Skip to main content

Hermann Weyl, The Reluctant Revolutionary

(Mathematical Intelligencer 25(1)(2003): 61–70)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Richer Picture of Mathematics
  • 2586 Accesses

Abstract

“Brouwer – that is the revolution!” – with these words from his manifesto “On the New Foundations Crisis in Mathematics” (Weyl 1921) Hermann Weyl jumped headlong into ongoing debates concerning the foundations of set theory and analysis. His decision to do so was not taken lightly, knowing that this dramatic gesture was bound to have immense repercussions not only for him, but for many others within the fragile and politically fragmented European mathematical community. Weyl felt sure that modern mathematics was going to undergo massive changes in the near future. By proclaiming a “new” foundations crisis, he implicitly acknowledged that revolutions had transformed mathematics in the past, even uprooting the entire edifice of mathematical knowledge. At the same time he drew a parallel with the “ancient” foundations crisis commonly believed to have been occasioned by the discovery of incommensurable magnitudes, a finding that overturned the Pythagorean worldview that was based on the doctrine “all is Number.” In the wake of the Great War that changed European life forever, the Zeitgeist appeared ripe for something similar, but even deeper and more pervasive.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In an interview with B.L. van der Waerden from 1984, I asked him why he thought Weyl had retreated from intuitionism by the mid 1920s. His reply, no doubt based on logic rather than personal knowledge of Weyl’s motives, offered a simple explanation. Weyl was essentially an analyst, he said, and if one accepts intuitionism then one cannot even prove the intermediate value theorem.

References

  • Alexanderson, G.L. 1987. George Pólya: A Biographical Sketch. In The Pólya Picture Album: Encounters of a Mathematician. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J. 1928. Intuitionistische Betrachtungen über den Formalismus. Sitzungsberichte der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften: 48–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, Leo. 1997. David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1894–1905). Archive for History of Exact Sciences 51: 83–198.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. David Hilbert between Mechanical and Electromagnetic Reductionism (1910–1915). Archive for History of Exact Sciences 53: 489–527.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein. 1998a. Collected Papers of Albert Einstein (CPAE), Vol. 8A: The Berlin Years: Correspondence, 1914–1917, Robert Schulmann, et al., eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998b Collected Papers of Albert Einstein (CPAE), vol. 8B: The Berlin Years: Correspondence, 1918, Robert Schulmann, et al., eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, Solomon. 2000. The Significance of Weyl’s Das Kontinuum, in [Hendricks, Pederson, Jørgensen 2000], 179–193

    Google Scholar 

  • Frei, Günther, and Urs Stammbach. 1992. Hermann Weyl und die Mathematik an der ETH Zürich, 1913–1930. Birkhäuser: Basel.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks, V.F., S.A. Pedersen, and K.F. Jørgensen, eds. 2000. Proof Theory. History and Philosophical Significance. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, David. 1904. Über die Grundlagen der Logik und der Arithmetik, Verhandlungen des III. Internationalen Mathematiker-Kongresses in Heidelberg 1904, 174–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1915. Die Grundlagen der Physik. (Erste Mitteilung), Königliche Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen. Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse. Nachrichten: 395–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1918 Axiomatisches Denken, Mathematische Annalen, 79: 405–415. (Reprinted in [Hilbert 1932–35], vol. 3, 146–156.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1922. Neubegründung der Mathematik. Erste Mitteilung, Abhandlungen aus dem Mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, 1: 157–177. (Reprinted in [Hilbert 1932–35], vol. 3, 157–177.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932–35. Gesammelte Abhandlungen. Vol. 3. Berlin: Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Gregory H. 1982. Zermelo’s Axiom of Choice: Its Origins, Development and Influence. New York: Springer.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peckhaus, Volker. 1990. Hilbertprogramm und Kritische Philosophie, Studien zur Wissenschafts-, Sozial- und Bildungsgeschichte der Mathematik, vol. 7, Göttingen; Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pólya, Georg. 1972. Eine Erinnerung an Hermann Weyl. Mathematische Zeitschrift 126: 296–298.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, David E. 2000. The Calm before the Storm: Hilbert’s Early Views on Foundations, in [Hendricks, Pederson, Jørgensen 2000], 55–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Felix Klein as Wissenschaftspolitiker. In Changing Images in Mathematics. From the French Revolution to the New Millennium, ed. Umberto Bottazzini and Amy Dahan, 69–92. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, Tilman. 2002. Hopes and Disappointments in Hilbert’s Axiomatic ‘Foundations of Physics. In History of Philosophy of Science, ed. M. Heidelberger and F. Stadler, 225–237. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scholz, Erhard. 2000. Hermann Weyl on the Concept of Continuum, in [Hendricks, Pederson, Jørgensen 2000], 195–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. Hermann Weyl’s Raum-Zeit-Materie and a General Introduction to his Scientific Work, (DMV Seminar, 30.) Basel/Boston: Birkhäuser Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Weyls Infinitesimalgeometrie, 1917–1925, in [Scholz 2001a], 48–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, Wilfried. 2000. Toward Finitist Proof Theory, in [Hendricks, Pederson, Jørgensen 2000], 95–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigurdsson, Skúli. 2001. Journeys in Spacetime, in [Scholz 2001a], 15–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, Dirk. 1995. Hermann Weyl’s Intuitionistic Mathematics. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1: 145–169.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Mystic, Geometer, and Intuitionist. The Life of L. E. J. Brouwer, vol. 1: The Dawning Revolution. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. The Development of Brouwer’s Intuitionism, in [Hendricks, Pederson, Jørgensen 2000], 117–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. L.E.J. Brouwer: Topologist, Intuitionist, Philosopher, 419. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, Hermann. 1910. Über die Definitionen der mathematischen Grundbegriffe. Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Blätter 7 (1910): 93–95, 109–113. (Reprinted in [Weyl 1968], vol. 1, 298–304.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1913. Die Idee der Riemannschen Fläche. Leipzig: Teubner.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1918a. Das Kontinuum. Leipzig: Veit & Co., 1918. The Continuum. Trans. S. Pollard and T. Bole. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1918b. Raum, Zeit, Materie. 1st ed. Berlin: Springer.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1919. Der circulus vitiosus in der heutigen Begründung der Analysis. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 28: 85–92.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1921. Über die neue Grundlagenkrise der Mathematik, Mathematische Zeitschrift, 10: 39–79. (Reprinted in [Weyl 1968], vol. 2, 143–180.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1944. Obituary: David Hilbert, 1862–1943, Obituary Notices of Fellows of the Royal Society 4: 547–553. Reprinted in [Weyl 1968], vol. 4, 120–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. In Mind and Nature: Selected Writings in Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics, ed. Peter Pesic. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zermelo, Ernst. 1908. Neuer Beweis für die Möglichkeit einer Wohlordnung. Mathematische Annalen 65: 107–128.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rowe, D.E. (2018). Hermann Weyl, The Reluctant Revolutionary. In: A Richer Picture of Mathematics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-67819-1_27

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics