Skip to main content

Knights, Knaves, Truth, Truthfulness, Grounding, Tethering, Aboutness, and Paradox

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Raymond Smullyan on Self Reference

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 14))

Abstract

Knights always tell the truth; Knaves always lie. Knaves for familiar reasons cannot coherently describe themselves as liars. That would be like Epimenides the Cretan accusing all Cretans of lying. Knights do not *intuitively* run into the same problem. What could prevent a Knight from truly reporting that s/he always tells the truth? Standard theories of truth DO prevent this, however, for such a report is self-referentially ungrounded. Standard theories have a problem, then! We try to fix it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Self-identified knights are the group Smullyan admires the most. If they were talking nonsense, he would have noticed it.

  2. 2.

    Kripke does allow ungrounded sentences to be intrinsically true: true in a fixed point none of whose assignments are reversed in other fixed points. But the Truthfulness-Teller cannot claim that lesser status either, for there are fixed points in which it is uniquely false.

  3. 3.

    Kripke cites Herzberger (1970). See also Davis (1979), Hazen (1981), Yablo (1982), and Yablo (1993). For the relation to grounding in set theory, see Mirimanoff (1917), Yuting (1953), Boolos (1971), Barwise and Etchemendy (1989), McLarty (1993), and Yablo (2006).

  4. 4.

    There could be an “unwinding” of K that does not depend on itself, yet is equally untethered. Kripke notes the possibility of “an infinite sequence of sentences P \(_{i}\), where P \(_{i}\) says that P \(_{i+1}\) is true” (Kripke 1975, 693). For unwindings more generally see Schlenker (2007) and Cook (2014).

  5. 5.

    Compressed for readability.

  6. 6.

    Taken from (3) above.

  7. 7.

    The underlying model M is a model, possibly partial, of the T-free part of the language.

  8. 8.

    Yablo (1982).

  9. 9.

    No consistent fixed point that is; but we have defined fixed points so that all of them are consistent.

  10. 10.

    If \(\varphi \) is TRUE, then \(|\varphi |^\mathbf{t}\) has a consistent tethered dependence tree and \(|\varphi |^\mathbf{f}\) doesn’t. By the Lemma, \(\varphi \) is true in a fact-dependent fixed point but not false in any fact-dependent fixed points. The converse is similar.

  11. 11.

    Lewis (1988).

  12. 12.

    Lewis (1988).

  13. 13.

    We will be interested only in fact-dependent fixed points, more carefully, fixed points that are fact-dependent relative to some choice \(\mathcal {A}\) of non-semantic atomic facts.

References

  • Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1989). The liar: An essay on truth and circularity. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1971). The iterative conception of set. The Journal of Philosophy, 215–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. T. (2014). The Yablo paradox: An essay on circularity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, L. (1979). An alternate formulation of Kripke’s theory of truth. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1), 289–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hazen, A. (1981). Davis’s formulation of Kripke’s theory of truth: A correction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(3), 309–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzberger, H. G. (1970). Paradoxes of grounding in semantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 145–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). Statements partly about observation. In Papers in philosophical logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLarty, C. (1993). Anti-Foundation and Self-Reference. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 22(1), 19–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirimanoff, D. (1917). Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali-Forti: et le problème fondamental de la théorie des ensembles. Enseignement mathématique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2007). The elimination of self-reference: Generalized yablo-series and the theory of truth. Journal of philosophical logic, 36(3), 251–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smullyan, R. (1986). What is the name of this book? Touchstone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1982). Grounding, dependence, and paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11, 117–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Hop, skip and jump: The agonistic conception of truth. Philosophical Perspectives, 7, 371–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2006). Circularity and paradox. In T. Bolander, V. F. Hendricks, & S. A. Pedersen (Eds.), Self-reference (pp. 139–157). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2014). Aboutness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yuting, S. (1953). Paradox of the class of all grounded classes. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 18(2), 114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Yablo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Yablo, S. (2017). Knights, Knaves, Truth, Truthfulness, Grounding, Tethering, Aboutness, and Paradox. In: Fitting, M., Rayman, B. (eds) Raymond Smullyan on Self Reference. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-68732-2_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics