Skip to main content

Hume as a Western Mādhyamika: The Case from Ethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethics without Self, Dharma without Atman

Abstract

There are obvious homologies between Hume’s metaphysics and the commitments of Madhyamaka Buddhism, to be found in his treatment of personal identity, the status of the external world and causality. But few have noticed that these homologies extend to ethics. In this essay I argue that Hume’s account of the relation between the metaphysics of the person and ethics, as well as his account of the basis of ethics in natural sympathy (extended through the power of the moral imagination to transform moral perception), also mirror Madhyamaka theory. Comparisons are drawn with the Madhyamaka ethical reflections of Santideva in particular. I do not rest my case on the claim that Hume was indirectly influenced by Buddhist ideas (as has been claimed by others recently, in connection with French intermediaries of the early eighteenth century). In any case, Hume is – in effect – a Mādhyamika through and through.

Thanks to Gordon Davis for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this essay.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My Tibetan colleagues note that in certain respects—e.g. Hume’s taking convention as a kind of explanatory bedrock, and his refusal to take it for granted that we always have concepts corresponding to our words—he appears to be a good thal ‘gyur pa/Prāsaṅgika; but in other respects, e.g. his apparent willingness to accept some convention-independent phenomena for granted—such as impressions or events—he appears more like a rang gyud pa/Svatantrika.

  2. 2.

    See Desideri (2010) for a detailed account of Desideri’s time in Tibet and fascinating observations on Buddhism.

  3. 3.

    See Liu (2002) for more on this affinity.

  4. 4.

    One must be careful not to oversell this disanalogy, however. Śāntideva devotes chapter 8 of Bodhicaryāvatāra (How to Lead an Awakened Life) to meditation precisely because he believes that it is important to repeatedly visualize the consequences of vice and virtue , and the interrelatedness of sentient beings , in order to counteract egoism by cultivating care. So Hume and Śāntideva agree about the need for cultivation, and indeed about the role of the imagination in that cultivation. They disagree about the nature of that cultivation, with Hume taking that process to be social, and Śāntideva taking it to be contemplative .

  5. 5.

    Of course this is not unique to Mahāyāna ethical cultivation . We also see the imagination at work in tantra.

  6. 6.

    See Prajñākaramati’s Pañjika to the Bodhicaryāvatāra (Oldmeadow 1994) and Kamalaśīla’s Bhavanākrama (Stages of Meditation) (Sharma 1997).

  7. 7.

    We might also note that there is a parallel in the Humean and Madhyamaka accounts of the role of reason in action selection itself. In each case, what we desire or reject is determined by the moral passions. Reason ( upāya , or practical wisdom ) enters the picture to determine the means by which we can achieve those ends. This is the point of the “slave of the passions” remark.

  8. 8.

    This, as I argue in 2012a and 2014, is a major difference between a Humean or Buddhist and a Kantian approach to ethics. For Kant , ethics is grounded in a transcendental realm, and in the reality and freedom of a unified self—a transcendental ego and ethical agent . For Hume and his Mādhyamika forebears, ethics is grounded in an understanding of the emptiness of the person, of the absence of such a self, and in the conventional reality of persons and suffering .

  9. 9.

    Translations my own from the sDe dge edition.

  10. 10.

    Translation from Cowherds 2016, pp. 59–60. See pp. 68–74 for the detailed reading of this passage as an argument for the irrationality of egoism .

  11. 11.

    As I argue in 2010/2011, Śāntideva distinguishes in the first chapter of Bodhicaryāvatāra between aspirational and engaged bodhicitta on the basis of whether or not the agent has cultivated a perception of phenomena as empty of intrinsic reality and so a spontaneous attitude of care towards others issuing from a decentering of the self.

  12. 12.

    Though this is not the place to go into this, there is a further nice affinity here: for, just as rGyal tshab claims (190) that the very idea of a self “makes no sense” and that the self “is incoherent, like the horns of a rabbit,” Hume , of course, argues that we have no idea of a self in the first place. So, according to both Hume and rGyal tshab, this is an instance where the intentional content of our passions is not only non-existent, but impossible. And each explain this possibility through a nominalist understanding of conception and intentionality.

References

  • Baier, A. 1987. Hume, the Women’s Moral Theorist. In Women and Moral Theory, ed. Eva Feder Kittay and Diana T. Meyers. Totowa: Roman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckwith, Christopher. 2015. Greek Buddha: Pyrrho’s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cowherds. 2016. Moonpaths: Ethics and Emptiness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desideri, I. 2010. Mission to Tibet, Trans. M Sweet and L Zwilling. Boston: Wisdom Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. 1990. Epoché and Sunyatā: Scepticism East and West. Philosophy East and West 40 (3): 285–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010/2011. What is it Like to be a Bodhisattva? Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 33(1–2): 327–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Western Idealism and its Critics. Sarnath: Central University of Tibetan Studies Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012a. Mindfulness and Ethics: Attention, Virtue and Perfection. In German as Achtsamkeit als Grundlage für ethisches Verhalten, ed. M. Zimmermann, C. Spitz and S Schmidtt, Achtsamkeit, 227–250. Stuttgart: Hans Huber. 2012. and Thai Journal of Buddhist Studies vol. III, pp. 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Buddhist Ethics. (in German as “Buddhistische Ethiks)” in Polylog 27: 98–110. (2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Just Another Word for Nothing Left to Lose: Freedom, Agency and Ethics for Mādhyamikas. In Freedom of the Will in a Cross-Cultural Perspective, ed. M. Dasti and E. Bryant, 164–185. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Engaging Buddhism: Why it Matters to Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 2010. Could Hume have Known about Buddhism. Huem Studies 35: 5–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. J. Schneewind,. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Y. 2002. Jesuits and Anti-Jesuits: Two Different Connections of Leibniz with China, The Eigtheenth Century vpl. 34, n0, 2, 161–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oldmeadow, P. 1994. A Study of the Wisdom Chapter (Prajñāpāramitā Pariccheda) of Bodhicaryāvatārapańjikā of Prajńāpāramitā. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, The Australian National University. https://openresearchrepository.anu.edu.au/handle/1885/110199.

  • rGyal tshab darma rinchen. 1999. Byang chub sems pa’i spyod pa la ‘jug pa’i rnam bshad rgyal sras ‘jug ngogs (Entering the Great Bodhisattva Path: An Explanation of Bodhicaryāvatāra). Sarnath: Gelugpa Student Welfare Committee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharma, P. 1997. Bhavanakarkama of Kamalasila. New Delhi: Aditya Parakashan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jay L. Garfield .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Garfield, J.L. (2018). Hume as a Western Mādhyamika: The Case from Ethics. In: Davis, G. (eds) Ethics without Self, Dharma without Atman. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 24. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-67407-0_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics