Skip to main content

The Historical and Cultural Context

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Thinking about Contradictions

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 386))

  • 238 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter contextualizes Vasil’ev’s work considering the state of logic in both Russia and Western Europe between the end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth century, and, above all, the ways in which Vasil’ev absorbed and re-worked input and suggestions flowing from external sources. This survey starts with the individual, Vasil’ev himself, and then moves outwards to isolate and identify the broader contexts within which his ideas developed. Among the main Russian logicians who were important for Vasil’ev there are Matvei Mikhailovich Troitsky, Mikhail I. Vladislavlev, Mikhail Ivanovich Karinsky, as well as the neo-Kantians Aleksandr Ivanovich Vvedensky and Ivan Ivanovich Lapshin. As to the Western scholars, even though Vasil’ev wrote during the years of the foundational crisis of mathematics, he placed great importance on Aristotelian logic and hence on traditional logicians like William Hamilton, John S. Mill, Rudolf Hermann Lotze, Christoph Sigwart, Benno Erdmann, and Wilhelm Wundt. At the same time, attention is focused on the work of some contemporaries like Isaac Husik, Jan Łukasiewicz, Alexius Meinong and Charles S. Peirce, whose work was relevant for the elaboration of non-classical logical ideas around the turn of the century. In particular, the reading of Peirce played an important role in Vasil’ev’s elaboration of the idea of a non-Aristotelian logic. Just as important was his acquaintance with Darwin’s evolutionary theories through the mediation of Sigwart.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a historical reconstruction of the fortunes of logic in Russia from the late medieval period to the nineteenth century see Anellis (1992).

  2. 2.

    On the history of philosophy in the universities see Bazhanov (1995). Stelzner & Kreiser (2004: 236–241) provide a highly synthetic picture. On the history of logic in Russia in the nineteenth century until the beginning of the twentieth century see also Bazhanov (2012; 2013: 65–67), Schumann (2014).

  3. 3.

    Cf. Cavaliere (1992–1993: 7 ff.). The Russian translations of the mentioned works are listed in the bibliography.

  4. 4.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1910: 10 fn. 1, 34, 41 = 1989: 18–19 fn. 8, 42, 48).

  5. 5.

    Cf. Vladislavlev (1872: 54–55).

  6. 6.

    Cf. Stelzner (2001: 250–251), Stelzner & Kreiser (2004: 256–257). For more details on the problematic of contradiction in Vladislavlev see Stelzner (2001: 243–249), Stelzner & Kreiser (2004: 387–393) again.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Biryukov (2001: 220–223).

  8. 8.

    Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 80 = 1989: 122 [1993: 351]).

  9. 9.

    In Russia, in 1901–1902, Samuil Osipovich Shatunovsky had maintained that the principle of excluded middle was not valid for infinite sets, and later, Pavel A. Florensky , in The Pillar and Ground of the Truth (1914 [1997]), spoke of degrees of belief, or faith, that go from +∞ to –∞ (cf. Bazhanov 2001: 207; 2011: 95). There is no lack of scholars who see already in Florensky a supporter of paraconsistency; cf. Guseinov & Lektorsky (2008: 13), Rhodes (2013: 20, 24 ff.). On the relationships between Vasil’ev’s imaginary logic and Florensky’s philosophy, see Biryukov & Pryadko (2010).

  10. 10.

    According to Hamilton (1861–18662: iii, 100), “all that we can positively think, that is, all that is within the jurisdiction of the law of Reason and Consequent, lies between two opposite poles of thought, which, as exclusive of each other, cannot, on the principles of Identity and Contradiction, both be true, but of which, on the principle of Excluded Middle, the one or the other must.” All this applies to anything, even to the inconceivable, hence both to the phenomenal and to the noumenal. On Hamilton’s concept of the laws of thought see Raspa (1999b: 84–89).

  11. 11.

    Cf. Biryukov (2001: 225–227), Stelzner & Kreiser (2004: 241–248).

  12. 12.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1910: 12, 14 fn. 1, 40 fn. 1 = 1989: 20, 22 fn. 10, 47–48 fn. 22; 1912: 218–219 fn. 2, 222 = 1989: 65 fn. 6, 68–69 [2003: 137 fn. 6, 140–141]; 1912–1913a: 80 = 1989: 122 [1993: 351]).

  13. 13.

    Vasil’ev (1912: 222 = 1989: 69 [2003: 141]).

  14. 14.

    Vasil’ev (1912: 218, fn. 2 = 1989: 65, fn. 6 [2003: 137, fn. 6]).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 72, fn. 1 = 1989: 114, fn. 10 [1993: 344]). In the translation, the note has been put in the text.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Biryukov (2001: 227–228).

  17. 17.

    On Kantianism in Russia see also Evtuhov (1995), who speaks about Vvedensky ’s reading of Kant and Kantianism at Kazan University. On Vvedensky ’s logical ideas and biography see Biryukov & Biryukova (2011; 2012).

  18. 18.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1911/1989: 126; 1912: 244 = 1989: 92 [2003: 161]; 1912–1913a: 80 = 1989: 122 [1993: 350]; 1925: 107).

  19. 19.

    By ‘classical logic’ we understand, in accordance with contemporary usage, not traditional logic, which arose with Aristotle and the stoic-megarian reflection, to continue through the Medieval age down to modern times, but logical systems (classical propositional calculus and the logic of predicates of the first and second order) that are opposed to intuitionistic, many-valued, paraconsistent logics etc., i.e. ‘non-classical logics.’ Nonetheless, as should emerge from the following pages, not all non-classical logics arise in reaction to classical logic, since non-classical elements were already present in traditional logic.

  20. 20.

    Cf. Priest (2000: 144).

  21. 21.

    Cf. for example Hamilton (1861–18662: iii, 79, 100) and Heymans (1905 2: 62 ff.); see also Sect. 2.1 fn. 10, and Sect. 5.1. With regard to twentieth century exponents of traditional formal logic, cf. Freytag-Löringhoff (1955: 13–14, 20) and Luce (1958: 124).

  22. 22.

    Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 59 = 1989: 101 [1993: 334]).

  23. 23.

    Cf. Vasil’ev (1912: 208, 223 = 1989: 55, 69 [2003: 128, 141]; 1925: 108).

  24. 24.

    Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 59 = 1989: 101–102 [1993: 334]).

  25. 25.

    Cf. Bazhanov (1990a: 334; 1998: 17).

  26. 26.

    Cf. Bazhanov (1992a: 46; 1998: 18–19; 2001: 209 ff.).

  27. 27.

    Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 79 = 1989: 122 [1993: 350]).

  28. 28.

    Sigwart (19043: ii, § 94, pp. 462–463 [1895: ii, 328–329]).

  29. 29.

    Vasil’ev (1912–1913a: 74 = 1989: 116 [1993: 346]). Cf. also Vasil’ev (1909c), with reference to which see Bazhanov (1990c).

  30. 30.

    Cf. Bazhanov (1992a: 46–47).

  31. 31.

    Peirce quoted in Carus (1910a: 45).

  32. 32.

    Cf. Peirce quoted in Carus (1910b: 158): “It does not seem to me to have been a lunatic study. On the contrary, perhaps if I had pursued it further, it might have drawn my attention to features of logic that had been overlooked. However, I came to the conclusion that it was not worth my while to pursue that line of thought further. In order to show what sort of false hypotheses they were that I traced out to their consequences, I will mention that one of them was that instead of the form of necessary inference being, as it is, that from A being in a certain relation to B, and B in the same relation to C, it necessarily follows that A is in the same relation to C, I supposed, in one case, that the nature of Reason were such that the fundamental form of inference was, A is in a certain relation to B and B in the same relation to C, whence it necessarily follows that C is in the same relation to A; and I followed out various other similar modifications of logic.”

  33. 33.

    Cf. Bazhanov (1992a: 48; 2001: 207); on Vasil’ev’s reading of Carus ’s essay see also Bazhanov (1988a: 68–70; 2009a: 108–111).

  34. 34.

    Cf. Carus (1910a: 37): “Every contradiction is a problem and every solution of a problem becomes a renewed justification of our belief in the consistency of existence. [...] If there were no consistency there would be no science, reason would be a mere coincidence of haphazard regularities, and a trust in the efficiency of reason should be branded as a vagary of deluded dreamers. The very existence of reason is an evidence that the universe is consistent throughout, and human reason is an instinctive comprehension of this most remarkable feature of existence, while science is simply the methodical application of reason.”

  35. 35.

    Kant (17811–17872: A 651 = B 679 [1998: 595]).

  36. 36.

    Cf. Peirce (1892: CP 6.39; W 8, 113).

  37. 37.

    Carus (1910a: 39).

  38. 38.

    Carus (1910a: 44).

  39. 39.

    Carus (1910a: 46).

  40. 40.

    Cf. Bazhanov (1992a: 50).

Bibliography

  • Anellis, Irving H. 1992. Theology against Logic: The Origins of Logic in Old Russia. History and Philosophy of Logic 13(1): 1542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1988a. Nikolai Aleksandrovich Vasil’ev. 1880–1940. Moskva: Nauka [= Бaжaнoв, Baлeнтин Aлeкcaндpoвич, Hикoлaй Aлeкcaндpoвич Bacильeв. 1880–1940. Mocквa: Hayкa, 1988].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1990a. The Fate of one Forgotten Idea: N. A. Vasil’ev and his Imaginary Logic. Studies in Soviet Thought 39(3–4): 333–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1990c. Ob evristicheskoi roli idei Darvina v postroenii voobrazhaemoi logiki N. A. Vasil’evym [On the Heuristic Role of Darwin’s Ideas in the Construction of the Imaginary Logic of N. A. Vasil’ev]. In x Vsesoiuznaia konferentsiia po logike, metodologii i filosofii nauki [x All-Union Conference on Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science], 6–7. Minsk: B. i. [= Бaжaнoв, Baлeнтин Aлeкcaндpoвич, Oб эвpиc1ecкoй poли идeй Дapвинa в пocтpoeнии вooбpaжaeмoй лoгики H. A. Bacильeвым // x Bcecoюзнaя кoнфepeнция пo лoгикe, мeтoдoлoгии и филocoфии нayки. Mинcк: Б. и., 1990, c. 6–7].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1992a. C. S. Peirce’s Influence on the Logical Work of N. A. Vasil’ev. Modern Logic 3(1): 45–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1995. Prervannyi polyot. Istoriia “Universitetskoi” filosofii i logiki v Rossii [The Interrupted Flight. The History of “University” Philosophy and Logic in Russia]. Moskva: Izdatel’stvo Moskovskogo Universiteta [= Бaжaнoв, Baлeнтин Aлeкcaндpoвич, Пpepвaнный пoлёт. Иcтopия “yнивepcитeтcкoй” филocoфии и лoгики в Poccии. Mocквa: Издaтeльcтвo Mocкoвcкoгo yнивepcитeтa, 1995].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 1998. Toward the Reconstruction of the Early History of Paraconsistent Logic: The Prerequisites of N. A. Vasil’ev’s Imaginary Logic. Logique et Analyse 41(161–162–163): 17–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 2001. The Origins and Emergence of Non-Classical Logic in Russia. Nineteenth Century until the Turn of the Twentieth Century. In Zwischen traditioneller und moderner Logik. Nichtklassische Ansätze. Hrsg. von Werner Stelzner und Manfred Stöckler, 205–217. Paderborn: mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 2009a. N. A. Vasil’ev i ego voobrazhaemaia logika. Voskreshenie odnoi zabytoi idei [N. A. Vasil’ev and his Imaginary Logic. The Rebirth of a Forgotten Idea]. Moskva: Kanon+ [= Бaжaнoв, Baлeнтин Aлeкcaндpoвич, H. A. Bacильeв и eгo вooбpaжaeмaя лoгикa. Bocкpeшeниe oднoй зaбытoй идeи. Mocквa: Кaнoн+, 2009].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 2011. The Dawn of Paraconsistency: Russia’s Logical Thought in the Turn of xx Century. Manuscrito – Revista Internacional de Filosofia 34(1): 89–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 2012. Logika v Rossii i pravoslavnaia tserkov’ [Logic in Russia and the Orthodox Church]. Logical Investigation 18: 5–25 [= Бaжaнoв, Baлeнтин Aлeкcaндpoвич, Лoгикa в Poccии и пpaвocлaвнaя цepкoвь].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bazhanov, Valentin Aleksandrovich. 2013. The Logical Community in the USSR and Modern Russia: The Furrow Syndrome. In Logic in Central and Eastern Europe. History, Science, and Discourse. Ed. by Andrew Schumann, 65–72. Lanham – Boulder – New York – Toronto – Plymoouth, UK: University Press of America.

  • Biryukov, Boris V. 2001. Die Antizipation nichtklassischer Ideen durch russische Logiker Ende des 19. und Anfang des 20. Jahrhunderts. In Zwischen traditioneller und moderner Logik. Nichtklassische Ansätze. Hrsg. von Werner Stelzner und Manfred Stöckler, 219–238. Paderborn: mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biryukov, Boris V. & Igor’ Petrovich Pryadko. 2010. Problema logicheskogo protivorechiia i russkaia religioznaia filosofiia [The Problem of Logical Contradiction and Russian Religious Philosophy]. Logical Investigations 16: 23–84 [= Биpюкoв, Бopиc B. / Пpядкo, Игopь Пeтpoвич, Пpoблeмa лoгичecкoгo пpoтивopeчия и pyccкaя peлигиoзнaя филocoфия // Лoгичecкиe иccлeдoвaния. 2010. Bып. 16, c. 23–84].

    Google Scholar 

  • Biryukov, Boris Vladimirovich & Ljubov’ Gavrilovna Biryukova. 2011. Aleksandr Ivanovich Vvedensky kak logik. Chast’ i [Aleksander Ivanovich Vvedensky as Logician. Part i]. Logical Investigations 17: 34–68 [= Биpюкoв, Бopиc Bлaдимиpoвич B. / Биpюкoвa, Любoвь Гaвpилoвнa, Aлeкcaндp Ивaнoвич Bвeдeнcкий кaк лoгик. Чacть i // Лoгичecкиe иccлeдoвaния, 2011, Bып. 17, c. 34–68].

    Google Scholar 

  • Biryukov, Boris Vladimirovich & Ljubov’ Gavrilovna Biryukova. 2012. Aleksandr Ivanovich Vvedensky kak logik. Chast’ ii [Aleksander Ivanovich Vvedensky as Logician. Part ii]. Logical Investigations 18: 34–59 [= Биpюкoв, Бopиc Bлaдимиpoвич B. / Биpюкoвa, Любoвь Гaвpилoвнa, Aлeкcaндp Ивaнoвич Bвeдeнcкий кaк лoгик. Чacть ii].

    Google Scholar 

  • Carus, Paul. 1910a. The Nature of Logical and Mathematical Thought. The Monist 20(1): 35–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carus, Paul. 1910b. Non-Aristotelian Logic. The Monist, 20(1): 158–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavaliere, Fania. 1992–1993. Alle origini delle logiche non-classiche. L’opera logica e filosofica di N. A. Vasil’ev. PhD thesis, Università degli Studi di Milano.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evtuhov, Catherine. 1995. An Unexpected Source of Russian Neo-Kantianism: Alexander Vvedensky and Lobachevsky’s Geometry Studies. Studies in East European Thought 47(3): 245–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freytag-Löringhoff, Bruno von. 1955. Logik. Ihr System und ihr Verhältnis zur Logistik. Stuttgart – Berlin – Köln – Mainz: Kohlhammer (19664).

    Google Scholar 

  • Florensky, Pavel A. 1914. Stolp i utverzhdenie istiny. (Opyt pravoslavnoi teoditsii v dvenadtsati pis’makh) [The Pillar and Ground of the Truth. (An Essay in Orthodox Theodicy in Twelve Letters)]. Moskva: «Put’» [= Флоренский, Пaвел Александрович, Столп и утверждение истины. (Опыт православной теодиции в двенадцати письмах). Москва: «Путь», 1914]. Engl. transl.: Florensky 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florensky, Pavel A. 1997. The Pillar and Ground of the Truth. Translated and annotated by Boris Jakim; with an introduction by Richard F. Gustafson. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guseinov, Abdusalam A. & Vladislav A. Lektorsky. 2008. La philosophie en Russie. Histoire et état actuel. Diogène 222(2): 5–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, William. 1861–18662. Lectures on Logic. Vols. iiiiv. In Hamilton, W., Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic. 4 vols. Ed. by Henry Longueville Mansel and John Veitch. Edinburgh and London: W. Blackwood and Sons (1859–18601). Repr. Stuttgart – Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1969–1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heymans, Gerardus. 19052. Die Gesetze und Elemente des wissenschaftlichen Denkens. Ein Lehrbuch der Erkenntnistheorie in Grundzüge. Zweite verbesserte Auflage. Leipzig: J. A. Barth (2 Bde., Leiden – Leipzig: S. C. Van Doesburg – O. Harrassowitz, 1890–18941).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 17811–17872. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Riga: J. F. Hartknoch, 17811; in Kants gesammelte Schriften. Bd. iv, 1–252. 17872; in Kants gesammelte Schriften. Bd. iii. Engl. transl.: Kant 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce, Arthur A. 1958. Logic. London: English University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1892. The Doctrine of Necessity Examined. The Monist 2: 321–337. In Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 6.35–65; and in Writings of Charles S. Peirce. Vol. 8, pp. 111–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham. 2000. Vasil’év and Imaginary Logic. History and Philosophy of Logic 21(2): 135–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes, Michael Craig. 2013. On Contradiction in Orthodox Philosophy. Studia Humana 2(3): 19–30. Repr. in Logic in Orthodox Christian Thinking. Ed. by Andrew Schumann, 82–103. Frankfurt M. [i.e.] Heusenstamm – Paris – Lancaster – New Brunswick, NJ: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, Venanzio. 1999b. In-contraddizione. Il principio di contraddizione alle origini della nuova logica. Trieste: Edizioni Parnaso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumann, Andrew. 2014. On the History of Logic in the Russian Empire (1850–1917). Technical Transactions, Fundamental Science, 1-Np: 185–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelzner, Werner. 2001. Zur Behandlung von Widerspruch und Relevanz in der russischen traditionellen Logik und bei C. Sigwart. In Zwischen traditioneller und moderner Logik. Nichtklassische Ansätze. Hrsg. von Werner Stelzner und Manfred Stöckler, 239–296. Paderborn: mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelzner, Werner & Lothar Kreiser. 2004. Traditionelle und nichtklassische Logik. Paderborn: mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigwart, Christoph. 19043. Logik. 2 Bde., dritte durchgesehene Auflage. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Tübingen: Lauppsche Buchhandlung, 1873–18781; Freiburg i. B.: Mohr, 1889–18932). Engl. transl.: Sigwart 1895. Russian transl.: Sigwart 1908–1909.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigwart, Christoph. 1895. Logic. 2 vols. Second edition, revised and enlarged. Translated by Helen Dendy. London – New York: Swan Sonnenschein & Co. – MacMillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1909c. Znachenie Darvina v filosofii [The Meaning of Darwin in Philosophy]. Kamsko-Volzhskaia Rech’. Kazan (30 January 1909), Feuilleton [= Значение Дарвина в философии // Камско-Волжская Речь. Казань 1909, 30 январия (Фельетонь)]. Repr. in Bazhanov, V. A., N. A. Vasil’ev i ego voobrazhaemaia logika. Voskreshenie odnoi zabytoi idei [N. A. Vasil’ev and his Imaginary Logic. The Rebirth of a Forgotten Idea], 216–223. Moskva: Kanon+, 2009 [= Бажанов, В. А., Н. А. Васильев и его воображаемая логика. Воскрешение одной забытой идеи. Москва: Канон+, 2009, c. 216–223].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1910. O chastnykh suzhdeniiakh, o treugol’nike protivopolozhnostei, o zakone iskliuchennogo chetvertogo [On Particular Judgments, the Triangle of Oppositions, and the Law of Excluded Fourth]. Uchenye zapiski Imperatorskogo Kazanskogo Universiteta [Scientific Memoirs of the Imperial University of Kazan], year lxxvii, book 10 (October 1910). Kazan: Tipolitografia of the Imperial University, pp. 1–47 [= О частных суждениях, о треугольнике противоположностей, о законе исключенного четвертoго // Ученыe записки Императорскoго Казанскoго Университета, Год lxxvii, десятая книга, 1910, октябрь. Казань: Типолитография Императорсoго Университета, c. 1–47]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 12–53. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 12–53].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1911/1989. Voobrazhaemaia logika (Konspekt lektsii) [Imaginary Logic (Conspectus of a Lecture)]. Kazan: Obshchestvo Narodnykh Universitetov, 6 pp. [= Воображаемая логика (Конспект лекции). Казань: Общество Народных Университетов, 1911, с. 6]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 126–130. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 126–130].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1912. Voobrazhaemaia (nearistoteleva) logika [Imaginary (non-Aristotelian) Logic]. Zhurnal Ministerstva Narodnogo Prosveshcheniia [The Journal of the Ministry of Education]. New series, xl (August 1912). Sankt-Peterburg: Senatokaia tipografiia, pp. 207–246 [= Воображаемая (неаристотелева) логика // Журнал Министерства Народного Просвещения. Новая серия, Ч. xl. 1912, август. Санкт-Петербург: Сенатокая типография, c. 207–246]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 53–94. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 53–94].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1912–1913a. Logika i metalogika [Logic and Metalogic]. Logos. Mezhdunarodnyi ezhegodnik po filosofii kul’tury. Russkoe izdanie [Logos. Internatonal Yearbook of Philosophy of Culture. Russian edition] 1–2: 53–81 [= Логика и металогика // Логос. Международный ежегодник по философии культуры. Русское издание. 1912–1913. Кн. 1–2, c. 53–81]. Repr. in Vasilev, N. A., Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov, 94–123. Moskva: Nauka, 1989 [= Васильев, Н. А., Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989, c. 94–123].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1989. Voobrazhaemaia logika. Izbrannye trudy [Imaginary Logic. Selected Works]. Ed. by V. A. Smirnov. Moskva: Nauka [= Воображаемая логика. Избранные труды. Под редакцией В. А. Смирнова. Москва: Наука, 1989].

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 1993. Logic and Metalogic. Translated by Vladimir L. Vasyukov. Axiomathes 4(3): 329–351. Engl. transl. of “Logika i metalogika”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasilev, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. 2003. Imaginary (non-Aristotelian) Logic. Translated by Roger Vergauwen and Evgeny A. Zaytsev. Logique et Analyse 46(182): 127–163. Engl. transl. of “Voobrazhaemaia (nearistoteleva) logika”.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vladislavlev, Mikhail Ivanovich. 1872. Logika: Obozrenie induktivnykh i deduktivnykh priemov myshleniia i istoricheskie ocherki: logiki Aristotelia, skholasticheskoi dialektiki, logiki formal’noi i induktivnoi [Logic. A Review of Inductive and Deductive Methods of Thought, together with Historical Studies on Aristotle’s Logic, Scholastic Dialectic, and Formal and Inductive Logic]. Sankt-Peterburg: tip. V. Demakova (18812) [= Bлaдиcлaвлeв, Mиxaил Ивaнoвич, Лoгикa: Oбoзpeниe индyктивныx и дeдyктивныx пpиeмoв мышлeния и иcтopичecкиe oчepки: лoгики Apиcтoтeля, cxoлacтичecкoй диaлeктики, лoгики фopмaльнoй и индyктивнoй. Caнкт-Пeтepбypг: тип. B. Дeмaкoвa, 1872, 18812].

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Raspa, V. (2017). The Historical and Cultural Context. In: Thinking about Contradictions. Synthese Library, vol 386. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66086-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics