Skip to main content

Darwinism in the Twentieth Century: Productive Encounters with Saltation, Acquired Characteristics, and Development

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Darwinian Tradition in Context

Abstract

Darwinism is one of several research traditions in evolutionary biology. I identify it, both before and after its unification with genetics, with Darwin’s theory of descent by natural selection from a common ancestor. Other traditions include saltationism/mutationism, Lamarckism, and evolutionary developmentalism (“evo-devo”). I argue that Darwinism’s continued dominance in evolutionary science reflects its proven ability to interact productively with these other traditions, an ability impressed on it by its founder’s example. Evolution by sudden leaps (saltations) is alien to the spirit of Darwinism, but Darwinism advanced its own agenda by incorporating and subverting saltationist themes. Similarly, Lamarckism’s belief in the heritability of acquired characteristics has been discredited, but some of the facts to which it seems congenial reappear in genetic Darwinism as phenotypic plasticity and niche construction. These examples help assess challenges to Darwinism’s hegemony currently arising from the role of regulatory genes and epigenetic factors in development. Rather than executing already entrenched genetic programs and relying on chance mutation to initiate evolutionary change, the developmental process appears to generate heritable variations that ab initio respond to environmental factors in an adaptive way.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Biology, evolutionary biology, evolutionary theory, and philosophy of biology differ but form a continuum. The center of gravity in this chapter is between the second and the third of these forms of inquiry, with glances at the fourth.

  2. 2.

    “Neo-Darwinism” originally referred to August Weismann’s (1834–1914) belief that natural selection working exclusively on germ-line heritability is the sole cause of evolution. “Hard heredity” is a necessary condition for the Darwinism of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis, but the Synthesis rejects the “all-sufficiency (Allmacht) of natural selection” and takes a population-level view of evolutionary processes.

  3. 3.

    Lamarck used the term publicly for the first time in 1802. In Latin, “biologia” occurred in the 1760s in the philosophical works of Christian Wolff and his disciples but with a different meaning.

  4. 4.

    Texts from letters to and from Darwin are cited by their identifying numbers in the Darwin Correspondence Project, https://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/letters

  5. 5.

    For Darwin, adaptations evolve by natural selection in order to and because they perform biological functions. He included the functionalist but anti-evolutionist Cuvier on his short list of heroes but not the incipiently evolutionist but structuralist Geoffroy (Darwin to Ogle January 17, 1882, #13622). His other heroes, Aristotle and Linnaeus, were also non-evolutionary functionalists.

  6. 6.

    “New ideas about [germ-line or hard] heredity emerged in part out of an enthusiasm for the concept of evolution by jumps or saltations, reflecting an anti-adaptationist position” (Bowler 2013: 195, 2017).

  7. 7.

    The phase “factors of [organic] evolution” was first used in Herbert Spencer (1887); the list of candidates is still growing. “Creative factor” was probably due to the influence of Henri Bergson’s Creative Evolution (1907), even if Morgan, Dobzhansky, and others ascribed evolutionary innovation and direction to factors other than Bergson’s inner-driven, intuitively apprehended source of change (élan vital) (Loison and Herring 2017).

  8. 8.

    Fisher proved mathematically that under certain conditions natural selection can favor heterozygotes, but, unlike Dobzhansky, he did not assign an evolutionary function to this scenario (Fisher 1930). Dobzhansky’s encounter with French evolutionists may have been a source of the distinction he drew between adaptations to specific environments (which can be traps) and heterotic adaptations for adapting (Loison and Herring 2017). As a young man, Dobzhansky read Bergson. He devoted his career to showing that natural selection can explain tendencies that Bergson’s followers ascribed to an inner drive that can be philosophically intuited but not experimentally proven. When he argued that, “Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution,” Dobzhansky’s overt target was creationism, but his point has wider significance (Dobzhansky 1973). In contrast to traits that evolutionary and non-evolutionary observers alike can agree are adaptive—the differently shaped beaks of the finches Darwin found on neighboring islands in the Galapagos, for example—evolutionary history’s most important adaptations cannot even be seen by pre- and anti-evolutionary biologists, let alone be explained by them.

  9. 9.

    Intelligent design creationists have glommed on to neutral mutation and evenly ticking molecular clocks as reasons for disputing not just natural selection but evolution itself. Not surprisingly, they have been loath to take note of complications suggesting the workings of natural selection after all (Hofmann 2017).

  10. 10.

    A caveat. In the interwar period, a talented circle of French geneticists, many with training in and funding from other countries, began experiments in physiological genetics. This work, conducted in research institutes, positioned Boris Ephrussi, André Lwoff, Francois Jacob, and Jacques Monod (who with Jacob discovered the lac operon, the first regulatory genetic mechanism to be understood) to take the lead in studies of gene regulation in the 1960s, in the process restoring the decisive importance of experiment (Burian and Gayon 1999; Loison and Herring 2017). At that time, molecular geneticists in America were still preoccupied with nailing down the genetic code and finding the mechanisms and pathways of protein production.

  11. 11.

    American neo-Lamarckism, prominent in the nineteenth century, did not last far into the twentieth. Unlike their French counterparts, American evolutionary biologists in the interwar period embraced genetic determinism and negative eugenics—eugenics aimed at preventing the supposed unfit from reproducing in contrast to the positive eugenics that flourished in the United Kingdom, which aimed at breeding a fitter governing class—in ways that tended to support the racism with which the United States still struggles (Kevles 1985). Dobzhansky worked with American anthropologists to develop a version of the Modern Synthesis that opposed all three: genetic determinism, eugenics, and racism (Jackson and Depew 2017).

  12. 12.

    “It takes an enormous amount of biological machinery for genes to be expressed; exactly which parts of the genome are processed depends on specific settings and structure of that machinery” (Burian and Kampourakis 2013: 613).

  13. 13.

    Crick pointed out in 1970 that his 1956 version of the central dogma was not as dogmatic as the (unnamed) Watson’s insistence that information must flow unidirectionally in temporal order from DNA to RNA to protein. See Burian and Kampourakis (2013: 616, n. 27).

  14. 14.

    Classical epigenesis and contemporary epigenetics do not refer to the same thing but do have historical connections. Neo-Darwinism reduced the scope of nongenetic forms of heritability, such as cytoplasmic inheritance, almost to zero. Those who defended the latter, notably C. H. Waddington, referred to all aspects of inheritance as “epigenetic.” The epigenome includes genes but goes beyond them. By stressing the ontogenetic locus in which an array of reproductive factors interact as “developmental resources,” current advocates of the evolutionary significance of epigenetic modifications contest whether DNA is the sole carrier of biological heritability. Seeing residues of preformationism lurking in the notion of molecules that carry and transmit “information,” they sometime call for a new form of preformationism’s ancient antagonist, epigenesis (Oyama et al. 2001).

  15. 15.

    Embedding organisms in ecological systems brings into view the lawful thermodynamic imperatives to which ecological systems must conform. In thermodynamically open, far from equilibrium systems, variation and selection of efficient dissipative pathways is inevitable. These physical and chemical imperatives permit, or even encourage, the emergence of developmental systems in which variation and selection take specifically biological forms. A lesson favorable to integrating evo-devo and Darwinism is that adaptive natural selection properly so called can take place only in developmental systems, which in turn are entrained with the environments by which they are co-defined.

  16. 16.

    Coyne and Orr (2004) summarize the methods and results of speciation research. That Coyne is an opponent of expanded, extended, or new syntheses is not unconnected with his understandable desire to defend real achievements of which he is a direct heir and contributor (Coyne and Orr 1989; Coyne 2009).

  17. 17.

    Lamarkism co-opted by Darwinism yet again!

  18. 18.

    My thanks to Richard Delisle, Jean-Baptiste Grodwohl, Jim Hofmann, and Bruce Weber for helping me improve this chapter.

References

  • Adams M (ed) (1994a) The evolution of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams M (1994b) Introduction: Theodosius Dobzhansky in Russia and America. In: Adams M (ed) The evolution of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 3–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch P, Alberch J (1981) Heterochronic mechanisms of morphological diversification and evolutionary change in the neo-tropical salamander, Bolitoglossa occidental. J Morphol 167:249–264

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Allen G (1979) Thomas Hunt Morgan: the man and his science. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Appel T (1987) The Cuvier-Geoffrey debate: French biology in the decades before Darwin. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Matthen M (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 49:55–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin JM (1896) A new factor in evolution. Am Nat 30:441–451; 536–553

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J (2016) The creativity of natural selection in the modern evolutionary synthesis Part I: Darwin, Darwinism, and the mutationists. J Hist Biol 49:659. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-016-9456-5

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler P (1988) The non-Darwinian revolution. John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler P (2013) Darwin deleted: imagining a world without Darwin. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler PJ (2017) Alternatives to Darwinism in the early twentieth century. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 195–218

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burian R, Gayon J (1999) The French school of genetics: from physiological and population genetics to regulatory molecular genetics. Annu Rev Genet 33:313–349

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Burian R, Kampourakis K (2013) Against ‘genes for’: could an inclusive concept of genetic material replace gene concepts? In: Kampourakis K (ed) The philosophy of biology: a companion for educators. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 597–628

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cairns J, Overbaugh J, Miller S (1988). The origin of mutants. Nature 335:142–145

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll S (2005) Endless forms most beautiful: the new science of evo-devo. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers R (1844) Vestiges of the natural history of creation. Churchill, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan Y, Marks M, Jones F, Villarreal G, Shapiro M, Shannon M, Brady D, Southwick A, Absher D, Grimwood J, Schmutz J, Myers R, Petrov D, Jónsson B, Schluter D, Bell M, Kingsley D (2010) Deletion of a Pitx1 enhancer. Science 327:302–305

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Colosimo P, Peichel C, Nereng K, Blackman B, Shapiro M, Schluter D, Kingsley D (2004) The genetic architecture of parallel armor plate reduction in threespine sticklebacks. PLoS Biol 2(5):E109

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Colosimo P, Hosemann K, Balabhardra S, Villareal G, Dickson M, Grimwood J, Schmutz J, Myers R, Schluter D, Kingsley D (2005) Widespread parallel evolution in sticklebacks by repeated fixation of ectodysplasin alleles. Science 307:1928–1933

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cook G (1999) Neo-Lamarckian experimentalism in America: origins and consequences. Q Rev Biol 74:417–437

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne J (2009) Are we ready for an “extended evolutionary synthesis”? http://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2009/02/16/are-we-ready-for-an-extended-evolutionary-synthesis. Accessed 4 Aug 2015

  • Coyne J, Orr A (1989) Patterns of speciation in Drosophila. Evolution 43:362–381

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne J, Orr A (2004) Speciation. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick F (1956) On protein synthesis. Symp Soc Exp Biol 12:139–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick F (1970) The central dogma of molecular biology. Nature 227(5258):561–563

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species. John Murray, London (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Facsimile of 1st ed)

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1868) The variation of animals and plants under domestication. John Murray, London, 2 vol

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1989) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2nd edn, 1st edn 1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (2006) The god delusion. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Delisle R (2001) Adaptationism versus cladism in human evolution studies. In: Corbey R, Roebroeks L (eds) Studying human origins: disciplinary history and epistemology. University of Amsterdam Press, Amsterdam, pp 107–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Delisle RG (2017) From Charles Darwin to the evolutionary synthesis: weak and diffused connections only. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 133–168

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dennert E (1904) At the deathbed of Darwinism (trans: O’Harra E, Peschges H). German Literary Board, Burlington (First German edition, 1903)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew D (2003) Baldwin and his many effects. In: Weber B, Depew D (eds) Evolution and learning. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 3–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew D (2009) The rhetoric of Darwin’s origin of species. In: Ruse M, Richards R (eds) The Cambridge companion to the origin of species. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 237–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew D (2011) Adaptation as process: the future of Darwinism and the legacy of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Stud Hist Philos Bio Biomed Sci 42:89–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Depew D, Weber B (2017) Developmental biology, natural selection, and the conceptual boundaries of the modern evolutionary synthesis. Zygon 52:468–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1937) Genetics and the origin of species, 1st edn. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1951) Genetics and the origin of species, 3rd edn. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1962) Mankind evolving. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1970) Genetics of the evolutionary process. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1973) Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. Am Biol Teach 35:125–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle WF (1999) Phylogenetic classification and the universal tree. Science 284(5423):2124–2129

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N, Gould SJ (1972) Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism. In: Schopf T (ed) Models in paleobiology. Freeman, San Francisco, pp 82–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge N, Tattersal I (1975) Evolutionary models, phylogenetic reconstruction, and another look at hominid phylogeny. Contrib Primatol 5:218–242

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Esposito M (2017) The organismal synthesis: holistic science and developmental evolution in the English-speaking world, 1915–1954. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 219–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Felicity C. Jones, Manfred G. Grabherr, Yingguang Frank Chan, Pamela Russell, Evan Mauceli, Jeremy Johnson, Ross Swofford, Mono Pirun, Michael C. Zody, Simon White, Ewan Birney, Stephen Searle, Jeremy Schmutz, Jane Grimwood, Mark C. Dickson, Richard M. Myers, Craig T. Miller, Brian R. Summers, Anne K. Knecht, Shannon D. Brady, Haili Zhang, Alex A. Pollen, Timothy Howes, Chris Amemiya, Jen Baldwin, Toby Bloom, David B. Jaffe, Robert Nicol, Jane Wilkinson, Eric S. Lander, Federica Di Palma, Kerstin Lindblad-Toh, David M. Kingsley (2012) The genomic basis of adaptive evolution in threespine sticklebacks. Nature 484 (7392):55–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foster PL (2007) Stress-induced mutagenesis in bacteria. Crit Rev Biochem Mol Biol 42:373–397

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1995) Sélection naturelle ou survie des plus aptes? Éléments pour une histoire du concept de fitness dans la théorie évolutionniste. In: Blanckaert C, Fischer J, Rey R (eds) Nature, histoire, société: essais en hommage à Jacques Roger. Klincksieck, Paris, pp 263–287

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1997) The ‘paramount power’ of selection: from Darwin to Kauffman. In: Della Chiara J (ed) Structure and norms in science, Synthese. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, pp 265–282

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1998) Darwinism’s struggle for survival. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1st French edition 1992)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S (1994) Dobzhansky, Waddington and Schmalhausen: embryology and the modern synthesis. In: Adams M (ed) The evolution of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 143–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S, Epel D (2009) Ecological developmental biology. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldenfeld N, Woese C (2007) Biology’s next revolution. Nature 445:369

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt R (1940) The material basis of evolution. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin B (1994) How the leopard changed its spots: the evolution of complexity. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1980a) Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging? Paleobiology 6:119–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1980b) The return of hopeful monsters. Nat Hist 86:22–30 (Reprint: Gould, SJ (1980) The panda’s thumb. Norton, New York, pp 186–193)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1980c) The uses of heresy: introduction to reissue of Goldschmidt 1940. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1983) The hardening of the modern synthesis. In: Grene M (ed) Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 71–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1989) Wonderful life: the Burgess shale and the nature of history. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1997) Darwinian fundamentalism. NY Rev Books 44:34–37. http://www.nybooks.com/issues/1997/06/12/

  • Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc Lond Ser B 205(1161):581–598

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Grene M, Depew D (2004) The philosophy of biology: an episodic history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hallgrímsson B, Hall B (2011) Variation: a central concept in biology. Academic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1950) Grundzüge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge MJS (2016) Chance and chances in Darwin’s early theorizing and in Darwinian theory today. In: Ramsey G, Pence C (eds) Chance and evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 41–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann J (2017) Rate variation during molecular evolution: creationism and the cytochrome c molecular clock. Evol Educ Outreach 10:1. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12052-017-0064-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huxley J (1942) Evolution: the modern synthesis. Allyn and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb M (1995) Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: the Lamarckian dimension. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb M (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson J, Depew D (2017) Darwinism, democracy, and race: American anthropology and evolutionary biology in the twentieth century. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2000) The century of the gene. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellogg V (1907) Darwinism today. Holt, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kettlewell B (1955) Selection experiments on industrial melanism in the Lepidoptera. Heredity 9:323–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kettlewell B (1956) Further selection experiments on industrial melanism in the Lepidoptera. Heredity 10:287–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kevles D (1985) In the name of eugenics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimura M (1968) Evolutionary rate at the molecular level. Nature 217(5129):624–626

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • King J, Jukes T (1969) Non-Darwinian evolution. Science 164(3881):788–798

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera U (2017) Symbiogenesis and cell evolution: an anti-Darwinian research agenda? In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 302–332

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lack D (1947) Darwin’s finches. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrove (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 91–195

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Uller T, Feldman M, Sterelny K, Müller G, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling Smee J (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? yes, urgently. Nature 514:161–162

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Larson E (1997) Summer for the gods. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee M, Ho S (2016) Molecular clocks. Curr Biol 26:R387–R407

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R, Lewontin R (1985) The dialectical biologist. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Levit GS, Hossfeld U (2017) Major research traditions in 20th century evolutionary biology: the relations of Germany’s Darwinism with them. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 169–194

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R (1982) Organism and environment. In: Plotkin H (ed) Learning, development and culture: essays in evolutionary epistemology. Wiley, New York, pp 151–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R, Levins R (2007) Biology under the influence: dialectical essays on ecology, agriculture, and health. Monthly Review Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd Morgan C (1896) On modification and variation. Science 4:733–740

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loison L, Herring E (2017) Lamarckian research programs in French biology (1900–1970). In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 243–270

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein J (2016) Garland Allen, Thomas Hunt Morgan, and development. J His Biol 49(4):587–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margulis L (1992) Symbiosis in cell evolution: microbial communities in the Archean and proterozoic eons. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Burian R, Kauffman S, Alberch P, Campbell J, Goodwin B, Lande R, Raup D, Wolpert L (1985) Developmental constraints and evolution. Q Rev Biol 60:265–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1942) Systematics and the origin of species. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1963) Animal species and evolution. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1980) Prologue. In: Mayr E, Provine W (eds) The evolutionary synthesis. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–48

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1992) Speciational evolution or punctuated equilibria. In: Somit A, Peterson S (eds) The dynamics of evolution. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 21–48

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon J, Rundle H (2002) Speciation in nature: the threespine stickleback model system. Trends Ecol Evol 7:470–488

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R, Skipper R, Dietrich M (2009) (Mis)interpreting mathematical models: drift as a physical process. Philos Theor Biol 1:e002. http://quod.lib.umich.edu/p/ptb/6959004.0001.002?view=text;rgn=main

  • Moorjani P, Amorin C, Arndt P, Przeworski M (2016) Variation in the molecular clock of primates. PNAS. www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10/1073/pnas.1600374113d

  • Morgan TH (1935). The scientific basis of evolution, 2nd edn. Norton, New York (1st edn, 1932)

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris SM (2003) Life’s solution: inevitable humans in a lonely universe. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moss L (2003) What genes can’t do. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham J (1984) Forward. In: Ho M, Saunders P (eds) Beyond neo-Darwinism: an introduction to the new evolutionary paradigm. Academic, London, pp vii–viii

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman S, Müller G (2000) Epigenetic mechanisms of character formation. J Exp Zool 288:304–2317

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson D (2014) The return of the organism as a fundamental explanatory concept in biology. Philos Compass 9:347–359. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyhart L (2009) Embryology and morphology. In: Ruse M, Richards R (eds) The Cambridge companion to the origin of species. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 237–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee J, Laland K, Feldman M (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborn HF (1895) The hereditary mechanism and the search for the unknown factors of evolution. In: Biological lectures delivered at the marine biological laboratory of Wood’s Holl [sic] in the summer of 1894. Ginn, Boston, pp 79–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborn HF (1896) A mode of evolution requiring neither natural selection nor the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Trans NY Acad Sci 15:141–142; 148

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S, Griffiths P, Gray R (eds) (2001) Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfennig D, Wund M, Snell-Root E, Cruickshank T, Schlichting C, Moczek A (2010) Phenotypic plasticity’s impacts on diversification and speciation. Trends Evol Ecol 25:459–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis? Evolution 61:2743–2749

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2017) Darwinism after the modern synthesis. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 89–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Müller G (eds) (2010) Evolution: the extended synthesis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville A, Danchin E (2017) Genetic assimilation and the paradox of blind variation. In: Huneman P, Walsh D (eds) Challenging the modern synthesis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine W (1971) The origins of theoretical population genetics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine W (1986) Sewall Wright and evolutionary biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rainger R (1991) An agenda for antiquity: Henry Fairfield Osborn and vertebrate paleontology at the American Museum of Natural History, 1890–1935. University of Alabama Press, Tuscalousa

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss J (2009) Not by design: retiring Darwin’s watchmaker. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards R (1992) The meaning of evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting C (2008) Hidden reaction norms, cryptic variation, and evolvability. Annu Rev Acad Sci 1133:187–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting C, Pigliucci M (1993) Control of phenotypic plasticity via regulatory genes. Am Nat 142:366–370

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Secord JA (2000) Victorian sensation: the extraordinary publication, reception, and secret authorship of Vestiges of the natural history of creation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedley D (2007) Creationism and its critics in antiquity. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan T (2017) Selfish genes and lucky breaks: Richard Dawkins’ and Stephen Jay Gould’s: divergent Darwinian agendas. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 11–36

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson GG (1944) Tempo and mode in evolution. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson GG (1953) The Baldwin effect. Evolution 7:110–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer H (1887) The factors of organic evolution. Appleton, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stocking G (1968) Race, culture, and evolution: essays in the history of anthropology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner DD (2017) Paleobiology’s uneasy relationship with the Darwinian tradition: stasis as data. In: Delisle RG (ed) The Darwinian tradition in context: research programs in evolutionary biology. Springer, Cham, pp 333–352

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington C (1953) Genetic assimilation of an acquired character. Evolution 7(2):118–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2015) Organisms, agency, and evolution. University of Cambridge Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber B, Depew D (2003) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Weismann A (1889) Essays upon heredity. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Woese K, Goldenfeld N (2009) How the microbial world saved evolution from the Scylla of molecular biology and the Charybdis of the modern synthesis. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 73:14–21

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Wray G, Hoekstra H, Futuyma D, Lenski R, Mackay T, Schluter D, Strassma J (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? no, all is well. Nature 514(161):163–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S (1932). The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding, and selection in evolution. Proc. 6th Int. Cong. Genet. 1: 356–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wund M (2008) A test of the ‘flexible stem’ model of evolution: ancestral plasticity, genetic cccomodation, and morphological divergence in the threespine stickleback radiation. Am Nat 172:449–462

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zuckerkandl E, Pauling L (1965) Evolutionary divergence and convergence in proteins. In: Bryson V, Vogel H (eds) Evolving genes and proteins. Academic, New York, pp 97–166

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David J. Depew .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Depew, D.J. (2017). Darwinism in the Twentieth Century: Productive Encounters with Saltation, Acquired Characteristics, and Development. In: Delisle, R. (eds) The Darwinian Tradition in Context. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69123-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics