Skip to main content

What is a Computer Simulation and What does this Mean for Simulation Validation?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Computer Simulation Validation

Part of the book series: Simulation Foundations, Methods and Applications ((SFMA))

  • 2657 Accesses

Abstract

Many questions about the fundamentals of some area take the form “What is …?” It does not come as a surprise then that, at the dawn of Western philosophy, Socrates asked the questions of what piety, courage, and justice are. Nor is it a wonder that the philosophical preoccupation with computer simulations centered, among other things, about the question of what computer simulations are. Very often, this question has been answered by stating that computer simulation is a species of a well-known method, e.g., experimentation. Other answers claim at least a close relationship between computer simulation and another method. In any case, correct answers to the question of what a computer simulation is should help us to better understand what validation of simulations is. The aim of this chapter is to discuss the most important proposals to understand computer simulation in terms of another method and to trace consequences for validation. Although it has sometimes been claimed that computer simulations are experiments, there are strong reasons to reject this view. A more appropriate proposal is to say that computer simulations often model experiments. This implies that the simulation scientists should to some extent imitate the validation of an experiment. But the validation of computer simulations turns out to be more comprehensive. Computer simulations have also been conceptualized as thought experiments or close cousins of the latter. This seems true, but not very telling since thought experiments are not a standard method and since it is controversial how they contribute to our acquisition of knowledge. I thus consider a specific view on thought experiments to make some progress on understanding simulations and their validation. There is finally a close connection between computer simulation and modeling, and it can be shown that the validation of a computer simulation is the validation of a specific model, which may either be thought to be mathematical or fictional.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    If somebody claims that computer simulations are, say, experiments, then what is claimed may either be regarded as essential of computer simulation (such that it should be included in its definition), or it may be supposed to be a contingent claim about computer simulations. I take it that the views under consideration are meant to capture essential properties of simulations, but this is not necessary for my argument.

  2. 2.

    The distinction goes back to Campbell 1957 (see Winsberg 2009, p. 579 following Parker). See also Campbell and Stanley (1963, p. 5) and Cook and Campbell (1979, p. 37). It was originally restricted to experiments in social science that aim at causal claims.

  3. 3.

    In a computer simulation, the computer hardware may of course be subject to influences not controlled for. But this is typically excluded by activities of verification, see below.

  4. 4.

    Our focus in this section is exclusively on scientific thought experiments. Philosophers too engage in thought experimentation, but it is at least arguable that thought experimentation in philosophy and the sciences function quite differently.

  5. 5.

    They also include experiments under this description, but in the last section, we have already noted crucial differences between experiment and simulation.

  6. 6.

    There is no need here to draw on Nersessian’s view that thought experimenting involves mental modeling since we’ll examine simulations and models in due course in Sect. 37.4.

  7. 7.

    This mark is not sufficient for a good thought experiment because even a valid argument can arrive at a wrong conclusion if some premise is false. But this complication does not matter for our argument.

  8. 8.

    Baumberger et al. (2017) have recently proposed to frame validationcs using notions from argumentation theory. But this conceptualization of validationcs is independent of the argument view.

  9. 9.

    We might also have provided a slightly different argument to represent a run of a computer simulation program: The idea would be that the premises state the computational model. Now the latter is defined such that results of the simulations are exact solutions to the computational model. So it is not an issue anymore to check that the argument is deductive. But the work of validation is only shifted to the examination of the premises. For instance, if we want to make a case that the computational model is sufficiently accurate by drawing on prior commitments to theory, we must show that the theory is likely sufficiently accurate and that it is appropriately reflected in the computational model.

References

  • Baumberger, C., Knutti, R., & Hirsch Hadorn, G. (2017). Building confidence in climate model projections: An analysis of inferences from fit. WIREs Climate Change, 8(3), e454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C. (2012). How can computer simulations produce new knowledge? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 395–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C. (2014). Are we sims? How computer simulations represent and what this means for the simulation argument. The Monist, 97(3), 399–417, (special issue edited by P. Humphreys).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, C. (2018). Are computer simulations experiments? And if not, how are they related to each other? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(2), 171–204. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-017-0181-5.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Beeler, J. R. (1983). Radiation effects computer experiments. Amsterdam etc: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1991). The laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (2004). Peeking into Plato’s haeven. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1126 –1138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R., & Fehige, Y. (2017). Thought experiments. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/thought-experiment/.

  • Campbell, D. T. (1957). Factors relevant to the validity of experiments in social settings. Psychological Bulletin, 54(4), 297–312. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0040950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T., & Stanley, J. C. (1963). Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for research. In N. L. Gale (Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching (pp. 88ff). Chicago, IL: Rand McNally.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (1979). Quasi-experimentation: Design & analysis issues for field settings. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1961). Relativity, the special and the general theory. A Popular Exposition. London: Methuen (1920, here quoted after edition published by Crown, New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • El Skaf, R., & Imbert, C. (2013). Unfolding in the empirical sciences: experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese, 190(16), 3451–3474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A., & Perovic, S. (2016). Experiment in physics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/physics-experiment/.

  • Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2017). Models in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/models-science/.

  • Frigg, R. P., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169, 593–613.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2004). Thought experiments rethought and reperceived. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1152–1163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, A. (2015). Definitions. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/definitions/.

  • Hartmann, S. (1996). The World as a process: Simulations in the natural and social sciences. In R. Hegselmann et al. (Eds.), Modelling and simulation in the social sciences from the philosophy of science point of view, Theory and decision library (pp. 77-100). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger, M. (2005). Experimentation and instrumentation. In D. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy. Appendix (pp. 12–20). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. G. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 64, S325–S336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves: Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169, 615–626.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Imbert, C. (2017). Computer simulations and computational models in science. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (Vol. 34, pp. 733–779). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koblick, D. C. (1959). An enzymatic ion exchange model for active sodium transport. The Journal of General Physiology, 42(3), 635–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, J. (2011). Epistemologie der Iteration. Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 59(1), 131–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, J., Wang, M., Chen, S., & Robbins, M. O. (2010). Molecular simulations of electroosmotic flows in rough nanochannels. Journal of Computational Physics, 229(20), 7834–7847.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M., & Bhimji, W. (2015). Computer simulations and experiments: The case of the Higgs boson. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 512, 71–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2009). Models, measurement and computer simulation: The changing face of experimentation. Philosophical Studies, 143, 33–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality: Models, mathematics, and simulations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naumova, E. N., Gorski, J., & Naumov, Y. N. (2008). Simulation studies for a multistage dynamic process of immune memory response to influenza: Experiment in silico. Annales Zoologici Fennici, 45, 369–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (1992). In the Theoretician’s laboratory: Thought experimenting as mental modeling. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. 1992, pp. 291–301).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, Nancy J. (2007). Thought experimenting as mental modeling. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 125–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, P., & Shaw, S. (2014). Validity in educational and psychological assessment. London: SAGE Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (1996). Are thought experiments just what you thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 333–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2004a). On Thought experiments: Is there more to the argument?. In Proceedings of the 2002 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Philosophy of Science (Vol. 71, pp. 1139–1151).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2004b). Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science. Blackwell: Oxford, pp. 44–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. S. (2008). Franklin, Holmes, and the epistemology of computer simulation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(2), 165–183.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. (2009). Does matter really matter? Computer Simulations, Experiments, and Materiality, Synthese, 169, 483–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (2009). The philosophy of scientific experimentation: A review. Automatic Experimentation 1. Open access. http://www.aejournal.net/content/1/1/2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saam, N. J. S. (2017). What is a computer simulation? A Review of a Passionate Debate, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 293–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, S. et al. (1979). Terminology for Model Credibility, Simulation, 32, 103–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verlet, L. (1967). Computer “experiments” on classical fluids. I. Thermodynamical properties of Lennard-Jones molecules. Physical Review, 159(1), 98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 58, 207–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2001). Simulations, models, and theories: Complex physical systems and their representations. In Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science (Vol. 68, pp. 442–454).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2003). Simulated experiments: Methodology for a virtual world. Philosophy of Science, 70, 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2009). A tale of two methods. Synthese, 169, 483–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m grateful to Julie Jebeile and Nicole J. Saam for useful comments and criticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claus Beisbart .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Beisbart, C. (2019). What is a Computer Simulation and What does this Mean for Simulation Validation?. In: Beisbart, C., Saam, N. (eds) Computer Simulation Validation. Simulation Foundations, Methods and Applications. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-70766-2_37

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-70766-2_37

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-70765-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-70766-2

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics