Skip to main content

Four Methods of Empirical Inquiry in the Aftermath of Newton’s Challenge

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
What Does it Mean to be an Empiricist?

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 331))

Abstract

In this paper I distinguish four methods of empirical inquiry in eighteenth century natural philosophy. In particular, I distinguish among what I call, (i) the mathematical-experimental method; (ii) the method of experimental series; (iii) the method of inspecting ideas; (iv) the method of natural history. While such a list is not exhaustive of the methods of inquiry available, even so, focusing on these four methods will help in diagnosing a set of debates within what has come to be known as ‘empiricism’; throughout the eighteenth century there was a methodological reaction against the hegemonic aspirations of mathematical natural philosophy associated with the authority of Newton.

In particular, I argue that the methods of inspecting ideas and natural history remained attractive to ‘empiricist’ thinkers with reservations about aspects of Newtonianism. Moreover, I show that the language of experimentalism meant different things to researchers with different attitudes toward Newton’s legacy. In order to illustrate and make more precise these claims, I embed my taxonomic treatment of the four methods within a narrative in which I primarily focus on Colin Maclaurin, Isaac Newton, David Hume, and Georges-Louis Leclerc de Buffon.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Charles Wolfe distinguishes usefully among three kinds of eighteenth century empiricism: (1). “A ‘Royal Society’, experimentalist empiricism, which may be the context in which an actual ‘philosophy of experiment’ emerges” (Boyle, Bacon); (2). “a moral/practical empiricism (Locke and Hume), in which themes such as anti-innatism … are in fact not epistemological, that is, not primarily reducible to concerns about the nature of knowledge or the cognitive states of the knower, but are rather motivated by embedded concerns such as anti-authoritarianism … and the desire to articulate a notion of toleration”; (3). “A medically motivated, ‘embodied’ empiricism, as found in such diverse figures as William Harvey …, Pierre Gassendi, Thomas Sydenham; in a different sense, La Mettrie, especially … within the tradition or trend of ‘medical Epicureanism’, as in Gassendi-Lamy-La Mettrie; and the Montpellier vitalists” (Wolfe 2010a, 335). My approach is motivated by different historiographical concerns than that that of Wolfe, but I am greatly indebted to his paper and to conversation with him over Mandeville, in particular.

  2. 2.

    Recent trends in historiography have turned against deploying the empiricist/rationalist distinction in studying seventeenth and eighteenth philosophy. In this paper the distinction will do no serious philosophical work.

  3. 3.

    See Petty (1690).

  4. 4.

    English (1999) and Tarbuck (2011).

  5. 5.

    Schliesser (2011) and Eric Schliesser (2012). See also Grabiner (2004).

  6. 6.

    Maclaurin (1748), 77.

  7. 7.

    Anstey (2005). For a methodological critique of Anstey, see the editors’ introduction to Biener and Schliesser (2014), 1–15.

  8. 8.

    Maclaurin (1748), 225.

  9. 9.

    Maclaurin (1748), 98–99.

  10. 10.

    During a lively facebook discussion (18 september 2012) Aaron Garrett and Dario Perinitti called my attention to Maclaurin’s correspondence with Crousaz, who also maintained a distinction between impressions and ideas. See Shank (2008), 160. But I see no reason to think that in this context Maclaurin has Crousaz in mind.

  11. 11.

    See Maclaurin (1748), 103. The inward substratum is introduced in the context of discussion a hypothetical objection, and it is not entirely clear if Maclaurin accepts a substratum view. But he exhibits familiarity with Lockean views. I thank Peter Millican for discussion.

  12. 12.

    Maclaurin (1748), 98.

  13. 13.

    Maclaurin (1748), 100. Here there may be Lockean influence. But this, too, is not decisive—for on the very next page he is explicitly criticizing Berkeley; in his Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Berkeley has a tendency to conflate Locke and Newton on time (Berkeley 1734, § 98–111, 118–31).

  14. 14.

    Maclaurin (1748), 224.

  15. 15.

    Maclaurin (1748), 90–1.

  16. 16.

    Maclaurin (1748), 221; see also 8; 288. For Maclaurin such analysis always comes before synthesis, which delivers a “system” (Maclaurin 1748, 91).

  17. 17.

    Maclaurin (1748), 54.

  18. 18.

    ’s Gravesande (1747), preface to third edition, xiv–xv. See also Ducheyne 2014a & b.

  19. 19.

    While no one would mistake Huygens for a Newtonian, Wolff is an eclectic, who mixes all kinds of elements in his mathematical philosophy. To quote from the summary of a very useful (Dutch, alas) treatment, “Wolff’s scientific position turns out to be neither Cartesian, nor Newtonian” (Hakfoort 1982, 38).

  20. 20.

    See, especially, Smith (2001) for very critical comments. For a very good treatment of ’s Gravesande’s methodological eclecticism: Ducheyne (2014a, b, and 2015).

  21. 21.

    In recent scholarship, George E. Smith has done most to illuminate the nature of this enterprise. See for a nice introduction, Smith (2008).

  22. 22.

    Maclaurin (1748), 221.

  23. 23.

    Ibid.

  24. 24.

    Berkeley (1951).

  25. 25.

    This objection may be discerned in Spinoza, but that need not be explored here.

  26. 26.

    For recent work see Harper (2012).

  27. 27.

    Newton (1999), 403–4 & 406.

  28. 28.

    It turns out that through the three editions of the Principia, Newton shifted from a so-called geometric conception of mass (cf. “volume” in the definition) to a more dynamic conception. See, especially Biener and Smeenk (2012).

  29. 29.

    Newton 1999, 411. On Newtonian abstraction, Domski (2012), 389–413.

  30. 30.

    For nice recent treatment of the methodological similarities and differences between Principia and Optics, see Ducheyne (2012).

  31. 31.

    Recall Maclaurin (1748, 221). See also Demeter (2012).

  32. 32.

    Cohen (1956).

  33. 33.

    ’s Gravesande (1747), xv: describing Newton’s Opticks.

  34. 34.

    There has been some modest, recognition of the significance of serial experimentation in the literature, especially in the work of Steinle. See: Steinle (2003) and Jalobeanu (2016). I thank Laura Georgescu for supplying me with these references.

  35. 35.

    Buffon and Lyon (1976), 177. For more on this strain in Buffon’s writings see Reill (2005).

  36. 36.

    See Feingold (2001). For recent criticism of Feingold, see Anstey (2005). Of course, the use of mathematics in natural philosophy was also traced back to Bacon’s writings; see Maclaurin (1748), who treats Bacon both as “founder of experimental philosophy” (59) as well as the source of the proper use of mathematical methods in natural philosophy (36). For recent scholarship on the role of Bacon in promoting mathematical natural philosophy, see Pastorino (2011), Jalobeanu (2013, and 2014).

  37. 37.

    Buffon and Lyon (1976), 176.

  38. 38.

    Newton (1999), Scholium to the definitions, 411.

  39. 39.

    I am making no claim about direct influence. Having said that, there are, in fact, passages in Buffon that read very Humean: “when, after having determined the facts through repeated observations, when, after having established new truths through precise experiments, we wish to search out the reasons for these same occurrences, the causes of these effects, we find ourselves suddenly baffled, reduced to trying to deduce effects from more general effects, and obliged to admit that causes are always will be known to us, because our senses … can give us ideas only of effects and never of causes. Thus we must be content to call cause a general effect, and must forego hope of knowing anything beyond that. These general effects are for us the true laws of nature.” (Buffon and Lyon 1976, 175).

  40. 40.

    The following paragraphs draw on joint work with Yoram Hazony (Hazony and Schliesser 2016).

  41. 41.

    The most influential twentieth century argument is Smith (1941).

  42. 42.

    I quote the treatise by paragraph number as supplied by Hume (2004); here Hume (2004), § 1.2.4.17. See also www.Davidhume.org

  43. 43.

    “[T]he whole subject of mechanics is distinguished from geometry by the attribution of exactness to geometry and of anything less than exactness to mechanics. Yet the errors do not come from the art, but from those who practice the art. Anyone who works with less exactness is a more imperfect mechanic, and if anyone could work with the greatest exactness, he would be the most perfect mechanic of all.” (Newton 1999, 381–2).

  44. 44.

    Hume (2004), § 1.2.4.17. See also idem § 1.4.1.1–2. Furthermore, see Meeker (2007).

  45. 45.

    Hume (2004), § 1.2.4.29–31.

  46. 46.

    For a book-length treatment see Gallie (1989).

  47. 47.

    Hume (2004), § 1.2.2.1.

  48. 48.

    Hume (2004), § 1.3.2.4; see also § 1.3.6.16.

  49. 49.

    The best treatment is Garrett (1997), chapter 2.

  50. 50.

    Hume (2004), n12, SBN 638–639.

  51. 51.

    As Andrew Janiak writes, “5. Clarke seems to endorse an instrumentalist interpretation of ‘gravitation’ as Newton discussed it especially in his fifth and final letter to Leibniz: see Clarke 5: sections 110–16, 118–23, and 124–30, in Leibniz (1931, 437, 439–40).”The reference is to Leibniz (1931); see Janiak (2014).

  52. 52.

    I have discussed these issues more at length in Schliesser (2007, 2009, and 2010). See also Rocknak (2012).

  53. 53.

    Hume (2004), introduction, § 7–8, and 10.

  54. 54.

    Boehm (2013).

  55. 55.

    Hume (2004), introduction, § 4.

  56. 56.

    See also Hume (2004), § 1.4.1–6. By focusing on this section, Kevin Meeker has done excellent work on Hume’s skeptical arguments about purported mathematical knowledge (Meeker 2007).

  57. 57.

    I have followed the citations as provided by www.Davidhume.org: Hume (2007) E 4.1, SBN 25.

  58. 58.

    Hume (2007), E 7.4, SBN 62.

  59. 59.

    Hume (2007), E 8.13, SBN 87.

  60. 60.

    Hume (2007), E 8.36, SBN 103.

  61. 61.

    Diderot (1994), 561. Translation taken from Wolfe (2010b), 109.

  62. 62.

    It is, of course, not impossible that this was never meant as a prediction, but more akin to what I have elsewhere labeled “philosophic prophecy”; see Schliesser (2013).

  63. 63.

    For a more thorough account of Buffon, see Hoquet (2010) as well as his paper in this volume.

  64. 64.

    Buffon, “Initial Discourse”, in: Buffon and Lyon (1976), 178.

  65. 65.

    The whole passage is instructive: “The sole means of constructing an instructive and natural system is to put together whatever is similar and to separate those things which differ. If the individual entities resemble each other exactly … such individuals will be of the same species … if, on the contrary, the differences exceed the similarities, such individuals are not even of the same class. This is the systematic order which ought to be followed in arranging the productions of nature.” (Buffon and Lyon 1976, 155).

  66. 66.

    Hurlbutt (1985) and Russell (2008).

Bibliography

Other Primary Literature

  • Berkeley, George. 1734. A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge… (1710). London: Jacob Tonson.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1951. De Motu (1721). In: The works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A.A. Luce and T.E. Jessop. London: Thomas Nelson, vol. 4, 31–52. 1948–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon, Georges-Louis Leclerc de, and John Lyon. 1976. The ‘initial discourse’ to Buffon’s histoire naturelle: The first complete english translation. Journal of the History of Biology 9 (1): 133–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diderot, Denis. 1994. Œuvres, vol. 1: “Philosophie”, ed. L. Versini. Paris: Robert Laffont.

    Google Scholar 

  • ’s Gravesande, Willem Jacob. 1747. The mathematical elements of natural philosophy confirmed by experiments: Or, an introduction to Sir Isaac Newton’s philosophy, Trans. John Theophilus Desaguliers, 3th ed. London: W. Innys.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 2004. A treatise of human nature, ed. David Fate and Mary J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. An enquiry concerning human understanding (1777), ed. by Peter Millican. Oxford: Oxford University Press (digital edition): http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html.

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1931. Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, ed. Carl J. Gerhardt. Leipzig: Alfred Lorentz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, Colin. 1748. An account or Sir Isaac Newton’s philosophical discoveries in four books. London: Patrick Murdoch.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, Isaac. 1999. The Principia, a new. Trans. I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, William. 1690. Political arithmetick. London: Robert Clavel.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Literature

  • Anstey, Peter R. 2005. Experimental versus speculative natural philosophy. In Science of Nature in the seventeenth century: Patterns of change in early modern natural philosophy, ed. Peter R. Anstey and J.A. Schuster The, 215–242. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Biener, Zvi, and Eric Schliesser, eds. 2014. Newton and empiricism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biener, Zvi, and Chris Smeenk. 2012. Cotes’ Queries: Newton’s empiricism and conceptions of matter. In Interpreting Newton, ed. Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser, 105–137. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, Miren. 2013. Hume’s foundational project in the treatise. European Journal of Philosophy 24 (1: March): 55–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, I. Bernard. 1956. Franklin and Newton: An inquiry into speculative Newtonian experimental science and Franklin’s work in electricity as an example thereof. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, Tamás. “Hume’s experimental method.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20.3 (2012): 577–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Domski, Mary. 2012. Newton and proclus: Geometry, imagination, and knowing space. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3): 389–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, Steffen. 2012. The main business of natural philosophy: Isaac Newton’s natural-philosophical methodology. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. ’s Gravesande’s appropriation of Newton’s natural philosophy, part I: Epistemological and theological issues. Centaurus 56 (1): 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • English, John C. 1999. John Hutchinson’s critique of newtonian heterodoxy. Church History 68: 581–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feingold, Mordechai. 2001. Mathematicians and naturalists: Sir Isaac Newton and the Royal Society. In Isaac Newton’s natural philosophy, ed. J.Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen, 77–102. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallie, Roger D. 1989. Thomas Reid and “the way of ideas”. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, Don. 1997. Cognition and commitment in Hume’s philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabiner, Judith V. 2004, December. Newton, Maclaurin, and the authority of mathematics. American Mathematical Monthly 111 (10): 841–852.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hakfoort, Casper. 1982. Christian Wolff Tussen Cartesianen en Newtonianen. Tijdschrift voor de Geschiedenis der Geneeskunde, Natuurwetenschappen, Wiskunde, en Techniek 5 (1): 27–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harper, William L. 2012. Isaac Newton’s scientific method: Turning data into evidence about gravity and cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazony, Yoram, and Eric Schliesser. 2016. Newton and Hume. In The Oxford handbook to David Hume, ed. Paul Russell, 673–707. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoquet, Thierry. 2010. History without time: Buffon’s natural history as a nonmathematical physique. Isis 101 (1): 30–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurlbutt, Robert H. 1985. Hume, Newton, and the design argument. revised ed. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jalobeanu, Dana. 2013. Four idols of Baconian scholarship. Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences 71: 123–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jalobeanu, Dana. “Disciplining Experience: Francis Bacon’s Experimental Series and the Art of Experimenting.” Perspectives on Science 24.3 (2016): 324–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janiak, Andrew. 2014. Newton’s philosophy. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. (Summer 2014 online edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/newton-philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meeker, Kevin. 2007. Hume on knowledge, certainty and probability: Anticipating the disintegration of the analytic/synthetic divide? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88: 226–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pastorino, Cesare. 2011. Weighing experience: Experimental histories and Francis Bacon’s quantitative program. Early Science and Medicine 16 (6): 542–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reill, Peter H. 2005. Vitalizing nature in the Enlightenment. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rocknak, Stefanie. 2012. Imagined causes: Hume’s conception of objects. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Patrick. 2008. The riddle of Hume’s Treatise: Skepticism, naturalism, and irreligion. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, Eric. 2007. Two definitions of ‘cause’, Newton, and the significance of the Humean distinction between natural and philosophical relations. The Journal of Scottish Philosophy 5 (1): 83–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Newton’s challenge to philosophy: A programmatic essay. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1): 101–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Newtonian Refutation of Spinoza: Newton’s challenge and the socratic problem. In Interpreting Newton: Critical essays, ed. Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser, 299–319. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Philosophic prophecy. In Philosophy and its history: Aims and methods in the study of early modern philosophy, ed. Mogens Laerke et al., 209–235. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shank, John Bennett. 2008. The Newton Wars and the beginning of the French enlightenment. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Norman Kemp. 1941. The philosophy of David Hume. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, George E. 2001. Comments on Ernan McMullin’s ‘The impact of Newton’s Principia on the philosophy of science’. Philosophy of Science 68: 327–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Newton’s Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2008/entries/newton-principia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinle, Friedrich. 2003. Experiments in history and philosophy of science. Perspectives on Science 10 (4): 408–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarbuck, Derya Gürses. 2011. John Wesley’s critical engagement with Hutchinsonianism 1730–1780. History of European Ideas 37 (1): 35–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, Charles T. 2010a. Empiricist heresies in early modern medical thought. In The body as object and instrument of knowledge: Embodied empiricism in early modern science, ed. Charles T. Wolfe and O. Gal, 333–344. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Rethinking empiricism and materialism: The revisionist view. Annales Philosophici, University of Oradea’s Annals of Philosophy 1 (1): 101–113.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Schliesser .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Additional information

I thank the editors of this volume, Charles Wolfe as well as a very hostile audience at ESHS in Barcelona for very useful, critical comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Schliesser, E. (2018). Four Methods of Empirical Inquiry in the Aftermath of Newton’s Challenge. In: Bodenmann, S., Rey, AL. (eds) What Does it Mean to be an Empiricist?. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 331. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69860-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics