Skip to main content

Rhetoric, Emotions and the Rule of Law in Aristotle

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 121))

  • 962 Accesses

Abstract

This article argues that two of the three types of rhetorical speech conceived by Aristotle, namely, judicial speech and rhetorical speech, could be used by those wishing to assure that a well-ordered political community of a kind envisaged by Aristotle, was actually governed in accordance with what Aristotle took to be good governance, i.e. “the rule of law”. In judicial settings, rhetorical speech can arouse emotions about the rule of law that may lead citizens to refrain from disrespecting it. In deliberative settings, it can create a kind of emotional involvement with our fellow citizen that seems to be required in order for a deliberative assembly to function well. If what is said here is correct, rhetoric as conceived by Aristotle would be a powerful tool in both the hands of the unjust and the just.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Edition used: Aristotle (1977).

  2. 2.

    Bates (2013), p. 59.

  3. 3.

    Editions used: Aristotle (1926, 1991).

  4. 4.

    Although the conjunction of these two passages suggests a correspondence between epideictic speeches and the magistracies, I shall also refrain from commenting on this possible analogy since constraints of space make it impossible for me to treat epideictic speeches in this article.

  5. 5.

    Engberg-Pedersen (1996), p. 122.

  6. 6.

    Edition used: Aristotle (1997).

  7. 7.

    Engberg-Pedersen (1996), p. 124.

  8. 8.

    Ibid., p. 133.

  9. 9.

    Grimaldi (1972), p. 2.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., p. 3.

  11. 11.

    For a recent defense of the opposing view see in this volume Rapp (2018).

  12. 12.

    On this topic, see Gagarin (1978).

  13. 13.

    Demosthenes (1935).

  14. 14.

    Antiphon (1954).

  15. 15.

    Whether or not Euaeon was actually convicted because of this, of course, is an entirely different matter. Nevertheless, the fact that Demosthenes interprets the case in this way in order to support his argument shows that he believed that the judges he was addressing would recognize and accept this reading.

  16. 16.

    Leighton (1996), p. 210.

  17. 17.

    Nussbaum (1996), p. 309.

  18. 18.

    Reeve (1996), p. 199.

  19. 19.

    Engberg-Pedersen (1996), p. 122.

  20. 20.

    Kennedy (1991), p. 18.

  21. 21.

    Bates (2013), p. 62.

  22. 22.

    Yack (2006), p. 422.

  23. 23.

    Ibid.

  24. 24.

    Ibid., p. 423.

  25. 25.

    Ibid., p. 424.

  26. 26.

    Cooper (1990).

  27. 27.

    Ibid., p. 236.

  28. 28.

    Ibid., p. 220.

  29. 29.

    The interpretation defended here does not need to claim that any cases where this conflict presents itself is a case of what van Straalen in this volume calls ‘the dilemma of dirty hands’. In order to support such a claim, we would have to show that Aristotle thought that even the best way out of at least some episodes of this conflict would involve the commission of an act that is both right and shameful, and that would involve an independent argument against Nielsen (2007) which would take us too far from our subject. However, insofar as the interpretation proposed here shows that Aristotle not only conceived of possible cases of that dilemma that are not considered either by van Straalen or by Nielsen but also provided us with recommendations on how to act on these cases that neither author mentions, this interpretation does give us reasons to at least reassess the claim first made by Nielsen (p. 273) and reaffirmed in this volume by van Straalen, according to which Aristotle did not recognize any cases that would qualify as cases of ‘the dilemma of dirty hands’.

  30. 30.

    As De Lara remarks in this volume, many authors seem to believe that according to Aristotle living in a polis and engaging in political participation can cause a subjective change in men that transforms individuals who are guided by self-interest into individuals who are guided by the pursuit of the common good. The interpretation offered here is in accordance with and complements the critique of this position offered by De Lara.

References

  • Antiphon. 1954. Discours: suivis des fragments d’Antiphon le sophiste. Translated by Louis Gernet. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1926. Aristotle, with an English Translation: the “Art” of Rhetoric. Translated by John Henry Freese. Loeb Classical Library. London and New York: W. Heinemann and G.P. Putnam’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947. The Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Harris Rackham. Loeb Classical Library. London: W. Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Politics. Translated by H. Rackham. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press and W. Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse. Translated by George A. Kennedy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Posterior Analytics; Topica. Translated by E. S. Forster and Hugh Tredennick. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bates, Clifford Angell. 2013. Law and the Rule of Law and Its Place Relative to Politeia in Aristotle’s Politics. In Aristotle and the Philosophy of Law: Theory, Practice and Justice, ed. Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer and Nuno M.M.S. Coelho, 59–75. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John. 1990. Political Animals and Civic Friendship. In Aristoteles “Politik”: Akten Des XI. Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Günter Patzig, 221–242. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demosthenes. 1935. Demosthenes III: Meidias, Androtion, Aristocrates, Timocrates, Aristogeiton 1 and 2, XXI-XXVI. Translated by J. H. Vince. Loeb Classical Library. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engberg-Pedersen, Troels. 1996. Is There an Ethical Dimension to Aristotelian Rhetoric? In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Amélie Rorty, 16–141. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gagarin, Michael. 1978. Self-Defense in Athenian Homicide Law. Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 19 (2): 111–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimaldi, William M.A. 1972. Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle’s Rhetoric. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag GMBH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, George A. 1991. Introduction. In On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leighton, Stephen R. 1996. Aristotle and the Emotions. In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, 206–237. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, Karen M. 2007. Dirtying Aristotle’s Hands? Aristotle’s Analysis of ‘Mixed Acts’ in the Nicomachean Ethics III, 1. Phronesis 52 (3): 270–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha Craven. 1996. Aristotle on Emotions and Rational Persuasion. In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, 303–323. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, Christof. 2018. Dispassionate Judges Encountering Hotheaded Aristotelians. In Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics, ed. Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer and Nuno M.M.S. Coelho. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C.D.C. 1996. Philosophy, Politics and Rhetoric in Aristotle. In Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, ed. Amélie Rorty, 191–205. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Straalen, Humber. 2018. Remorse and Virtue Ethics. In Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics, ed. Liesbeth Huppes-Cluysenaer and Nuno M.M.S. Coelho. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yack, Bernard. 2006. Rhetoric and Public Reasoning: An Aristotelian Understanding of Political Deliberation. Political Theory 34 (4): 417–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Simão Nascimento .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Nascimento, D.S. (2018). Rhetoric, Emotions and the Rule of Law in Aristotle. In: Huppes-Cluysenaer, L., Coelho, N. (eds) Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 121. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66703-4_19

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66703-4_19

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-66702-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-66703-4

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics