Skip to main content

Burley, Ockham, and English Logicians on Impositio as a Type of Obligatio

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Language of Thought in Late Medieval Philosophy

Part of the book series: Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action ((HSNA,volume 5))

  • 442 Accesses

Abstract

This is a study of how the doctrine of impositio, the endowing of terms and propositions with a new signification, was treated in English obligationes texts from Walter Burley to the end of the fourteenth century. I show that in Burley and Ockham the rules for impositio were closely linked to the solution of insolubilia, but that this emphasis disappeared. I also show that Burley’s doctrines were more honoured on the European continent than in England. I then examine the different doctrines of subsequent English logicians and how they were applied to selected sophismata. Here Roger Swyneshed and Richard Brinkley are particularly important, the first because of his nova responsio, and the second because of his doctrine that speakers can change imposition at will.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The editors of the Summa logicae discuss the authenticity of both tracts (SL, OPh I, 41*–43*), but conclude that they are genuine.

  2. 2.

    Alfonso Maierù’s unpublished edition of Strode’s Insolubilia, based on three manuscripts, shows that Strode referred to “Eland,” and Stephen Read has recently found further evidence that this is the correct version of the name.

  3. 3.

    For manuscripts and editions see Ashworth (2015, 374–375).

  4. 4.

    Subsequent citations to Strode are to the sections of my unpublished edition.

  5. 5.

    See Brinkley (Obligationes, 1–2) for an examination of the evidence.

  6. 6.

    Anonymus, Obligationes cum insolubilibus, f. 49 rb: “Et hec dicta de regulis et suppositionibus sufficiant, habitis regulis et suppositionibus obligationum in hac pertinente.”

  7. 7.

    Brinkley, Obligationes §1: “Post insolubilia sequuntur obligationes. Cuius ordinis haec est causa quod multae obligationes ex principiis insolubilium sunt solvendae.”

  8. 8.

    The treatise ends with the name “Johannes Ecaf” or “Eclif,” but no author with that name has been identified.

  9. 9.

    For more discussion and references see Ashworth (2015) and Dutilh Novaes (2007).

  10. 10.

    Burley, De Obligationibus, 3.84: “[…] omnes responsiones retorquendae sunt ad idem instans.”

  11. 11.

    For discussion of its nature and influence see Ashworth (1996).

  12. 12.

    The translation “conventional” is inaccurate, since ad placitum signification is first instituted at the pleasure of the original impositor (or impositors), and can only then become conventional.

  13. 13.

    Swyneshed, Obligationes §21: “Propter impositionem alicujus propositionis ad illam non est responsio varianda.”

  14. 14.

    Brinkley, Obligationes §9: “[…] cum iste terminus ‘A’ sit significativus ad placitum, in arbitrio eorum est cui intentioni in anima voluerint eam subordinare.”

  15. 15.

    Brinkley, Obligationes §27: “Propter impositionem novam factam circa propositionem est responsio ad eam varianda.”

  16. 16.

    Anonymus, De insolubilibus, 33: “[…] ubicumque est nova impositio pro tanto est responsio varianda.”

  17. 17.

    Alfonso Maierù kindly sent me this section of his unpublished edition of the Introductio.

References

  • Albert of Saxony. (2010). Logik. (H. Berger, Ed. and Trans.). Felix Meiner: Hamburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anonymus. (1483). Logica. Oxford: Theodoric Rood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anonymus. (1524). De obligationibus. In Libellus Sophistarum ad Usum Cantabrigiensium. London: Wynand ‘Wynkyn’ de Worde.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anonymus. (2008). De insolubilibus. In F. Pironet (Ed.), William Heytesbury and the treatment of insolubilia in fourteenth-century England followed by a critical edition of three anonymous Treatises De insolubilibus inspired by Heytesbury. In S. Rahman, T. Tulenheimo & E. Genot (Eds.) Unity, truth and the liar: The modern relevance of medieval solutions to the liar paradox, (pp. 255–333). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anonymus. Obligationes cum insolubilibus secundum usum Oxonie. In Roma, Biblioteca Casanatense MS 85, ff. 43ra–49vb.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, E. Jennifer. (1996). Autour des Obligationes de Roger Swyneshed: la nova responsio. Les Études Philosophiques, 3, 341–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, E. Jennifer. (2015). Richard Billingham and the Oxford Obligationes texts: Restrictions on positio. Vivarium, 53, 372–390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Billingham, Richard. (1994). Ars obligatoria. In Salamanca, Univ. 1735 (II), transcribed by A. D’Ors and J. M. Gambra, Cuadernos del instituto de historia de la lógica, Serie A, no. 2, 33–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinkley, Richard. (1995). Obligationes. In P. V. Spade & G. A. Wilson (Eds.), Richard Brinkley’s ‘Obligationes’. A late fourteenth century treatise on the logic of disputation. Münster: Aschendorff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridan, John. (2004). Johannes Buridanus, Summulae: De practica sophismatum (F. Pironet, Ed.). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burley, Walter. (1963). De Obligationibus. In R. Green (Ed.), The logical treatise “De Obligationibus”: An introduction with critical texts of William of Sherwood and Walter Burley. PhD diss., University of Louvain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buser, William. (1990). Obligationes. In L. Pozzi (Ed.), La coerenza logica nella teoria medioevale delle obbligazioni (con l’edizione del trattato Obligationes di Guglielmo Busa). Parma: Edizioni Zara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, Catarina. (2007). Formalizing medieval logical theories: Suppositio, Consequentiae and Obligationes. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fland, Robert. (1980). Obligationes. In P. V. Spade (Ed.), Robert Fland’s Obligationes: An Edition. Mediaeval Studies 42: 41–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • John of Holland. (1985). John of Holland: Four tracts on logic (Suppositiones, Fallacie, Obligationes, Insolubilia). (E. P. Bos, Ed.). Nijmegen: Ingenium Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavenham, Richard. (1978). Obligationes. In P. V. Spade (Ed.), Richard Lavenham’s Obligationes. Rivista Critica di Storia della Filosofia 33: 225–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ockham, William. (1974). Summa logicae (= SL), Opera Philosophica I (= OPh). (P. Boehner, G. Gál, & S. Brown, Eds.). St. Bonaventure: The Franciscan Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strode, Ralph. Introductio to his complete Logica. (A. Maierù, Ed.). Unpublished edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strode, Ralph. Obligationes. (E. J. Ashworth, Ed.). Unpublished edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swyneshed, Roger. (1977). Obligationes. In P. V. Spade, (Ed.), Roger Swyneshed’s Obligationes: Edition and Comments. Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 44: 243–285.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to E. Jennifer Ashworth .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ashworth, E.J. (2017). Burley, Ockham, and English Logicians on Impositio as a Type of Obligatio . In: Pelletier, J., Roques, M. (eds) The Language of Thought in Late Medieval Philosophy. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66634-1_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics