). Frege in perspective. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, J. (2001). Theory and elucidation: The end of the age of innocence. In J. Floyd & S. Shieh (Eds.), Future pasts: The analytic tradition in twentieth century philosophy (pp. 43–66). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, J. (forthcoming). Frege’s unmetaphysical story about natural language and truth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2001). Philosophical investigations/Philosophische Untersuchungen (3rd ed.). G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gisela Bengtsson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bengtsson, G. (2018). Frege on Dichtung and Elucidation. In: Bengtsson, G., Säätelä, S., Pichler, A. (eds) New Essays on Frege. Nordic Wittgenstein Studies, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-71186-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics