Skip to main content

Experimenting with Consistency

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 387))

Abstract

This paper discusses logical accounts of the notions of consistency and negation, and in particular explores some potential means of defining consistency and negation when expressed in modal terms. Although this can be done with interesting consequences when starting from classical normal modal logics, some intriguing cases arise when starting from paraconsistent modalities and negations, as in the hierarchy of the so-called cathodic modal paraconsistent systems (cf. Bueno-Soler, Log Univers 4(1):137–160, 2010). The paper also takes some first steps in exploring the philosophical significance of such logical tools, comparing the notions of consistency and negation modally defined with the primitive notions of consistency and negation in the family of Logics of Formal Inconsistency (LFIs), suggesting some experiments on their expressive power.

A foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds, adored by little statesmen and philosophers and divines.

Ralph Waldo Emerson ( 1841 ).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is commonly accepted that (PEx) and (PNC) are taken to be independent, in the sense that neither of them entails the other; see, e.g., Béziau and Franceschetto (2015) for an argument, where it is also argued that a legitimate paraconsistent logic must reject both principles. As we show in Sect. 15.4, however, such a conclusion should be taken cum grano salis.

  2. 2.

    Notice that this definition implies that any classical contradiction is consistent; this is not any problem, however, since ‘consistent’ does not mean ‘true’.

  3. 3.

    A modal system is classified as normal if it contains the Distribution Axiom (K) and the Necessitation Rule (Nec) among its axioms and rules, and as minimal if it has only (K) as a modal axiom and only (Nec) as a modal rule. In this sense, the above defined systems are the minimal normal modal extension of each propositional basis.

  4. 4.

    The obvious example comes from some axiomatizations of geometry where ‘point’ is a primitive concept whose meaning is governed by geometric axioms.

  5. 5.

    M. Fitting in (2017), proposes a formalization of the notion of evidence that defines an embedding of the logic BLE into the modal logic KX4 (a modification of S4). Formally, evidence can be understood as permitting contradictions. It is shown that BLE has both implicit and explicit evidence interpretations in a formal sense.

  6. 6.

    Extracted from http://www.jonahschupbach.com/choiceandinference/2013/08/20/logic-for-lunatics-2/

  7. 7.

    As an analogy, imaginary numbers do no exclude real numbers, but help to explain real numbers and expand the logical space where real numbers exist.

References

  • Akiba, K. (1996). Field on the notion of consistency. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 37(4), 625–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allo, P. (2011). The logic of being informed revisited and revised. Philosophical Studies, 153, 427–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batens, D. (1980). Paraconsistent extensional propositional logics. Logique et analyse, 90–91, 195–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y. (2002). S5 is a paraconsistent logic and so is first-order classical logic. Logical Studies, 9, 301–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y. (2003). New light on the square of oppositions and its nameless corner. Logical Investigations, 10, 218–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau, J.-Y., & Franceschetto, A. (2015). Strong three-valued paraconsistent logics. In J.-Y. Béziau, M. Chakraborty, & S. Dutta (Eds.), New Directions in Paraconsistent Logic: 5th WCP, Kolkata, Feb 2014 (pp. 131–145). New Delhi: Springer India.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brunner, A., & Carnielli, W. (2005). Anti-intuitionism and paraconsistency. Journal of Applied Logic, 3(1), 161–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno-Soler, J. (2009). Completeness and incompleteness for anodic modal logics. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 4(5), 291–310. Pre-print available at: ftp://logica.cle.unicamp.br/pub/e-prints/vol.9,n.5,2009.pdf

  • Bueno-Soler, J. (2010). Two semantical approaches to paraconsistent modalities. Logica Universalis, 4(1), 137–160. Pre-print available at: http://www.cle.unicamp.br/e-prints/vol{\_}9,n{\_}6,2009.html

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A. (2011). The single-minded pursuit of consistency and its weakness. Studia Logica, 97(1), 81–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Coniglio, M. E. (2016a). Paraconsistent set theory by predicating on consistency. Journal of Logic and Computation, 26(1), 97–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Coniglio, M. E. (2016b). Paraconsistent logic: Consistency, contradiction and negation (Logic, epistemology and the unity of science). Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., Coniglio, M. E., & Marcos, J. (2007). Logics of formal inconsistency. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 14, pp. 1–93) Amsterdam: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Marcos, J. (2002). A taxonomy of C-systems. In W. A. Carnielli, M. E. Coniglio, & I. M. L. D’Ottaviano (Eds.), Paraconsistency the logical way to the inconsistent (Lecture notes in pure and applied mathematics, Vol. 228, pp. 1–94) New York: Marcel Dekker.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coniglio, M. E., & Peron, N. M. (2009). A paraconsistentist approach to Chisholm’s paradox. Principia, 13(3), 299–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnielli, W. A., & Rodrigues, A. (2016). An epistemic approach to paraconsistency: A logic of evidence and truth. Pre-print available from ftp://ftp.cle.unicamp.br/pub/e-prints/vol.15,n{\_}5,2015.pdf

    Google Scholar 

  • Emerson, R. W. (1841). Essays. First series. “Self-Reliance”. http://www.emersoncentral.com/selfreliance.htm

  • Field, H. (1991). Metalogic and modality. Philosophical Studies, 62, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2017). Paraconsistent logic, evidence, and justification. Studia Logica. Issn:1572-8730. doi:10.1007/s11225-017-9714-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2011). The philosophy of information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, L. (1949). Fragments of the propositional calculus. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 42–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapsner, A., Miller, D., & Dyckhoff, R. (2014). Report on Kalman Cohen’s 1954 Oxford thesis on alternative systems of logic. In J.-Y. B’eziau (Ed.), Handbook of the 5th World Congress of Paraconsistency. Online: http://www.paraconsistency.org/book/Handbook-WCP5.pdf

  • Lemmon, E. J., & Scott, D. (1977). An introduction to modal logic. In K. Segerberg (Ed.), The Lemmon notes. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcos, J. (2005). Modality and paraconsistency. Logical Studies, 9, 213–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mortensen, C. (2016). Change and inconsistency. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1980). Truth and probability. In H. E. Kyburg & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (pp. 23–52). Huntington: R. E. Krieger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vineberg, S. (2001). The notion of consistency for partial belief. Philosophical Studies, 102, 281–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, G. (2015). Is there a logic of information? Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 27(1), 95–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. N. (1981). Inconsistency and contradiction. Mind, 360, 600–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wójtowicz, K. (2001). Some remarks on Hartry Fields notion of “logical consistency”. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 9, 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Both authors acknowledge support from FAPESP Thematic Project LogCons 2010/51038-0, Brazil, and the second author thanks a research grant from The National Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq), Brazil. We are indebted to David Gilbert, Raymundo Morado, and Peter Verdee for discussions that helped to improve this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juliana Bueno-Soler .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bueno-Soler, J., Carnielli, W. (2017). Experimenting with Consistency. In: Markin, V., Zaitsev, D. (eds) The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic. Synthese Library, vol 387. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66162-9_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics