Skip to main content

Normative Ethics Before the Twentieth Century

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Scientific Approach to Ethics
  • 663 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter we will explore the most interesting period in the development of ethics—the appearance of the idea of science and the following construction of a new type of knowledge based only on rational argumentation. We will explore how the creators of the new human knowledge understood the methodological status of ethics and will see that surprisingly many of them believed in the possibility of building a scientific variant of ethics. Other philosophers took opposite positions and claimed that scientific ethics was impossible. Later this skepticism had a strong influence on further development of moral philosophy and other social sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Bacon divided all sciences into Natural Philosophy and Human Philosophy. The latter was divided into Philosophy of Humanity which studies a man as such and Civil Philosophy which studies interaction of people in society. Philosophy of Humanity is divided into study of body and study of soul, and the study of soul was divided into two parts: logic which studies cognitive reasoning and ethics which studies will, the appetites, and affections. Ethics also consisted from two parts: “exemplar of platform of good” which should establish an ideal of good and “the regiment or culture of the mind” which should bring the person to the discovered ideal.

  2. 2.

    Descartes’ Method was published in 1637, Hobbes’ Leviathan in 1651. During his long stay in Paris, Hobbes enjoyed the intellectual company of skeptics (Maren Mersenne, Pierre Gassendi, and others), and therefore breathed the same intellectual atmosphere as Descartes (Herbert 2011, p. x). We know that Hobbes wrote a review on one of Descartes’ books, and Descartes once said that Hobbes’ “ability in morals was far greater than in metaphysics and physics.” (Robertson 1886, p. 58). Leo Strauss suggested that Hobbes borrowed his understanding of passions from Descartes’ The Passions of the Soul (1649) (Strauss 1936).

References

  • Asmis, Elizabeth. 1984. Epicurus’ Scientific Method. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, Max. 1964. The Gap Between “Is” and “Should”. The Philosophical Review 73 (2): 165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Box, Ian. 1996. Bacon’s Moral Philosophy. In The Cambridge Companion to Bacon, ed. M. Peltonen, 260–282. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Caluori, Damian. 2007. The Scepticism of Francisco Sanchez. Archiv fĂĽr Geschichte der Philosophie 89 (1): 30–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, RenĂ©. 1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Vol. 1–2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Filmer, Robert. 1648. The Necessity of the Absolute Power of All Kings. London. 

    Google Scholar 

  • Finn, Stephen J. 2006. Thomas Hobbes and the Politics of Natural Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, Richard. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, Gary B. 2011. Thomas Hobbes: The Unity of Scientific and Moral Wisdom. UBC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1839. The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Edited by W. Molesworth, Vols. 1–11. London: J. Bohn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1739. A Treatise of Human Nature. London: Printed for John Noon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutcheson, Francis. 1725. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. Printed by J. Darby in London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor, with an introduction by Christine M. Korsgaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (2006).

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1824. The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes. 12th ed. London: Rivington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, Richard A. 1976. Blackstone and Bentham. The Journal of Law and Economics 19 (3): 569–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, Richard. 1758. A Review of the Principal Questions and Difficulties in Morals: Particularly Those Relating to the Original of Our Ideas of Virtue, Its Nature, Foundation, Reference to the Deity, Obligation, Subject Matter, and Sanctions. London: printed for A. Millar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raphael, David Daiches. 2007. The Impartial Spectator: Adam Smith’s Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, George Croom. 1886. Hobbes. Edinburgh: William Blackwood and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Adam. 1759. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. London: printed for A. Millar; and A. Kincaid and J. Bell, in Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, Leo. 1936. The Political Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes: Its Basis and Its Genesis. Translated by Elsa M. Sinclair. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Storchevoy, M. (2018). Normative Ethics Before the Twentieth Century. In: A Scientific Approach to Ethics. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69113-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics