Skip to main content

Non-Aristotelian Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 252 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 386))

Abstract

This chapter deals with attempts, contemporary with Vasil’ev’s own, to develop non-Aristotelian logics that present affinities with imaginary logic. Already in Aristotle’s work there are passages that press in the direction of a non-Aristotelian logic, in so far as they show that the syllogism is independent of the principle of contradiction. Some Aristotelian scholars like Heinrich Maier and Isaac Husik had drawn attention to such passages. Husik in particular proposes, on the basis of them and of Herbert Spencer’s philosophy, a hypothetical logic in which the syllogism is independent of the principle of contradiction; judgments are allowed that assert contradictory predicates of the same subject; contradictory objects are subjects of true propositions; and a hypothetical world is assumed, for which such a different logic would be valid. Jan Łukasiewicz was familiar with Maier and Husik’s works. He subjects to rigorous critique the Aristotelian principle of contradiction, claiming that it is uncertain, that it is not a simple, ultimate and necessary principle, and that in relation to contradictory objects it is actually false. Łukasiewicz took the notion of contradictory objects from Meinong, according to whom such objects — which are overdetermined objects of higher order in which a surplus of determinations inheres, amongst which there is a relation of incompatibility — can occur as genuine subjects in true propositions. The chapter concludes with an outline of the controversy between Meinong and Russell, with which Łukasiewicz was thoroughly acquainted, and his proposal of a non-Aristotelian logic in which the principle of contradiction is insignificant.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Notes

  1. 1.

    Vasil’ev (1911/1989: 126).

  2. 2.

    Vasil’ev (1912: 212 = 1989: 59 [2003: 131]).

  3. 3.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 8).

  4. 4.

    Aristotle , An. post. i 11, 77a10–12. Both the interpolation of Arabic and Roman numerals in Aristotle’s text and the italics, here and in later quotations, are mine.

  5. 5.

    As opposed to traditional logic, in which the subject precedes the predicate, in Aristotle AaC means ‘A belongs to all the C’s,ʼ that is ‘All C are A.’

  6. 6.

    Cf. Ross (1949: 542, ad i 11. 77a10), Bocheński (1970 3: 72), McKirahan (1992: 77), Barnes (1994 2: 145, ad i 11. 77a10); but cf. also Husik (1906: 219) and Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 93; 1910b: 32 [1971: 504]).

  7. 7.

    Cf. Aristotle , An. post. i 7, 75b7–14.

  8. 8.

    Cf. Aristotle, An. post. i 10, 76a37–b2; 11, 77a23–24; Metaph. γ 3, 1005a25–27. Cf. also McKirahan (1992: 71–73).

  9. 9.

    A translation of lines 77a15–18 conforming more closely to the interpretation I propose is as follows: “For if you are given (2) something of which it is true to say that it is a man, (2′) even if not-a-man is also true of it, then provided only that it is true to say (1) that man is an animal and not not-an-animal, it will be true to say (3) that Callias, (2″) even if he is not-Callias, is nevertheless an animal, and not not-an-animal.

  10. 10.

    Aristotle , An. post. i 11, 77a12–21. For a commentary on the passage cf. Ross (1949: 542–543, ad I 11. 77a10–21), Mignucci (1975: 221–237; 2007: 185–187 ad 77a10–21), McKirahan (1992: 76–79), Barnes (1994 2: 145–147, ad i 11. 77a10).

  11. 11.

    Recently, some scholars have hypothesized a paraconsistent approach to the Aristotelian syllogistic. da Costa , Beziau & Bueno (1998: 142–50; cf. also da Costa , Krause & Bueno 2007: 828–829) proposed a paraconsistent interpretation of traditional syllogistic built on the monadic paraconsistent first-order C 1 * logic. Priest (2005: 132) claimed, with reference to An. pr. ii 15, that syllogistic is paraconsistent. Finally, in a more detailed way through the analysis of both An. pr. ii 15 and An. post. i 11, Gomes & D’Ottaviano (2010) showed that Aristotle ’s theory of syllogism is a paraconsistent theory in a broad sense.

  12. 12.

    Cf. Peirce (1880: CP 3.192–193; W 3, 176–178).

  13. 13.

    Cf. Husik (1906: 217, fn. 1).

  14. 14.

    Maier (1896–1900: ii.2, 238).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Maier (1896–1900: ii.2, 239 fn. 3).

  16. 16.

    Cf. Waitz (1844–1846: ii, 328–329, ad 77 a 10).

  17. 17.

    Husik (1906: 219). The original text by Waitz (1844–1846: ii, 328) runs: “Principium contradictionis quod dicitur in ipsam demonstrationem non assumitur, nisi etiam in conclusione expressum esse debeat.”

  18. 18.

    Husik (1906: 219). The interpolation of Arabic and Roman numerals in Husik’s text, here and in later quotations, is mine.

  19. 19.

    Husik (1906: 219–220).

  20. 20.

    Cf. Husik (1906: 215–216).

  21. 21.

    Spencer (1865/1966: 192; 1873 2: 423–424); cited also in Mill (1872 8/1973–1974: ii, vii, § 5, pp. 278–279; 1872 4/1979: 381 n.).

  22. 22.

    Cf. Spencer (1865/1966: 213).

  23. 23.

    Cf. Spencer (1865/1966: 205, 208).

  24. 24.

    For more details on Mill and Spencer ’s conceptions regarding the principles of contradiction and of excluded middle see Raspa (1999b: 89–97).

  25. 25.

    Husik (1906: 216).

  26. 26.

    Ibid.

  27. 27.

    Husik (1906: 217).

  28. 28.

    Cf. ibid.

  29. 29.

    Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 10, 149; 1910b: 16 [1971: 488]).

  30. 30.

    Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 11, 149; 1910b: 16–17 [1971: 488]).

  31. 31.

    Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 12, 149; 1910b: 18 [1971: 488]).

  32. 32.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 16–18; 1910b: 17 [1971: 489]). On the distinction between equivalence and synonymity see Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 15–16).

  33. 33.

    Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 18); cf. also Aristotle, Metaph. γ 7, 1011b26–27.

  34. 34.

    Cf. Trendelenburg (1870 3: i, 23, 31–32; ii, 174), Ueberweg (1882 5: § 77, 234–237), Sigwart (1904 3: i, § 23, pp. 188–191 [1895: i, 139–141]).

  35. 35.

    Maier (1896–1900: i, 41–45, esp. p. 42 fn. 1) had indicated, for each of the formulations distinguished by Łukasiewicz , the self-same passages subsequently examined by the latter.

  36. 36.

    Cf. Twardowski (1894 [1977]).

  37. 37.

    Cf. Meinong (1899: GA ii, 381 ff. [1978: 141 ff.]). On the relationship between Meinong’s and Twardowski ’s conceptions regarding the distinction between act, content and object see Raspa (2016: 39 ff.).

  38. 38.

    Here I give only a sketch of Łukasiewicz ’s concept and criticism of the principle of contradiction; for more details on this topic see Raspa (1999a; 1999b: 53 ff., 110 ff., 139 ff., 257 ff.; 2000).

  39. 39.

    Mill (1872 8/1973–1974: ii, vii, § 5, pp. 277–278).

  40. 40.

    Cf. Mill (1872 8/1973–1974: ii, vii, § 5, pp. 278–279; 1872 4/1979: 381 fn. *).

  41. 41.

    Husserl (1900–1901: i, 81 [2001: i, 58]).

  42. 42.

    Cf. Husserl (1900–1901: i, 81–82 [2001: i, 58]).

  43. 43.

    A lecture on “Teza Husserla na stosunku logiki do psychologii [Husserl’s Thesis on the Relationship between Logic and Psychology]” held by Łukasiewicz at the Polish Philosophical Society testifies to this (for a short report of the lecture, cf. Łukasiewicz 1904). He speaks more at length about this subject in “Logika a psychologia [Logic and Psychology]” (cf. Łukasiewicz 1907). Cf. also Borkowski and Słupecki (1958: 46–47), Kuderowicz (1988: 142–143), Sobociński (1956: 8–9), and Woleński (1989: 194).

  44. 44.

    Aristotle , Metaph. γ 3, 1005b25–26.

  45. 45.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 30–34; 1910b: 21 and fn. 1–2 [1971: 492–493 and fn. 6–7]).

  46. 46.

    Łukasiewicz’s criticism of Aristotle’s psychological formulation of the principle of contradiction follows another path but reaches the same conclusion. Łukasiewicz takes into account the passages of Metaph. γ 3, 1005b26–32 — read in connection with Int. 14, 23a27–39 — and γ 6, 1011b15–22, which he interprets as two complementary parts of a single attempt conducted by Aristotle to prove the validity of the principle of contradiction even for beliefs. The result achieved by Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 19 ff.; 1910b: 18 ff. [1971: 489 ff.]) is that the impossibility for a subject to have contradictory beliefs at the same time is demonstrable only provided that we treat these as if they were sentences for which the alternative true or false is valid. Therefore, the psychological formulation of the principle of contradiction is nothing but a consequence of the logical one. In such a way, Aristotle would fall into that error which is the exact converse of “psychologism in logic,” that is, “logicism in psychology.” However, sentences are not beliefs. The latter are “psychical phenomena” and, as such, are always positive. Consequently, it can never happen that two beliefs are in contradiction like an affirmation and its negation. Such a thing would involve that the same belief should be present and at the same time should not be present in the same mind, but a belief that does not exist cannot be in contradiction with another. In reality, while sentences mean that something is or is not and while they are in a relation of correspondence or of non-correspondence with their own objects or facts, so that they can be true or false, beliefs have a different structure. As psychical phenomena, they do not assert simply that something is or is not but they rather represent an intentional relation with something: without something that is intended, Łukasiewicz says, there is no belief. This intentional relation consists of two parts: the act of belief and the Meinongian objective (see Sect. 6.6). The expression in words or in signs of the second part of the intentional relation is the sentence, which can be true or false, but the first part does not refer to any fact, so we can say that it is neither true nor false. Then, beliefs are not purely logical objects. Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 25, 29–30).

  47. 47.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 49 ff.; 1910b: 22 [1971: 493–494]).

  48. 48.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 57 ff.; 1910b: 23 [1971: 494]).

  49. 49.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 102, 109 ff.; 1910b: 35 [1971: 506–507]).

  50. 50.

    Cf. Raspa (1999b: 80 ff. and passim).

  51. 51.

    By principle of the syllogism Łukasiewicz means, following Couturat (1905: 8), the law of transitivity: ((ab) ∧ (bc)) → (ac); cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 155).

  52. 52.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 95, 191–192; 1910b: 32–33 [1971: 504]).

  53. 53.

    According to Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 91 and fn. *), Maier did not recognize the fundamental significance this passage has for Aristotle ’s entire system of logic, while Husik, notwithstanding “the correctness of his central idea,” expressed his views in a very imprecise manner. The truth of the matter is that Łukasiewicz is indebted both to Maier and, above all, to Husik.

  54. 54.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 93–95). See also Bocheński (1970 3: 71–72), who shares Łukasiewicz ’s interpretation, and in contrast Zwergel (1972: 21–28) and Seddon (1981: 203–206), who disagree with it.

  55. 55.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 96); but cf. also Peirce (1878: CP 5.403; W 3, 266–267), whom we have already alluded to (see Sect. 2.3) and to whom we shall return presently (see Sect. 5.4 fn. 61 and Sect. 5.6).

  56. 56.

    Cf. Meinong (1899: GA ii, 386 [1978: 144]).

  57. 57.

    Meinong (1904: GA ii, 489 [1960: 82]).

  58. 58.

    Meinong (1904: GA ii, 494 [1960: 86]).

  59. 59.

    On this controversy, only touched on in passing here, cf. Griffin & Jacquette (eds., 2009). A careful reconstruction of the dispute is provided by Farrell Smith (1985). I have dealt with it in Raspa (1995/1996: 181 ff.; 1999b: 247 ff.), where the relevant literature on the topic is listed.

  60. 60.

    Cf. Russell (1905b/1973: 105).

  61. 61.

    Cf. Russell (1905b/1973: 115–116). On the notion of existence here presupposed see Russell (1905a/1973: 98–99).

  62. 62.

    Cf. Meinong (1900: GA i, 470; 1906: GA v, 389).

  63. 63.

    Cf. Kant (1781 1–17872: A 151 = B 190–191 [1998: 280]). Cf. also Raspa (2015: 137).

  64. 64.

    Ernst Mally (GA i, 494, Zusatz 17) also observed that an object which possesses the only determinations to be a mountain and to be golden, and for the rest it is ontologically incomplete in every other respect, cannot exist or be real.

  65. 65.

    Russell (1905b/1973: 117).

  66. 66.

    Cf. Meinong (1915: GA vi, 180).

  67. 67.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 110 and fn.; 1910b: 35 and fn. 1 [1971: 506 and fn. 14]).

  68. 68.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1957 2: 12, 46–47, 73–74).

  69. 69.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1957 2: 46, 88).

  70. 70.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1958 2 [1963: 67–68]; 1937 [1970: 243, 248]). Cf. also Sobociński (1956: 11 ff.) and Jordan (1963: 13). In 1910, Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 8, 9) used the term ‘metalogical,’ but not in the sense that it later acquired and still retains in mathematical logic today.

  71. 71.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1910a/1987: 95–101); a glance at the same argument can be detected also in Łukasiewicz (1910b: 33). For further details cf. Raspa (1999a: 76 ff.; 1999b: 262 ff.).

  72. 72.

    Cf. Łukasiewic z (1910c [1987]; 1913: 32–33).

  73. 73.

    Cf. Łukasiewicz (1920 [1970: 87–81]; 1930/1988: 107–109 [1970: 164–166]; 1961: 125 [1970: 126]).

  74. 74.

    Cf. Jaśkowski (1948 [1969]). In his brief historical survey of the problem followed by the exposition of the known solutions, Jaśkowski (1948: 57 ff. [1969: 143 ff.]) ignores Vasil’ev’s point of view. Independently of Jaśkowski , Newton C. A. da Costa (1963; 1964a; 1964b; 1964c; 1974) also began to study inconsistent and non-trivial systems. Cf. also D’Ottaviano (1990b: 20 ff.).

  75. 75.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1910: 8 = 1989: 17).

  76. 76.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 80 = 1989: 122 [1993: 350]).

  77. 77.

    Cf. Mally (1909).

  78. 78.

    Itelson ’s point of view is referred to in Couturat (1904: 1038–1039): “celle-ci est la science des êtres, des objets existants, tandis que la Logique est la science de tous les objets réels ou non, possibles ou impossibles, abstraction faite de leur existence (De rebus omnibus et de quibusdam aliis). Ainsi la Logique est délivrée de toutes les difficultés d’ordre métaphysique; elle n’a pas à s’occuper des jugements d’existence, ils sont extra-logiques (Cogito; argument ontologique). Et pourtant la Logique a une valeur objective universelle, puisqu’elle s’applique, en particulier, aux objets réels; ainsi s’explique que la nature obéisse aux lois de la Logique. La Logique ne s’occupe même pas du vrai et du faux, car le vrai et le faux sont des qualités de la pensée, et non des objets: la Logique porte sur les relations formelles des objets, non sur la relation de la pensée à ses objets.”

  79. 79.

    Cf. Renouvier (1876).

  80. 80.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1911/1989: 127; 1912: 222 = 1989: 68 [2003: 140]; 1912–1913a: 61 = 1989: 102 [1993: 335]).

Bibliography

  • Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione. Recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit L. Minio-Paluello. Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19745 (19491).

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotelis Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. D. Ross, Praefatione et appendice auxit L. Minio-Paluello. Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19824 (19641).

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotelis Metaphysica. Recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. Jaeger. Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19694 (19571).

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, Jonathan. 19942. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics. Translated with a Commentary by J. Barnes, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press (19751).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bocheński, Józef M. 19703. Formale Logik. Freiburg – München: Alber (19561).

    Google Scholar 

  • Borkowski, Ludwik & Jerzy Słupecki. 1958. The Logical Works of J. Łukasiewicz. Studia Logica 8: 7–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, Otávio. 2017. Vasiliev and the Foundations of Logic. In Nikolai Vasiliev’s Logical Legacy and Modern Logic. Ed. by D. Zaitsev and V. Markin. Dordrecht: Springer (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • Couturat, Louis. 1904. ii me Congrès de Philosophie — Genève. ii. Logique et Philosophie des Sciences. Séances de section et séances générales. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 12(6): 1037–1077.

    Google Scholar 

  • Couturat, Louis. 1905. L’Algèbre de la Logique. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et Cie (= «Scientia», Phys.-mathém. Classe, No. 24).

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A. 1963. Calculs propositionnels pour les systèmes formels inconsistants. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie de Sciences de Paris 257: 3790–3793.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A. 1964a. Calculs des prédicats pour les systèmes formels inconsistants. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie de Sciences de Paris 258: 27–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A. 1964b. Calculs des prédicats avec égalité pour les systèmes formels inconsistants. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie de Sciences de Paris 258: 1111–1113.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A. 1964c. Calculs de descriptions pour les systèmes formels inconsistants. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie de Sciences de Paris 258: 1366–1368.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A. 1974. On the theory of inconsistent formal systems. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15(4): 497–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C. A., Jean-Yves Béziau & Otávio Bueno. 1998. Elementos da teoria paraconsistente de conjunto [Elements of the Paraconsistent Set Theory]. Campinas, SP: Centro de Lógica, Epistemologia e História da Ciência, Universidade Estadual de Campinas. (Coleção CLE, v. 23).

    Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, Newton C.A., Décio Krause & Otávio Bueno. 2007. Paraconsistent Logics and Paraconsistency. In Philosophy of Logic. Ed. by Dale Jacquette, 791–911. Amsterdam et al.: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Ottaviano, Itala M. Loffredo. 1990. On the Development of Paraconsistent Logic and da Costa’s Work. The Journal of Non-Classical Logic 7(1/2): 9–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrell Smith, Janet. 1985. The Russell-Meinong Debate. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45: 305–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomes, Evandro Luís & Itala M. Loffredo D’Ottaviano. 2010. Aristotle’s Theory of Deduction and Paraconsistency. Principia: Revista Internacional de Epistemologia 14 (1): 71–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, Nicholas & Dale Jacquette (eds.). 2009. Russell vs. Meinong: The Legacy of “On Denoting”. New York – London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husik, Isaac. 1906. Aristotle on the Law of Contradiction and the Basis of the Syllogism. Mind n.s. 15: 215–222. Repr. in Husik, I., Philosophical Essays. Ancient, Mediaeval & Modern. Ed. by Milton C. Nahm and Leo Strauss, 87–95. Oxford: B. Blackwell, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1900–1901. Logische Untersuchungen. Halle a. S.: M. Niemeyer. In Husserliana. Bd. xviii: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Hrsg. von Elmar Holenstein. Den Haag: M. Nijhoff, 1975; Bde. xix/1–2: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Hrsg. von Ursula Panzer. Den Haag: M. Nijhoff, 1984. Russian transl.: Husserl 1909. Engl. transl.: Husserl 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001. Logical Investigations. 2 vols. Translated by John N. Findlay from the Second German edition of Logische Untersuchungen, with a new Preface by Michael Dummett and edited with a new Introduction by Dermot Moran. London and New York: Routledge (19701).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaśkowski, Stanisław. 1948. Rachunek zdań dla systemów dedukcyjnych sprzecznych. In Studia Societatis Scientiarum Torunensis. Sectio A, vol. i, Nr. 5, Toruń, pp. 57–77. Engl. transl.: Jaśkowski 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, Zbigniew A. 1963. Philosophy and Ideology. The Development of Philosophy and Marxism-Leninism in Poland since the Second World War. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 17811–17872. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Riga: J. F. Hartknoch, 17811; in Kants gesammelte Schriften. Bd. iv, 1–252. 17872; in Kants gesammelte Schriften. Bd. iii. Engl. transl.: Kant 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuderowicz, Zbigniew. 1988. Das philosophische Ideengut Polens. Bonn: Bouvier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1904. Teza Husserla na stosunku logiki do psychologii [Husserl’s Thesis on the Relationship between Logic and Psychology]. Przegląd Filozoficzny 7: 476–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1907. Logika a psychologia [Logic and Psychology]. Przegląd Filozoficzny 10: 489–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1910a/1987. O zasadzie sprzeczności u Arystotelesa. Studium krytyczne [On the Principle of Contradiction in Aristotle. A Critical Study]. Kraków: Polska Akademia Umiejętności. Rev. and ed. by Jan Woleński. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1910b. O zasadzie sprzeczności u Arystotelesa (Über den Satz des Widerspruchs bei Aristoteles). Bulletin international de l’Académie des Sciences de Cracovie. Classe de philologie. Classe d’histoire et de philosophie, 15–38. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1910c. O zasadzie wyłączonego środka [On the Principle of the Excluded Middle]. Przegląd Filozoficzny 13: 372–373. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1920. O logice trójwartościowej [On Three-Valued Logic]. Ruch Filozoficzny 5: 170–171. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1970: 87–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1930/1988. Philosophische Bemerkungen zu mehrwertigen Systemen des Aussagenkalküls. In Comptes rendus des séances de la Société des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie, cl. iii, 23: 51–77. Repr. in Logischer Rationalismus. Philosophische Schriften der Lemberg-Warschauer Schule. Hrsg. von David Pearce und Jan Woleński, 100–119. Frankfurt a. M.: Athenäum, 1988. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1970: 153–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1937. W obronie logistyki. Myśl katolicka wobec logiki współczesnej [In Defence of Logistic. The Catholic Thought and Contemporary Logic]. Studia Gnesnensia 15: 22 pp. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1970: 236–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 19572. Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. 2nd enl. ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press (19511).

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 19582. Elementy logiki matematycznej. 2 wyd., Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe (Warszawa: Koło Matematyczno-Fizyczne Słuchaczów Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego, 19291). Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1961. O determinizmie [On Determinism]. In Łukasiewicz, J., Z zagadnień logiki i filozofii. Pisma wybrane [Problems of Logic and Philosophy. Selected Writings]. Wyboru dokonał, wstępem i przypisami opatrzył Jerzy Słupecki, 114–126. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Engl. transl.: Łukasiewicz 1970: 110–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1963. Elements of Mathematical Logic. Translated by Olgierd Wojtasiewicz. Warszawa – Oxford: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe – Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1970. Selected Works. Ed. by Ludwik Borkowski. Amsterdam – Warszawa: North-Holland P. C. – Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1971. On the Principle of Contradiction in Aristotle. Translated by Vernon Wedin. Review of Metaphysics 24(3): 485–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Łukasiewicz, Jan. 1987. On the Principle of the Excluded Middle. Translated by Jan Woleński and Peter Simons. History and Philosophy of Logic 8: 67–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Heinrich. 1896–1900. Die Syllogistik des Aristoteles. 3 Bde. Tübingen: Verlag der H. Lauppschen Buchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mally, Ernst. 1909. Gegenstandstheorie und Mathematik. In Bericht über den iii. Internationalen Kongress für Philosophie zu Heidelberg (1–5.ix.1908). Hrsg. von Theodor Elsenhans, 881–886. Heidelberg: Carl Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan, Richard D., Jr. 1992. Principles and Proofs. Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Science. Princeton (N.J.): Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1899. Über Gegenstände höherer Ordnung und deren Verhältnis zur inneren Wahrnehmung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane 21: 182–272. Repr. in Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, ii, 377–471. Engl. transl.: Meinong 1978: 137–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1900. Abstrahieren und Vergleichen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 24: 34–82. Repr. in Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, i, 443–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1904. Über Gegenstandstheorie. In Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie. Hrsg. von A. Meinong, 1–50. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Repr. in Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, ii, 481–530. Engl. transl.: Meinong 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1906. Über die Erfahrungsgrundlagen unseres Wissens. Berlin: J. Springer (= Abhandlungen zur Didaktik und Philosophie der Naturwissenschaft. Sonderhefte der Zeitschrift für physikalischen und chemischen Unterricht. i, 6, 379–491). Repr. in Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, v, 367–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1915. Über Möglichkeit und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Beiträge zur Gegenstandstheorie und Erkenntnistheorie, Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Repr. in Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe, vi, xvxxii, 1–728, 777–808.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1960. The Theory of Objects. Translated by I. Levi, D. B. Terrell, and R. M. Chisholm. In Realism and the Background of Phenomenology. Ed. by Roderick M. Chisholm, 76–117. Glencoe (Ill.): Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1968–1978. Alexius Meinong Gesamtausgabe. Hrsg. von Rudolf Haller und Rudolf Kindinger gemeinsam mit Roderick M. Chisholm. Graz: Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, Alexius. 1978. On Objects of Higher Order and Husserl’s Phenomenology. Ed. by Marie-Luise Schubert Kalsi. The Hague – Boston – London: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mignucci, Mario. 1975. L’argomentazione dimostrativa in Aristotele. Commento agli Analitici secondi, i. Padova: Antenore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mignucci, Mario. 2007. Aristotele, Analitici secondi. Organon iv. A cura di M. Mignucci, introduzione di Jonathan Barnes. Roma – Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1872a8/1973–1974. A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation. 2 vols. London: Longmans, Green, Roberts, and Dyer (London: Parker, 18431). In Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Vols. viiviii. Ed. by John M. Robson, with an introduction by R. F. McRae. Toronto and Buffalo: University of Toronto Press — London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973–1974. Russian transl.: Mill 1878.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1872b4/1979. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy, and of The Principal Philosophical Questions Discussed in his Writings. London: Longmans, Green, Roberts, and Dyer (18651). Repr. in Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Vol. ix. Ed. by John M. Robson, with an introduction by Alan Ryan. Toronto and Buffalo: University of Toronto Press – London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1878. How to Make Our Ideas Clear. The Popular Science Monthly 12: 286–302. In Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 5.388–410; and in Writings of Charles S. Peirce. Vol. 3, 257–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1931–1935–1958. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vols. ivi ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931–1935. Vols. viiviii ed. by Arthur W. Burks. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1880. On the Algebra of Logic. American Journal of Mathematics 3: 15–57. In Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 3.154–251; and in Writings of Charles S. Peirce. Vol. 4, pp. 163–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1982 ff. Writings of Charles S. Peirce. A Chronological Edition. Ed. by «Peirce Edition Project». Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham. 2005. Paraconsistency and Dialetheism. In Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Logic. Vol. 8: The Many-valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic. Ed. by Dov M. Gabbay and John Woods, 129–204. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 1999a. Łukasiewicz on the Principle of Contradiction. Journal of Philosophical Research 24: 57–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 1999b. In-contraddizione. Il principio di contraddizione alle origini della nuova logica. Trieste: Edizioni Parnaso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 2000. Łukasiewicz versus Aristotele. Paradigmi 18(53): 413–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 2015. Contraddizione, pensabilità, impossibilità. In L’impossibilità normativa. A cura di Paolo Di Lucia e Stefano Colloca, 127–148. Milano: LED. URL: http://www.ledonline.it/ledonline/761-impossibilita-normativa/761-impossibilita-normativa-raspa.pdf.

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 1995/1996. Su ciò che non esiste. Da Bolzano a Meinong: un excursus nella filosofia austriaca. Studi Urbinati. B: Scienze umane e sociali 67: 115–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 2016. Meinong und Twardowski – Orte und Worte Zur Einleitung. In Alexius Meinong und Kazimierz Twardowski, Der Briefwechsel, herausgegeben und eingeleitet von Venanzio Raspa, 1–74. Berlin – Boston: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renouvier, Charles. 1876. Uchronie (l’utopie dans l’histoire), esquisse historique apocryphe du développement de la civilisation européenne tel qu’il n’a pas été, tel qu’il aurait pu être. Paris: Bureau de la Critique philosophique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, William D. 1949. Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics. A revised Text with Introduction and Commentary by W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1905a/1973. The Existential Import of Propositions. Mind n. s. 14: 398–401. Repr. in Russell, B., Essays in Analysis. Ed. by Douglas Lackey, 98–102. London: Allen and Unwin, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1905b/1956. On Denoting. Mind n. s. 14: 479–493. Repr. in Russell, B., Essays in Analysis. Ed. by Douglas Lackey, 103–119. London: Allen and Unwin, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seddon, Frederick A., Jr. 1981. The Principle of Contradiction in Metaphysics, Gamma. The New Scholasticism 55(1): 191–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigwart, Christoph. 1895. Logic. 2 vols. Second edition, revised and enlarged. Translated by Helen Dendy. London – New York: Swan Sonnenschein & Co. – MacMillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigwart, Christoph. 19043. Logik. 2 Bde., dritte durchgesehene Auflage. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Tübingen: Lauppsche Buchhandlung, 1873–18781; Freiburg i. B.: Mohr, 1889–18932). Engl. transl.: Sigwart 1895. Russian transl.: Sigwart 1908–1909.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobociński, Bolesław. 1956. In Memoriam Jan Łukasiewicz (1878–1956). Philosophical Studies 6: 3–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, Herbert. 1865/1966. Mill versus Hamilton — The Test of Truth. Fortnightly Review 1: 531–550. Repr. in Spencer, H., Essays: Scientific, Political & Speculative. Vol. ii, 188–217. Osnabrück: Zeller 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, Herbert. 18732. The Principles of Psychology. Vol. ii. New York: D. Appleton and Company (London: Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans, 18551).

    Google Scholar 

  • Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf. 18703. Logische Untersuchungen. 2 Bde. 3. vermehrte Auflage, Leipzig: Hirzel (Berlin: Bethge, 18401; 2. ergänzte Auflage, Leipzig: Hirzel, 18622).

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski, Kazimierz. 1894. Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellungen. Eine psychologische Untersuchung. Wien: Hölder. Mit einer Einleitung von Rudolf Haller. München – Wien: Philosophia, 1982. Engl. transl.: Twardowski 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ueberweg, Friedrich. 18825. System der Logik und Geschichte der logischen Lehren. 5., verbesserte Auflage, bearbeitet und hrsg. von Jürgen Bona Meyer. Bonn: A. Marcus (18571, 18652, 18683, 18744).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1910. O chastnykh suzhdeniiakh, o treugol’nike protivopolozhnostei, o zakone iskliuchennogo chetvertogo [On Particular Judgments, the Triangle of Oppositions, and the Law of Excluded Fourth]. Uchenye zapiski Imperatorskogo Kazanskogo Universiteta [Scientific Memoirs of the Imperial University of Kazan], year lxxvii, book 10 (October 1910). Kazan: Tipolitografia of the Imperial University, pp. 1–47 [= О частных суждениях, о треугольнике противоположностей, о законе исключенного четвертoго // Ученыe записки Императорскoго Казанскoго Университета, Год lxxvii, десятая книга, 1910, октябрь. Казань: Типолитография Императорсoго Университета, c. 1–47]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 12–53. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 12–53].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1911/1989. Voobrazhaemaia logika (Konspekt lektsii) [Imaginary Logic (Conspectus of a Lecture)]. Kazan: Obshchestvo Narodnykh Universitetov, 6 pp. [= Воображаемая логика (Конспект лекции). Казань: Общество Народных Университетов, 1911, с. 6]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 126–130. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 126–130].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1912. Voobrazhaemaia (nearistoteleva) logika [Imaginary (non-Aristotelian) Logic]. Zhurnal Ministerstva Narodnogo Prosveshcheniia [The Journal of the Ministry of Education]. New series, xl (August 1912). Sankt-Peterburg: Senatokaia tipografiia, pp. 207–246 [= Воображаемая (неаристотелева) логика // Журнал Министерства Народного Просвещения. Новая серия, Ч. xl. 1912, август. Санкт-Петербург: Сенатокая типография, c. 207–246]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 53–94. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 53–94].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1912–1913a. Logika i metalogika [Logic and Metalogic]. Logos. Mezhdunarodnyi ezhegodnik po filosofii kul’tury. Russkoe izdanie [Logos. Internatonal Yearbook of Philosophy of Culture. Russian edition] 1–2: 53–81 [= Логика и металогика // Логос. Международный ежегодник по философии культуры. Русское издание. 1912–1913. Кн. 1–2, c. 53–81]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 94–123. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 94–123].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1989. Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov. Moskva: Nauka [= Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1993. Logic and Metalogic. Translated by Vladimir L. Vasyukov. Axiomathes 4(3): 329–351. Engl. transl. of “Logika i metalogika”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 2003. Imaginary (non-Aristotelian) Logic. Translated by Roger Vergauwen and Evgeny A. Zaytsev. Logique et Analyse 46(182): 127–163. Engl. transl. of “Voobrazhaemaia (nearistoteleva) logika”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waitz, Theodor. 1844–1846. Aristotelis Organon Graece. Novis codicum auxiliis adiutus recognovit, scholiis ineditis et commentario instruxit Theodorus Waitz. Lipsiae: Sumtibus Hahnianis. Repr. Aalen: Scientia Verlag, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woleński, Jan. 1989. Logic and Philosophy in the Lvov-Warsaw School. Dordrecht – Boston – London: Kluwer, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwergel, Herbert A. 1972. Principium contradictionis. Die aristotelische Begründung des Prinzips vom zu vermeidenden Widerspruch und die Einheit der Ersten Philosophie. Meisenheim am Glan: Hain.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Raspa, V. (2017). Non-Aristotelian Logic. In: Thinking about Contradictions. Synthese Library, vol 386. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66086-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics