Skip to main content

Revisiting Holism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Semantics, Pragmatics and Meaning Revisited

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 17))

  • 367 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I argue that a holistic account of mental content is inescapable and, in fact, not as problematic as critics (especially Fodor and Lepore, Holism: a shopper’s guide. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford/Cambridge, 1992) argue. First, I introduce (the complexities of) the distinction between the wide and narrow kinds of mental content and then briefly discuss the relation between various philosophical notions of mental content and Relevance Theory’s (RT) linguistic semantics. Next, I argue that all philosophical notions of shared content, namely causal-externalist wide content, social-externalist wide content and non-truth-theoretic narrow content, are problematic and that holism is the only plausible thesis about mental content. I endorse Bilgrami’s (holistic) thesis about the unity and locality of content. I discuss how Bigrami’s philosophy fits in with the wholly inferential model of utterance interpretation I argued for in Chap. 3. Finally, I discuss how, in the light of Bilgrami’s thesis and the Representational Hypothesis, we can and should distinguish between a domain of concepts and a domain of associations between semiotic labels and concepts.

The quotation from Noûs, 32, Akeel Bilgrami, Why holism is harmless and necessary, 105–126, Copyright © 1998 Wiley, is reprinted here with permission of John Wiley and Sons Inc.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The network effect and radical individualism are conceptually distinct but closely related aspects of holism.

  2. 2.

    Actually, the assumption that ‘meanings’ are not possessed by each individual shows that they are not collectively shared. I discuss this point further in Sect. 4.3.3.

  3. 3.

    This terminology is borrowed from Bilgrami (1992).

  4. 4.

    In fact, Putnam’s narrow-wide distinction was designed as a thesis about the content of linguistic expressions and was only subsequently employed in theories of concepts as such (as argued by Brown 2011).

  5. 5.

    These examples are taken from Recanati (1993: 66).

  6. 6.

    Perry’s argument cannot be maintained. If I entertain the same narrow content ‘His pants are on fire’ but apprehend different thoughts about (a) Mark, who’s my friend, and (b) Tom, who I hold a grudge against, I may rush to help Mark but laugh at Tom. In this example, it is Perry’s wide content, thus, that explains my differing actions.

  7. 7.

    Whereas schemas are context-independent, they do not seem to be independent of the mind-external environment since schemas are, presumably, acquired in experience (see Sect. 3.1). In this context, it is interesting to consider Bach’s (1996) comment that one challenge for the proponents of narrow content is to ‘specify narrow contents informatively, rather than by abstraction from wide contents’.

  8. 8.

    This holds on the assumption of the analytic-synthetic distinction.

  9. 9.

    Even though I endorse the idea of public availability in terms of context-dependence (and in spite of its variability), I do not endorse the narrow-wide distinction, to which Perry is committed. I say more about these issues in Sect. 4.3 and 4.4.

  10. 10.

    Conceptual role semantics is concerned with the content of concepts (i.e. sub-propositional entities), whereas inferential role semantics is concerned with the role a proposition plays in a set of inference patterns (Pagin 2006).

  11. 11.

    Furthermore, there exist puzzles where one and the same term has to correspond to two distinct Fodorian concepts, i.e. concepts with the same content but distinct syntaxes. An example is provided by the so-called Paderewski puzzle. Paderewski was a famous Polish pianist as well as Prime Minister. Thus, we can easily imagine a situation where a person who mistakenly believes that Paderewski the pianist and Paderewski the politician were two different people has a further belief that they have met Paderewski the politician, but not Paderewski the pianist in person. Fodor’s solution to this puzzle is to argue that this person has two syntactically distinct concepts which share the same content.

  12. 12.

    In the unlikely event that it were possible to investigate people’s mental contents, conceptual primitive by conceptual primitive, and if we found a single conceptual structure recurrent across individuals in association with a given semiotic label (see my discussion of RT’s process of ‘concept narrowing’ in Sect. 3.1), we could not extrapolate from such an observation to the existence of collectively shared linguistic semantics. Relatedly, we could not extrapolate from such finding to the existence of the cognitive process of deterministic decoding of such content.

  13. 13.

    That is, the ‘problem’ arises if one – like Fodor and Lepore – doesn’t acknowledge the role of pragmatic constraints.

  14. 14.

    As discussed in Chap. 2, Chomsky (2000) sympathises with Bilgrami’s account.

  15. 15.

    However, conceptual spaces theory makes use of dynamically construed prototypes for some categories.

  16. 16.

    This interpretation seems to be right especially in the light of Bilgrami’s (1992: 12) argument that the locality thesis ‘dissolves the very idea of content composed of context-invariant concepts’. He (ibid.) argues that the locality thesis offers ‘a way out of the dogmas of a certain way of thinking which leave us on the one hand with a false distinction [wide-narrow] and, on the other, with an artificially tidy picture of the mind’.

  17. 17.

    See Pollock (2013) for a relevant discussion and defence of holism.

  18. 18.

    Evans’s LCCM approach (2006, 2009) is an interesting illustration of adherence to this classical, but hugely problematic (as discussed in Chap. 3) notion of a linguistic sign. This theory is of interest to us because it stresses the importance of a meaning potential whilst insisting on the moderate lumping paradigm. On the one hand, Evans reserves the term ‘meaning’ to what can be characterised as ad hoc concepts, stressing that ‘meaning’ is a context-dependent phenomenon. However, he also argues (e.g. 2009: 153) that both ‘stable units of semantic structure’ – i.e. lexical concepts, which partly constitute the ‘bipolar symbolic units’ that populate the linguistic system – and a ‘dynamically evolving non-linguistic knowledge’ (a.k.a. meaning potential) are required for ‘meaning’ construction. Whereas I agree with Evans (e.g. 2009: 84) that words do not have meaning and think that Evans’s work is a fruitful contribution to the study of how different parts of the meaning potential are activated in utterance interpretation, the objections I raised against the Saussurean approaches in Chap. 3 apply here equally strongly. Evans acknowledges that context helps select between different lexical concepts associated with a polysemous word and argues that such contextually selected lexical concept is needed to give access to specific – i.e. consistent with the context – regions of the meaning potential representation. In other words, for Evans there’s no accessing of the meaning potential without the gatekeeper in the form of a lexical concept. But we have seen that on a multiple-trace theory of memory activation of specific regions of the meaning potential can be achieved without positing lexical concepts (or any other kind of summary representations). Specific regions of the meaning potential representation (i.e. specific memory traces associated with a given morpho-phonetic label) will be activated in response to the context sensitive probe (mental representation of an acoustic event that activates an aggregate of exemplars labelled with a morpho-phonetic label and mental representation of context which activates relevant traces within that aggregate). Furthermore, even though for Evans ‘meaning’ is an utterance phenomenon, it is seen as a property of an utterance (e.g. 2009: 73) – hence, my earlier likening of it to ad hoc concepts. I leave the explanation of why this is a problem until Chap. 6, where I discuss why a clear distinction needs to be made between the content of a communicated thought – an ad hoc concept – on the one hand, and meaning – qua relation – on the other (I have made a similar promise earlier in relation to Urquiza’s stance on Relevance Theoretic approach to ‘meaning’).

References

  • Alwood, J. (2003). Meaning potentials and contexts: Some consequences for the analysis of variation in meaning. In H. Cuckens, R. Dirven, & J. Taylor (Eds.), Cognitive approaches to lexical semantics (pp. 22–66). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1996). Content: Wide vs. narrow. In E. Craig (Ed.), The Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. Routledge. http://online.sfsu.edu/kbach/widenarr.html. Accessed 21 Jan 2011.

  • Bilgrami, A. (1992). Belief and meaning. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilgrami, A. (1998). Why holism is harmless and necessary. Noûs, 32, 105–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. In P. A. French et al. (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy 10: Studies in the philosophy of mind (pp. 615–678). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1993). Holism, hyper-analyticity and hyper-compositionality. Mind and Language, 8(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1995). An argument for holism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 95, 151–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1998a). Holism, mental and semantic. In E. Craig (Ed.), The Routledge enclyclopaedia of philosophy. Routledge. http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/MentalSemanticHolism.htm. Accessed 21 Jan 2011.

  • Block, N. (1998b). Conceptual role semantics. In E. Craig (Ed.), The Routledge enclyclopaedia of philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, C. (2011). Narrow mental content. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-narrow. Accessed 21 Jan 2011.

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. In P. French et al. (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy (Vol. 4). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Reprinted in Burge, T. (2007). Foundations of mind (pp. 100–150). Oxford: Clarendon Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton-Roberts, N. (2013). Meaning, semantics and semiotics. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.), Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics (pp. 1–22). London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2010). Explicit communication and ‘free’ pragmatic enrichment. In B. Soria & E. Romero (Eds.), Explicit communication: Robyn Carston’s pragmatics (pp. 217–287). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2013). Word meaning, what is said and explicature. In C. Penco & F. Domaneschi (Eds.), What is said and what is not. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, V. (2006). Lexical concepts, cognitive models and meaning construction. Cognitive Linguistics, 17, 491–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, V. (2009). How words mean: Lexical concepts, cognitive models, and meaning construction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2008). LOT2: Language of thought revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A shopper’s guide. Oxford/Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (2015). Minds without meanings: An essay on the content of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1960). On sense and reference. In P. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 36–56). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2014). The geometry of meaning: Semantics based on conceptual spaces. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harder, P. (2009). Meaning as input: The instructional perspective. In V. Evans & S. Pourcel (Eds.), New directions in cognitive linguistics (pp. 15–26). Amsterdam: Johns Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hintzman, D. (1986). “Schema abstraction” in a multiple trace memory model. Psychological Review, 93, 411–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. W. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar: Volume I theoretical prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E. (1999). Semantic holism. In R. Auri (Ed.), The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (2006). Meaning holism. In E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.), Handbook of philosophy of language (pp. 213–232). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pateman, T. (1987). Language in mind and language in society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1977). Frege on demonstratives. Philosophical Review, 86, 474–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (2013). Mental content, holism and communication. PhD thesis, University of Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In Philosophical papers, vol. 2: Mind language and reality (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1993). Direct reference: From language to thought. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2005). Literalism and contextualism: Some varieties. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruhl, C. (1989). On Monosemy: A study in linguistic semantics. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandra, D. (1998). What linguists can and can’t tell you about the human mind: A reply to croft. Cognitive Linguistics, 9(4), 361–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1998). The mapping between the mental and the public lexicon. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Thought and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J. R. (2012). The mental corpus: How language is represented in the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuggy, D. (2003). The Nawatl verb kīsa: A case study in polysemy. In H. Cuckens, R. Dirven, & J. Taylor (Eds.), Cognitive approaches to lexical semantics (pp. 22–66). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyler, A., & Evans, V. (2001). Reconsidering prepositional polysemy networks: The case of over. Language, 77, 724–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warglien, M., & Gärdenfors, P. (2013). Semantics, conceptual spaces and the meeting of minds. Synthese, 190(12), 2165–2193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wikforss, A. M. (2004). Externalism and incomplete understanding. The Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 287–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev, J. (2003). Polysemy or generality? Mu. In H. Cuckens, R. Dirven, & J. Taylor (Eds.), Cognitive approaches to lexical semantics (pp. 22–66). Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sztencel, M. (2018). Revisiting Holism. In: Semantics, Pragmatics and Meaning Revisited. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 17. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69116-9_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69116-9_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-69115-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-69116-9

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics